The Structure of Orders in the Pushdown Hierarchy Laurent Braud

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Structure of Orders in the Pushdown Hierarchy Laurent Braud The structure of orders in the pushdown hierarchy Laurent Braud To cite this version: Laurent Braud. The structure of orders in the pushdown hierarchy. Modeling and Simulation. Uni- versité Paris-Est, 2010. English. NNT : 2010PEST1009. tel-00587409 HAL Id: tel-00587409 https://pastel.archives-ouvertes.fr/tel-00587409 Submitted on 20 Apr 2011 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. THESE` pour obtenir le grade de DOCTEUR DE L’UNIVERSITE´ PARIS-EST The structure of orders in the pushdown hierarchy Les structures d’ordre dans la hi´erarchie `apile Sp´ecialit´e informatique Ecole´ doctorale MSTIC Soutenue publiquement par Laurent Braud le 10 d´ecembre 2010 JURY : Zolt´an Esik´ , rapporteur, Wolfgang Thomas, rapporteur, Arnaud Carayol, examinateur, Damian Niwinski´ , examinateur, Dominique Perrin, examinateur, Didier Caucal, directeur de th`ese. 2 Contents 1 Introduction 7 1.1 (enfran¸cais)................................... 7 1.2 (inEnglish) ................................... 13 2 Preliminaries 19 2.1 Notationsandfirststructures . .. 19 2.1.1 Finitewords............................... 19 2.1.2 Structures ................................ 20 2.1.3 Graphs.................................. 21 2.1.4 Deterministictrees ........................... 22 2.2 Linearorderings................................. 22 2.2.1 Ordinals................................. 24 2.2.2 ScatteredorderingsandHausdorffrank . .. 26 2.2.3 Ordersinadeterministictree . 29 2.3 Logic....................................... 30 2.3.1 First-orderlogic............................. 30 2.3.2 Monadicsecond-orderlogic. 31 2.3.3 Decidability ............................... 31 2.4 Graphtransformations . 33 2.4.1 Graphinterpretations. 33 2.4.2 Graphexpansions............................ 35 2.5 Thepushdownhierarchy . 37 2.5.1 Definition ................................ 37 2.5.2 Someproperties............................. 38 3 Linear order construction 43 3.1 Ordinalsinthepushdownhierarchy . .... 43 3.2 Powers of ζ ................................... 45 3.3 n-regularpresentation ............................. 48 3.3.1 Prefix-recognizablegraphs . 49 3.3.2 Configuration graphs of n-hopdas ................... 49 3.3.3 Encodingordinals............................ 50 3 4 CONTENTS 3.4 Coveringgraphs................................. 53 3.4.1 Fundamentalsequence . 54 3.4.2 Coveringgraphs............................. 56 3.4.3 Otherpropertiesofcoveringgraphs . ... 60 3.4.4 Strictness of covering graphs in the hierarchy . ....... 62 3.4.5 The case of Gε0 ............................. 65 4 The structure of tree frontiers 67 4.1 Tree-walkingautomaton . 67 4.2 Fromgraphstofrontiers . 69 4.3 Ordinals..................................... 73 4.4 Scatteredlinearorders . .. 78 4.4.1 Treeswithscatteredfrontiers . .. 78 4.4.2 Permutationofsubtrees . 79 4.4.3 Cantor-Bendixson rank of deterministic trees . ....... 81 4.4.4 Hausdorff rank of scattered orders in Graphn ............. 86 4.5 Finitecombs................................... 87 5 Schemes and morphic words 91 5.1 Recursionschemes ............................... 92 5.1.1 Definition ................................ 92 5.1.2 Schemesinthepushdownhierarchy . 94 5.2 Morphicwords ................................. 97 5.2.1 Definitionandproperties. 97 5.2.2 Constructioninthepushdownhierarchy . ... 99 5.2.3 Words in Graph2 aremorphic,directproof . 99 5.2.4 Words in Graph2 are morphic, by recursion schemes . 102 5.3 Secondorder ..................................106 5.3.1 Second-ordermorphicwords . 106 5.3.2 Second-order scheme ω-frontiers . .109 5.3.3 Liouvilleword..............................117 List of notations 119 Index 121 Bibliography 123 List of Figures 1.1 Un graphe fini et une propri´et´ede ce graphe. ...... 7 1.2 L’arbrebinairecomplet. .. 8 1.3 Afinitegraphandoneofitsproperties.. ..... 13 1.4 Thecompletebinarytree. 14 2.1 Exampleofagraph:theladder. 21 2.2 The graph representation of the ordinal ω +2................. 24 2.3 Theladderanditsunfolding. .. 36 2.4 Treegraphofthecompletebinarytree. ..... 36 2.5 Thepushdownhierarchy.. 38 2.6 Exemple of graph constructions in the hierarchy. ......... 39 3 3.1 Finite graph G3 which unfolding has frontier ω ................ 44 3.2 Folded graphs of trees of frontier ζ, η and ω(1 + η). ............. 45 3.3 Folded regular graph of a tree of frontier ζω.................. 46 3.4 {0, 1}-treegraph of ω............................... 48 3.5 The operation inc(ωω). ............................. 52 3.6 Covering graph of ωω. ............................. 56 3.7 Exponentiation of the covering graph of ω................... 62 4.1 Order in a finite tree t and “arranged” tree s(t)................ 72 4.2 Non-full tree of frontier ω having a branch with infinitely many 0’s. 74 4.3 A finite graph G, “spanning tree” T , completed tree T¯, and unfolding.. 76 4.4 Ordersinatree.................................. 84 ω 5.1 Rules for S1, of frontier ω . .......................... 95 5.2 General rules for Sn, of frontier ω ↑↑ (n +1). ................ 95 5.3 Paperfoldingsequence. .. 98 5.4 A graph which unfolding yields the morphic word abaab . a2i b... ....100 5.5 Generalshapeofthefoldedgraph. 101 5.6 Rules of a scheme which frontier is a morphic word. .......105 5.7 Order-2 safe scheme which frontier is the Champernowne word. .107 5.8 Order-2 safe scheme which frontier is the Liouville word. ..........118 5 6 LIST OF FIGURES Chapter 1 Introduction 1.1 (en fran¸cais) En logique math´ematique, on distingue les objets math´ematiques, ou structures, et leurs propri´et´es, ou logique. Les structures `aleur tour sont constitu´ees d’´el´ements et de relations entre ces ´el´ements. Dans cette th`ese, nous travaillerons uniquement sur ce que l’on appelle des “graphes color´es dont les arcs sont ´etiquet´es”, c’est-`a-dire des structures dont les relations sont d’arit´eau plus 2. De plus, ces structures seront d´enombrables — on peut num´eroter chaque objet avec un entier — et de pr´esentation finie — il existe une quantit´e finie d’information permettant de repr´esenter la structure de fa¸con non ambig¨ue. “Un chemin entre deux sommets blancs est en pointill´es ou passe par un sommet noir.” Figure 1.1: Un graphe fini et une propri´et´ede ce graphe. La logique la plus simple est celle dite du premier ordre, car elle manipule simplement les ´el´ements proprement dits de la structure consid´er´ee. Elle permet d’exprimer des propri´et´es du type “tout sommet colori´een noir a un voisin blanc” ou “s’il existe un sommet blanc, alors il existe 3 arcs distincts en pointill´es”. Elle est cependant restreinte `ades propri´et´es ponctuelles et ne dit rien sur la structure dans sa globalit´e. Une solution est alors de consid´erer une logique plus forte, qui permet de manipuler directement des ensembles d’´el´ements. C’est la logique du second ordre monadique, qui permet d’exprimer des propri´et´es raisonnablement compliqu´ees. Des exemples classiques sont “il y a un chemin entre x et y” ou “le sous-arbre t est infini”. On la notera souvent par le sigle MSO. De fa¸con g´en´erale, la logique du second ordre d´esigne l’ensemble des formules qui parlent des relations entre les ´el´ements. Mais elle a le d´efaut d’ˆetre paradoxalement trop puissante; elle ´echappe ainsi aux outils usuels de l’informatique, selon la d´efinition donn´ee 7 8 CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION ci-apr`es. C’est pourquoi on se restreint aux relations qui ne prennent qu’une variable : ce sont bien les ensembles. Ceci explique l’adjectif monadique. Notre probl`eme n’est pas de connaˆıtre enti`erement une structure donn´ee, mais de savoir exprimer ses propri´et´es. Cette nuance autorise l’usage d’un automatisme. En effet, la question qui se pose est alors la suivante. Etant´ donn´ees une logique et une structure, existe-t-il un algorithme qui prenne en entr´ee une formule close de cette logique et renvoie oui ou non selon que la structure satisfait la formule ou non? C’est la question de la d´ecidabilit´ede du model-checking de la logique `alaquelle ap- partiennent les formules que l’on veut tester. Savoir construire un tel algorithme est un d´efi majeur de l’informatique d’aujourd’hui, car cette question est naturellement li´ee `ala notion de v´erification de programmes. En effet, savoir si un programme fait effectivement ce que l’on veut — par exemple, savoir s’il termine — est expressible par une formule, que doit v´erifier la structure des configurations du programme. Construction de structures Par exemple, un r´esultat fondemental de Rabin [Rab69] indique que l’arbre binaire com- plet, esquiss´eFigure 1.2, a une th´eorie monadique d´ecidable. Plus g´en´eralement, pour une logique donn´ee, peut-on esp´erer trouver une caract´erisation de toutes les structures qui jouissent de la mˆeme propri´et´e? Probablement pas, mais cela n’empˆeche pas les sci- entifiques de chercher `aen d´ecrire le plus possibles. En particulier, pour la logique du second ordre monadique, l’int´erˆet de la communaut´escientifique se porte sur la hi´erarchie `apile [Cau03], aussi appel´ee hi´erarchie de Caucal. Figure 1.2: L’arbre binaire complet. Pour d´ecrire historiquement cette hi´erarchie, il nous faut remonter `a[MS85], o`ules auteurs s’int´eressent aux graphes des configurations des automates `apiles en partant d’une configuration donn´ee. Il caract´erisent exactement ces graphes par un crit`ere g´eom´etrique : si on fixe un sommet, et que l’on retire successivement ce sommet, puis les sommets `a distance 1, puis `adistance 2 et ainsi de suite, on obtient une suite de graphes. Le r´esultat fondamental est que l’ensemble de ces graphes est fini `aisomorphisme pr`es : la suite se 1.1. (EN FRANC¸AIS) 9 r´ep`ete. Cette propri´et´eleur permet d’´etendre le r´esultat de Rabin `atout une classe de graphes.
Recommended publications
  • Order Types and Structure of Orders
    ORDER TYPES AND STRUCTURE OF ORDERS BY ANDRE GLEYZALp) 1. Introduction. This paper is concerned with operations on order types or order properties a and the construction of order types related to a. The reference throughout is to simply or linearly ordered sets, and we shall speak of a as either property or type. Let a and ß be any two order types. An order A will be said to be of type aß if it is the sum of /3-orders (orders of type ß) over an a-order; i.e., if A permits of decomposition into nonoverlapping seg- ments each of order type ß, the segments themselves forming an order of type a. We have thus associated with every pair of order types a and ß the product order type aß. The definition of product for order types automatically associates with every order type a the order types aa = a2, aa2 = a3, ■ ■ ■ . We may further- more define, for all ordinals X, a Xth power of a, a\ and finally a limit order type a1. This order type has certain interesting properties. It has closure with respect to the product operation, for the sum of ar-orders over an a7-order is an a'-order, i.e., a'al = aI. For this reason we call a1 iterative. In general, we term an order type ß having the property that ßß = ß iterative, a1 has the following postulational identification: 1. a7 is a supertype of a; that is to say, all a-orders are a7-orders. 2. a1 is iterative.
    [Show full text]
  • Multiplication in Vector Lattices
    MULTIPLICATION IN VECTOR LATTICES NORMAN M. RICE 1. Introduction. B. Z. Vulih has shown (13) how an essentially unique intrinsic multiplication can be defined in a Dedekind complete vector lattice L having a weak order unit. Since this work is available only in Russian, a brief outline is given in § 2 (cf. also the review by E. Hewitt (4), and for details, consult (13) or (11)). In general, not every pair of elements in L will have a product in L. In § 3 we discuss certain properties which ensure that, in fact, the multiplication will be universally defined, and it turns out that L can always be embedded as an order-dense order ideal in a larger space L# which has these properties. It is then possible to define multiplication in spaces without a unit. In § 4 we show that if L has a normal integral 0, then 4> can be extended to a normal integral on a larger space Li(<t>) in L#, and £i(0) may be regarded as an abstract integral space. In § 5 a very general form of the Radon-Niko- dym theorem is proved, and in § 6 this is used to give a relatively simple proof of a theorem of Segal giving a necessary and sufficient condition for the Radon-Nikodym theorem to hold in a measure space. 2. Multiplication in spaces with a unit. Let L be a vector lattice which is Dedekind complete (i.e., every set which is bounded above has a least upper bound) and has a weak order unit 1 (i.e., inf (1, x) > 0, whenever x > 0).
    [Show full text]
  • When Is a Lots Densely Orderable?
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector Topology and its Applications 30 (1988) 225-235 225 North-Holland WHEN IS A LOTS DENSELY ORDERABLE? Victor NEUMANN-LARA Institute de Matetmiticas, Uniuersidad National Autdnoma de M&ico, Ciudad Universitaria, Mhico 20, D.F. Richard C. WILSON Departamento de Matemdticas, Universidad Autdnoma Metropolitana, Unidad Iztapalapa, M&ico 13, D.F. Received 15 May 1986 Revised 19 October 1987 We obtain sufficient conditions for a linearly ordered topological space (LOTS) to be densely orderable. As a consequence we obtain a characterization of those metrizable LOTS with connected ordered compactifications. AMS (MOS) Subj. Class.: Primary 54F05 1. Introduction A well-known result states that the weight w of a linearly ordered topological space (LOTS) is equal to the sum of the density d and the number of jumps j. Thus if j > d, then w =j and hence j is an order-topological invariant of the space in the sense that any other order which induces the same topology will have the same number of jumps. On the other hand, if j G d (in particular if j = Ko) then this is not necessarily the case-for example, the space of rationals Q with the order topology is homeomophic to Q x (0, l} with the lexicographic order topology. In this paper we will obtain conditions under which a LOTS can be reordered without jumps, that is to say under which there exists a dense order inducing the same topology. 2.
    [Show full text]
  • General-Well-Ordered Sets
    J. Austral. Math. Soc. 19 (Series A), (1975), 7-20. GENERAL-WELL-ORDERED SETS J. L. HICKMAN (Received 10 April 1972) Communicated by J. N. Crossley It is of course well known that within the framework of any reasonable set theory whose axioms include that of choice, we can characterize well-orderings in two different ways: (1) a total order for which every nonempty subset has a minimal element; (2) a total order in which there are no infinite descending chains. Now the theory of well-ordered sets and their ordinals that is expounded in various texts takes as its definition characterization (1) above; in this paper we commence an investigation into the corresponding theory that takes character- ization (2) as its starting point. Naturally if we are to obtain any differences at all, we must exclude the axiom of choice from our set theory. Thus we state right at the outset that we are working in Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory without choice. This is not enough, however, for it may turn out that the axiom of choice is not really necessary for the equivalence of (1) and (2), and if this were so, we would still not obtain any deviation from the "classical" theory. Thus the first section of this paper will be devoted to showing that we can in fact have sets that are well-ordered according to (2) but not according to (1). Naturally we have no hope of reversing this situation, for it is a ZF-theorem that any set well-ordered by (1) is also well-ordered by (2).
    [Show full text]
  • Logic and Rational Languages of Words Indexed by Linear Orderings
    Logic and Rational Languages of Words Indexed by Linear Orderings Nicolas Bedon1, Alexis B`es2, Olivier Carton3, and Chlo´eRispal1 1 Universit´eParis-Est and CNRS Laboratoire d’informatique de l’Institut Gaspard Monge, CNRS UMR 8049 Email: [email protected], [email protected] 2 Universit´eParis-Est, LACL Email: [email protected], 3 Universit´eParis 7 and CNRS LIAFA, CNRS UMR 7089 Email: [email protected] Abstract. We prove that every rational language of words indexed by linear orderings is definable in monadic second-order logic. We also show that the converse is true for the class of languages indexed by countable scattered linear orderings, but false in the general case. As a corollary we prove that the inclusion problem for rational languages of words indexed by countable linear orderings is decidable. 1 Introduction In [4, 6], Bruy`ere and Carton introduce automata and rational expressions for words on linear orderings. These notions unify naturally previously defined no- tions for finite words, left- and right-infinite words, bi-infinite words, and ordinal words. They also prove that a Kleene-like theorem holds when the orderings are restricted to countable scattered linear orderings; recall that a linear ordering is scattered if it does not contain any dense sub-ordering. Since [4], the study of automata on linear orderings was carried on in several papers. The emptiness problem and the inclusion problem for rational languages is addressed in [7, 11]. The papers [5, 2] provide a classification of rational languages with respect to the rational operations needed to describe them.
    [Show full text]
  • Discretely Ordered Groups Peter a Linnell, Akbar Rhemtulla and Dale P
    Algebra & Number Theory Volume 3 2009 No. 7 Discretely ordered groups Peter A Linnell, Akbar Rhemtulla and Dale P. O. Rolfsen mathematical sciences publishers ALGEBRA AND NUMBER THEORY 3:7(2009) Discretely ordered groups Peter A Linnell, Akbar Rhemtulla and Dale P. O. Rolfsen We consider group orders and right-orders which are discrete, meaning there is a least element which is greater than the identity. We note that nonabelian free groups cannot be given discrete orders, although they do have right-orders which are discrete. More generally, we give necessary and sufficient conditions that a given orderable group can be endowed with a discrete order. In particular, every orderable group G embeds in a discretely orderable group. We also consider conditions on right-orderable groups to be discretely right-orderable. Finally, we discuss a number of illustrative examples involving discrete orderability, includ- ing the Artin braid groups and Bergman’s nonlocally-indicable right orderable groups. 1. Introduction Let G be a group and suppose < is a strict total order relation on the set of its elements. Then .G; </ is a right-ordered group if f < g implies that f h < gh for all f; g; h 2 G. If in addition f < g implies that h f < hg, then we say .G; </ is an ordered group. If such an order exists for a given group G, we say that G is right-orderable or orderable, respectively. We call the order < discrete if there is an element a 2 G such that 1 < a, where 1 denotes the identity element of G, and there is no element of G strictly between these.
    [Show full text]
  • Which Countable Ordered Sets Have a Dense Linear Extension?
    Mathematica Slovaca Aleksander Rutkowski Which countable ordered sets have a dense linear extension? Mathematica Slovaca, Vol. 46 (1996), No. 5, 445--455 Persistent URL: http://dml.cz/dmlcz/136684 Terms of use: © Mathematical Institute of the Slovak Academy of Sciences, 1996 Institute of Mathematics of the Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic provides access to digitized documents strictly for personal use. Each copy of any part of this document must contain these Terms of use. This paper has been digitized, optimized for electronic delivery and stamped with digital signature within the project DML-CZ: The Czech Digital Mathematics Library http://project.dml.cz řvlathernatica Slovaca ©1996 .. _. ... /~nn/~\ .• ,- . .,- ..-.- Mathematical Institute Math. Sl0VaC3, 46 (1996), NO. 5, 445-455 Slovák Academy of Sciences Dedicated to the memory of Professor Milan Kolibiar WHICH COUNTABLE ORDERED SETS HAVE A DENSE LINEAR EXTENSION? ALEKSANDER RUTKOWSKI (Communicated by Tibor Katrindk ) ABSTRACT. We try to answer the question: when a partial order can be ex­ tended to an order isomorphic to the ordering of rationals? One necessary and a few sufficient conditions for the existence of such an extension are presented. 1. Introduction This article is located on the crossing of paths leading from the two fundamen­ tal results on ordered sets, namely: Marczewski Theorem and Cantor Theorem. MARCZEWSKI THEOREM. ([13]) Every partial order can be extended to a linear order (with the same underlying set). Moreover, it is the intersection of such extensions. CANTOR THEOREM. ([5]) Every countable linearly and densely ordered set containing neither the least nor the greatest element is order-isomorphic to the set Q of all rationals (with natural order).
    [Show full text]
  • The Embedding Structure for Linearly Ordered Topological Spaces ∗ A
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector Topology and its Applications 159 (2012) 3103–3114 Contents lists available at SciVerse ScienceDirect Topology and its Applications www.elsevier.com/locate/topol The embedding structure for linearly ordered topological spaces ∗ A. Primavesi a,1, K. Thompson b, ,2 a School of Mathematics, University of East Anglia, Norwich, NR4 7TJ, UK b Institut für Diskrete Mathematik und Geometrie, Technische Universität Wien, Wiedner Hauptstraße 8-10/104, A-1040 Wien, Austria article info abstract MSC: In this paper, the class of all linearly ordered topological spaces (LOTS) quasi-ordered by primary 54F05 the embeddability relation is investigated. In ZFC it is proved that for countable LOTS this secondary 06F30, 03E75 quasi-order has both a maximal (universal) element and a finite basis. For the class of ℵ uncountable LOTS of cardinality κ where κ 2 0 , it is proved that this quasi-order has no Keywords: maximal element and that in fact the dominating number for such quasi-orders is maximal, Linearly ordered topological space i.e. 2κ . Certain subclasses of LOTS, such as the separable LOTS, are studied with respect to LOTS Universal structure the top and internal structure of their respective embedding quasi-order. The basis problem Basis for uncountable LOTS is also considered; assuming the Proper Forcing Axiom there is an Well-quasi-order eleven element basis for the class of uncountable LOTS and a six element basis for the class of dense uncountable LOTS in which all points have countable cofinality and coinitiality.
    [Show full text]
  • Ordered Products of Topological Groups Melvin Henriksen Harvey Mudd College
    Claremont Colleges Scholarship @ Claremont All HMC Faculty Publications and Research HMC Faculty Scholarship 9-1-1987 Ordered Products of Topological Groups Melvin Henriksen Harvey Mudd College Ralph Kopperman City College of New York Frank A. Smith Kent State University Recommended Citation Henriksen, M., R. Kopperman, and F. A. Smith. "Ordered products of topological groups." Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society 102.2 (September 1987): 281-295. DOI: 10.1017/S030500410006730X This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the HMC Faculty Scholarship at Scholarship @ Claremont. It has been accepted for inclusion in All HMC Faculty Publications and Research by an authorized administrator of Scholarship @ Claremont. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Math. Proc. Camb. Phil. Soc. (1987), 102, 281 281 Printed in Great Britain Ordered products of topological groups BY M. HENRIKSEN Harvey Mudd College, Claremont, CA 91711, U.S.A. R. KOPPERMAN City College of New York, New York, NY 10031, U.S.A. AND F. A. SMITH Kent State University, Kent, OH 44242, U.S.A. (Received 25 June 1986; revised 5 January 1987) 1. Introduction The topology most often used on a totally ordered group (G, <) is the interval topology. There are usually many ways to totally order GxG (e.g., the lexicographic order) but the interval topology induced by such a total order is rarely used since the product topology has obvious advantages. Let R( +) denote the real line with its usual order and Q( + ) the subgroup of rational numbers. There is an order on Q x Q whose associated interval topology is the product topology, but no such order on IR x IR can be found.
    [Show full text]
  • Automorphism Groups of Totally Ordered Sets: a Retrospective Survey
    Automorphism groups of totally ordered sets: a retrospective survey. V. V. Bludov, M. Droste and A. M. W. Glass July 23, 2009 To Charles on his 75th birthday with our gratitude for his research, help and friendship. Abstract In 1963, W. Charles Holland proved that every lattice-ordered group can be embedded in the lattice-ordered group of all order- preserving permutations of a totally ordered set. In this article we examine the context and proof of this result and survey some of the many consequences of the ideas involved in this important theorem. 1 Genesis In 1957, P. M. Cohn noted that Cayley's (right regular) Representation Theorem applies immediately to right-ordered groups [12]. That is, let G be a group with a total order that is preserved by multiplication on the right. Embed G in the group A(G) := Aut(G; ·) of all order-preserving permutations of the set (G; ·) via the right regular representation; i.e., |||||||||||||{ AMS Classi¯cation: 06F15, 20F60, 20B27, 20F10. Keywords: totally ordered set, permutation group, representation, primitive permutation group, amalgamation, free product with amal- gamated subgroup, right-orderable group, normal subgroups, Bergman property, outer automorphism groups. 1 f(g#) = fg (f; g 2 G). Now A(G) can be right totally ordered as follows: let Á be any well-ordering of the set G and de¯ne a < b i® ®0a < ®0b, where ®0 is the least element of G (under Á) of the support of ba¡1. If we choose Á so that its least element is the identity of G, then the right regular embedding preserves the group operation and the total order: g1 < g2 in G i® g1# < g2# in A(G).
    [Show full text]
  • The 116 Reducts of (Q, <
    The 116 reducts of (Q, <, a)∗ Markus Junker, Martin Ziegler Mathematisches Institut Abteilung fur¨ mathematische Logik Universit¨at Freiburg, Germany July 2006, revised December 2007 Abstract This article aims to classify those reducts of expansions of (Q, <) by unary predicates which eliminate quantifiers, and in particular to show that, up to interdefinability, there are only finitely many for a given language. Equivalently, we wish to classify the closed subgroups of Sym(Q) containing the group of all automorphisms of (Q, <) fixing setwise certain subsets. This goal is achieved for expansions by convex predicates, yielding expansions by constants as a special case, and for the expansion by a dense, co-dense predicate. Partial results are obtained in the general setting of several dense predicates. 1 Introduction In this article, we study expansions of (Q, <) by unary predicates that have quantifier elimi- nation. Our goal is to classify the reducts and to show that, up to interdefinability, there are only finitely many such. Here, a reduct for us is a structure with domain Q in some relational language each of whose basic relations are ∅-definable in the original structure. We will consider two interdefinable reducts as the same structure. E.g. Q with the circular ordering coming from < is a reduct of (Q, <), and considered to be the same reduct as Q with the reverse circular ordering. All structures under consideration here are ℵ0-categorical, and so we can identify a structure with its automorphism group, viewed as a permutation group on Q. A reduct then corresponds to a closed subgroup of the full symmetric group on Q containing the automorphism group of the original structure.
    [Show full text]
  • EDL Exercises
    EDL Exercises James Read∗ These are my problem sheets for the Prelims paper, Elements of Deductive Logic (EDL). Most are not original to me, but are based upon the sheets of Stephen Blamey, Adam Caulton (about 80% of everything below), Anthony Eagle, and James Studd. Please do contact me at the email address below if you have any questions or queries. ∗[email protected] 1 1 Set theory and induction 1.1 Important concepts These are the concepts introduced in this week’s class and readings. Check that you understand them all. Sets: members and elements; extensionality; the empty set (or null set); • singletons; intersection, union, relative complement; disjointness; subset and superset, proper subset and proper superset; power set; Russell’s paradox. Sequences: the set-theoretic definition of an ordered pair; the criterion of • identity for ordered pairs; sequences (or n-tuples); the Cartesian product. Relations: relations over a set; binary relations; domain and range; reflex- • ive, irreflexive and non-reflexive; symmetric, asymmetric, anti-symmetric and non-symmetric; transitive, intransitive and non-transitive; the tran- sitive closure (or ancestral) of a relation; equivalence relations and parti- tions; the identity relation; predicates determining a relation. Functions: argument and value; domain and range; total vs. partial func- • tions on a set; criterion of identity for functions; one-to-one (or injective); into; onto (or surjective); one-to-one correspondences (or bijections); the inverse of a function; n-place functions (including n = 0); truth func- tions; enumeration; equinumerosity and cardinality; Cantor’s theorem; countability, denumerability and uncountability. Induction and recursion: inductive definition of a set (base case, generat- • ing relation and closure condition); recursive definition of a function (base case and recurrence relation); proof by induction (base cases and induc- tive steps); the Weak Principle of Induction (or ordinary induction), the Strong Principle of Induction (or complete induction), the Least Number Principle.
    [Show full text]