Stable Facts, Relative Facts

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Stable Facts, Relative Facts Stable Facts, Relative Facts Andrea Di Biagio1, ∗ and Carlo Rovelli2, 3, 4, y 1Dipartimento di Fisica, Universit`aLa Sapienza, I-00185 Roma, EU 2AMU Universit´e,Universit´ede Toulon, CNRS, CPT, F-13288 Marseille, EU 3Perimeter Institute, 31 Caroline Street N, Waterloo ON, N2L2Y5, Canada 4The Rotman Institute of Philosophy, 1151 Richmond St. N London N6A5B7, Canada (Dated: June 28, 2020) We define and characterise two kinds of facts that play a role in quantum theory: stable and relative. We describe how stable facts emerge in a world of relative facts and then discuss the respective roles they play in connecting the theory and the world. The distinction between relative and stable facts resolves the difficulties pointed out by the no-go theorems of Frauchiger and Renner, Brukner, and Bong et. al.. Basing the ontology of the theory on relative facts clarifies the role of decoherence in bringing about the classical world and solves the apparent incompatibility between the `linear evolution' and `projection' postulates. I. FACTS IN QUANTUM THEORY or cannot be extended to systems with an infinite num- ber of degrees of freedom [3], or else. But the universal The common textbook presentation of quantum theory success of the theory and all current empirical evidence assumes the existence of a classical world. A measure- strongly suggest that real physical objects are `classical', ment involves an interaction between the classical world meaning they do not display quantum properties, only and a quantum system. The measurement produces a approximatively. There are no exactly classical objects, definite result, for instance a dot on a screen. The result strictly speaking, as everything we interact with is made is a fact by itself, but also establishes a fact about a quan- of atoms and photons, which obey quantum theory. tum system. For instance, a certain measurement result- In formulating the fundamental theory of nature, the ing in a definite record establishes that at some time the use of effective concepts valid only within an approxi- ~ mation is unconvincing. Therefore the attempts to in- z-component of the spin of an electron is Lz = 2 . This is a fact. terpret quantum theory as a universal theory, such as Quantum probabilities are probabilities for facts, given Many Worlds, Hidden Variables, and others do not rely other facts. The facts are therefore entries of which the on postulating classical objects. A possibility to interpret probability amplitudes are function. In particular, facts quantum theory as a universal theory neither postulating are used as conditionals for computing probabilities of classical objects, nor postulating unobservable worlds, other facts. For instance, if the spin of the electron men- unobservable variables, or unobserved physics, is Rela- tioned above is then immediately measured in a direction tional Quantum Mechanics (RQM) [4,5]. RQM bases at an angle θ from the z-axis, the probability to find the the interpretation of the theory on a larger ensemble of ~ ~ facts, of which stable facts are only a subset. These are value Lθ = 2 (a fact), given the fact that Lz = 2 , is ~ ~ 2 called relative facts. P Lθ = 2 j Lz = 2 = cos (θ=2). Hence, facts are what quantum mechanics is about. Facts ascertained in a conventional measurement are A. Relative facts stable in the following sense. If we know that one of N mutually exclusive facts ai (i = 1 :::N) has happened, the probability P (b) for a fact b to happen is given by Relative facts are defined to happen whenever a phys- ical system interacts with another physical system. Con- X P (b) = P (bjai)P (ai); (1) sider two systems S and F. If an interaction affects F i in a manner that depends on the value of a certain vari- 1 able LS of S, then the value of LS is a fact relative to where P (ai) is the probability that ai has happened and F. This is true by definition irrespectively of whether F P (bjai) is the probability for b given ai. We take equation is a classical system or not. That is, whenever the two (1) as a characterisation of stable facts. systems interact, the value of the variable LS becomes a This textbook presentation of quantum mechanics is fact relative to F. incomplete because it assumes the existence of a classi- The interaction with F is the context in which LS takes cal world. An exactly classical world might exist because a specific value; we call the system F, in this role, a current quantum theory has limited validity|for in- stance is violated by physical collapse mechanisms [1,2], 1 We use `variable' to denote any quantity that in the classical the- ory is a function on phase pace. We prefer to avoid the expression ∗ [email protected] `observable', which is loaded with irrelevant extra baggage: the y [email protected] ideas of observation and a complex observer. 2 `context'.2 The interaction with the context determines B. Decoherence the fact that a certain variable, LS , has a certain value. Stable facts are only a subset of relative facts, as Since stability is a characteristic feature of the classi- there are many relative facts that are not stable facts. cal world (whose facts invariably satisfy (1)), answering Quantum theory provides probabilities that relate rela- the questions above amounts to explaining in terms of tive facts, but these satisfy (1) only if b and the ai are relative facts what it takes for a system to be classical. facts relative to the same system. That is, if we label Various characterisations of a classical or semiclassical facts with the system they refer to, writing a(F) for a fact situation can be found in the literature: large quantum relative to the system F, it is always true that numbers, semiclassical wave packets or coherent states, macroscopic systems, large or infinite number of degrees (F) X (F) (F) (F) P (b ) = P (b jai )P (ai ); (2) of freedom... All these features play a role in charac- i terising classical systems in specific situations. But the while it is in general false that key phenomenon that makes facts stable is decoherence [9{11]: the suppression of quantum interference that hap- (W) X (W) (F) (F) pens when some information becomes inaccessible. P (b ) = P (b jai )P (ai ) (3) i Consider two systems F and E (E for `Environment'), and a variable LF of the system F. Let F ai be the (F) if W 6= F. When (3) holds, we say that the facts ai are eigenvalues of LF . A generic state of the coupled system stable with respect to W. F − E can be written in the form The failure of (3) is easily understood in terms of the X standard language of quantum theory. If F is sufficiently j i = ci jF aii ⊗ j ii ; (5) isolated it may be possible to maintain the quantum co- i herence of the coupled system S−F formed by S and F where j ii are normalised states of E. Define together. The interaction entangles the two systems and 2 interference effects between different values of the vari- = max j h ij ji j : (6) i;j able LS can later be detected in the measurements by an observer W. The probabilities for facts of the S −F Now, suppose that: (a) is vanishing or very small and system relative to W, indeed, can be computed from an (b) a system W does not interact with E. Then the prob- entangled state of the form ability P (b) of any possible fact relative to W resulting from an interaction between F and W can be computed c1ja1i ⊗ jF a1i + c2ja2i ⊗ jF a2i (4) from the density matrix obtained tracing over E, that is 0 where ai are values of LS and F ai are values of F s X 2 ρ = TrE j ih j = jcij jF aiihF aij + O(): (7) `pointer variable' LF . Probabilities computed from this state feature interference terms, and this violates (3) be- i cause what sums is amplitudes, not probabilities. The (E) 2 By posing P (F ai ) = jcij , we can then write value of LS , therefore, is not a stable fact. Hence facts relative to a system F cannot in general be (W) X (W) (E) (E) P (b ) = P (b jF ai )P (F ai ) + O(): (8) taken as conditionals for computing probabilities of facts i relative to a different system W. Equation (1) holds only Thus, probabilities for facts b relative to W calculated if b and ai are facts relative to the same system, but fails in general if used for facts relative to different systems. in terms of the possible values of LF satisfy (3) up to a The notation S for `system', F for `Friend' and W small deviation. Hence the fact LF = ai relative to E for `Wigner' is meant to to evoke the famous Wigner's is stable with respect to W to the extent to which one friend ideal experiment [8]; there is no assumption, how- ignores effects of order . In the limit ! 0, the variable ever, about the system F being quantum or classical, LF of the system F is exactly stable with respect to W. microscopic or macroscopic. The extensive theoretical work on decoherence [12] has Relative facts play a central role in the Relational In- shown that decoherence is practically unavoidable and terpretation of Quantum Mechanics (RQM) [4,5]. We extremely effective as soon as large numbers of degrees shall discuss this role in detail later on.
Recommended publications
  • Yes, More Decoherence: a Reply to Critics
    Yes, More Decoherence: A Reply to Critics Elise M. Crull∗ Submitted 11 July 2017; revised 24 August 2017 1 Introduction A few years ago I published an article in this journal titled \Less interpretation and more decoherence in quantum gravity and inflationary cosmology" (Crull, 2015) that generated replies from three pairs of authors: Vassallo and Esfeld (2015), Okon and Sudarsky (2016) and Fortin and Lombardi (2017). As a philosopher of physics it is my chief aim to engage physicists and philosophers alike in deeper conversation regarding scientific theories and their implications. In as much as my earlier paper provoked a suite of responses and thereby brought into sharper relief numerous misconceptions regarding decoherence, I welcome the occasion provided by the editors of this journal to continue the discussion. In what follows, I respond to my critics in some detail (wherein the devil is often found). I must be clear at the outset, however, that due to the nature of these criticisms, much of what I say below can be categorized as one or both of the following: (a) a repetition of points made in the original paper, and (b) a reiteration of formal and dynamical aspects of quantum decoherence considered uncontroversial by experts working on theoretical and experimental applications of this process.1 I begin with a few paragraphs describing what my 2015 paper both was, and was not, about. I then briefly address Vassallo's and Esfeld's (hereafter VE) relatively short response to me, dedicating the bulk of my reply to the lengthy critique of Okon and Sudarsky (hereafter OS).
    [Show full text]
  • It Is a Great Pleasure to Write This Letter on Behalf of Dr. Maria
    Rigorous Quantum-Classical Path Integral Formulation of Real-Time Dynamics Nancy Makri Departments of Chemistry and Physics University of Illinois The path integral formulation of time-dependent quantum mechanics provides the ideal framework for rigorous quantum-classical or quantum-semiclassical treatments, as the spatially localized, trajectory-like nature of the quantum paths circumvents the need for mean-field-type assumptions. However, the number of system paths grows exponentially with the number of propagation steps. In addition, each path of the quantum system generally gives rise to a distinct classical solvent trajectory. This exponential proliferation of trajectories with propagation time is the quantum-classical manifestation of nonlocality. A rigorous real-time quantum-classical path integral (QCPI) methodology has been developed, which converges to the stationary phase limit of the full path integral with respect to the degrees of freedom comprising the system’s environment. The starting point is the identification of two components in the effects induced on a quantum system by a polyatomic environment. The first, “classical decoherence mechanism” is associated with phonon absorption and induced emission and is dominant at high temperature. Within the QCPI framework, the memory associated with classical decoherence is removable. A second, nonlocal in time, “quantum decoherence process”, which is associated with spontaneous phonon emission, becomes important at low temperatures and is responsible for detailed balance. The QCPI methodology takes advantage of the memory-free nature of system-independent solvent trajectories to account for all classical decoherence effects on the dynamics of the quantum system in an inexpensive fashion. Inclusion of the residual quantum decoherence is accomplished via phase factors in the path integral expression, which is amenable to large time steps and iterative decompositions.
    [Show full text]
  • Less Decoherence and More Coherence in Quantum Gravity, Inflationary Cosmology and Elsewhere
    Less Decoherence and More Coherence in Quantum Gravity, Inflationary Cosmology and Elsewhere Elias Okon1 and Daniel Sudarsky2 1Instituto de Investigaciones Filosóficas, Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México, Mexico City, Mexico. 2Instituto de Ciencias Nucleares, Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México, Mexico City, Mexico. Abstract: In [1] it is argued that, in order to confront outstanding problems in cosmol- ogy and quantum gravity, interpretational aspects of quantum theory can by bypassed because decoherence is able to resolve them. As a result, [1] concludes that our focus on conceptual and interpretational issues, while dealing with such matters in [2], is avoidable and even pernicious. Here we will defend our position by showing in detail why decoherence does not help in the resolution of foundational questions in quantum mechanics, such as the measurement problem or the emergence of classicality. 1 Introduction Since its inception, more than 90 years ago, quantum theory has been a source of heated debates in relation to interpretational and conceptual matters. The prominent exchanges between Einstein and Bohr are excellent examples in that regard. An avoid- ance of such issues is often justified by the enormous success the theory has enjoyed in applications, ranging from particle physics to condensed matter. However, as people like John S. Bell showed [3], such a pragmatic attitude is not always acceptable. In [2] we argue that the standard interpretation of quantum mechanics is inadequate in cosmological contexts because it crucially depends on the existence of observers external to the studied system (or on an artificial quantum/classical cut). We claim that if the system in question is the whole universe, such observers are nowhere to be found, so we conclude that, in order to legitimately apply quantum mechanics in such contexts, an observer independent interpretation of the theory is required.
    [Show full text]
  • A Numerical Study of Quantum Decoherence 1 Introduction
    Commun. Comput. Phys. Vol. 12, No. 1, pp. 85-108 doi: 10.4208/cicp.011010.010611a July 2012 A Numerical Study of Quantum Decoherence 1 2, Riccardo Adami and Claudia Negulescu ∗ 1 Dipartimento di Matematica e Applicazioni, Universit`adi Milano Bicocca, via R. Cozzi, 53 20125 Milano, Italy. 2 CMI/LATP (UMR 6632), Universit´ede Provence, 39, rue Joliot Curie, 13453 Marseille Cedex 13, France. Received 1 October 2010; Accepted (in revised version) 1 June 2011 Communicated by Kazuo Aoki Available online 19 January 2012 Abstract. The present paper provides a numerical investigation of the decoherence ef- fect induced on a quantum heavy particle by the scattering with a light one. The time dependent two-particle Schr¨odinger equation is solved by means of a time-splitting method. The damping undergone by the non-diagonal terms of the heavy particle density matrix is estimated numerically, as well as the error in the Joos-Zeh approxi- mation formula. AMS subject classifications: 35Q40, 35Q41, 65M06, 65Z05, 70F05 Key words: Quantum mechanics, Schr¨odinger equation, heavy-light particle scattering, interfer- ence, decoherence, numerical discretization, numerical analysis, splitting scheme. 1 Introduction Quantum decoherence is nowadays considered as the key concept in the description of the transition from the quantum to the classical world (see e.g. [6, 7, 9, 19, 20, 22, 24]). As it is well-known, the axioms of quantum mechanics allow superposition states, namely, normalized sums of admissible wave functions are once more admissible wave functions. It is then possible to construct non-localized states that lack a classical inter- pretation, for instance, by summing two states localized far apart from each other.
    [Show full text]
  • Decoherence and Its Role in Interpretations of Quantum Physics
    Decoherence and its Role in Interpretations of Quantum Physics Simon Matthew Thomas Newey Submitted in Accordance with the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Leeds School of Philosophy, Religion and History of Science February 2019 2 The candidate confirms that the work submitted is his/her/their own and that appropriate credit has been given where reference has been made to the work of others. This copy has been supplied on the understanding that it is copyright material and that no quotation from the thesis may be published without proper acknowledgement. The right of Simon Mathew Thomas Newey to be identified as Author of this work has been asserted by Simon Mathew Thomas Newey in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 3 Acknowledgements I would like to thank my supervisors Juha Saatsi and Stephen French for their patience, support and guidance over the last four years. I am grateful to the Arts and Humanities Research Council for funding this project. I am also grateful for helpful and interesting conversations I have had over the last four years with Callum Duguid, Guido Bacciagaluppi, Karim Thébault, Richard Dawid, and Simon Saunders. 4 Abstract The purpose of this thesis is to examine different conceptions of decoherence and their significance within interpretations of quantum mechanics. I set out three different conceptions of decoherence found in the literature and examine the relations between them. I argue that only the weakest of these conceptions is empirically well supported, and that the other two rely on claims about the structure of the histories (robust patterns within the wavefunction) which we occupy which require justification.
    [Show full text]
  • Experimental Test of Decoherence Theory Using Electron Matter Waves Peter J
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by UNL | Libraries University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Faculty Publications, Department of Physics and Research Papers in Physics and Astronomy Astronomy 2018 Experimental test of decoherence theory using electron matter waves Peter J. Beierle Liyun Zhang Herman Batelaan Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/physicsfacpub This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Research Papers in Physics and Astronomy at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications, Department of Physics and Astronomy by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. PAPER • OPEN ACCESS Experimental test of decoherence theory using electron matter waves To cite this article: Peter J Beierle et al 2018 New J. Phys. 20 113030 View the article online for updates and enhancements. This content was downloaded from IP address 129.93.168.10 on 04/08/2019 at 20:58 New J. Phys. 20 (2018) 113030 https://doi.org/10.1088/1367-2630/aaed4e PAPER Experimental test of decoherence theory using electron matter OPEN ACCESS waves RECEIVED 26 August 2018 Peter J Beierle1 , Liyun Zhang2 and Herman Batelaan1 REVISED 1 Department of Physics and Astronomy, University of Nebraska-Lincoln, Lincoln, NE 68588, United States of America 24 October 2018 2 Key Laboratory of Quantum Information and Quantum Optoelectronic Devices, Xi’an Jiaotong University, Xi’an 710049, People’s ACCEPTED FOR PUBLICATION Republic of China 1 November 2018 PUBLISHED E-mail: [email protected] 21 November 2018 Keywords: decoherence, quantum decoherence, electron diffraction, coherence length, surface decoherence, image charge, which-way information Original content from this work may be used under Supplementary material for this article is available online the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 licence.
    [Show full text]
  • Quantifying Early Time Quantum Decoherence Dynamics Through
    Letter pubs.acs.org/JPCL Quantifying Early Time Quantum Decoherence Dynamics through Fluctuations Bing Gu† and Ignacio Franco*,†,‡ †Department of Chemistry and ‡Department of Physics, University of Rochester, Rochester, New York 14627, United States ABSTRACT: We introduce a general but simple relation between the timescale for quantum coherence loss and the initial fluctuations of operators that couple a quantum system with a surrounding bath. The relation allows the prediction and measurement of early time decoherence dynamics for any open quantum system, through purity, without reconstructing the system’s many-body density matrix. It is applied to predict the decoherence time for basic modelsthe Holstein chain, spin- boson and Caldeira-Legget modelscommonly employed to capture electronic, vibrational, and vibronic dynamics in molecules. Such development also offers a practical platform to test the ability of approximate quantum dynamics methods to capture decoherence. In particular, a class of mixed quantum-classical schemes for molecular dynamics where the bath is treated classically, such as Ehrenfest dynamics, are shown to correctly capture short-time decoherence when the initial conditions are sampled from the Wigner distribution. These advances provide a useful platform to develop decoherence times for molecular processes and to test approximate molecular dynamics methods. he loss of quantum coherence is a fundamental and eigenstate with no net dipole will exhibit zero polarization. T ubiquitous process in nature that occurs in any quantum Other commonly used observables such as transport, line- system coupled to an environment, e.g., electrons coupled to shapes, and interference can only offer a basis-dependent vibrations, or vibrations in the presence of solvent.
    [Show full text]
  • Supercomputer Simulations of Transmon Quantum Computers Quantum Simulations of Transmon Supercomputer
    IAS Series IAS Supercomputer simulations of transmon quantum computers quantum simulations of transmon Supercomputer 45 Supercomputer simulations of transmon quantum computers Dennis Willsch IAS Series IAS Series Band / Volume 45 Band / Volume 45 ISBN 978-3-95806-505-5 ISBN 978-3-95806-505-5 Dennis Willsch Schriften des Forschungszentrums Jülich IAS Series Band / Volume 45 Forschungszentrum Jülich GmbH Institute for Advanced Simulation (IAS) Jülich Supercomputing Centre (JSC) Supercomputer simulations of transmon quantum computers Dennis Willsch Schriften des Forschungszentrums Jülich IAS Series Band / Volume 45 ISSN 1868-8489 ISBN 978-3-95806-505-5 Bibliografsche Information der Deutschen Nationalbibliothek. Die Deutsche Nationalbibliothek verzeichnet diese Publikation in der Deutschen Nationalbibliografe; detaillierte Bibliografsche Daten sind im Internet über http://dnb.d-nb.de abrufbar. Herausgeber Forschungszentrum Jülich GmbH und Vertrieb: Zentralbibliothek, Verlag 52425 Jülich Tel.: +49 2461 61-5368 Fax: +49 2461 61-6103 [email protected] www.fz-juelich.de/zb Umschlaggestaltung: Grafsche Medien, Forschungszentrum Jülich GmbH Titelbild: Quantum Flagship/H.Ritsch Druck: Grafsche Medien, Forschungszentrum Jülich GmbH Copyright: Forschungszentrum Jülich 2020 Schriften des Forschungszentrums Jülich IAS Series, Band / Volume 45 D 82 (Diss. RWTH Aachen University, 2020) ISSN 1868-8489 ISBN 978-3-95806-505-5 Vollständig frei verfügbar über das Publikationsportal des Forschungszentrums Jülich (JuSER) unter www.fz-juelich.de/zb/openaccess. This is an Open Access publication distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License 4.0, which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited. Abstract We develop a simulator for quantum computers composed of superconducting transmon qubits.
    [Show full text]
  • Decoherence and the Transition from Quantum to Classical—Revisited
    Decoherence and the Transition from Quantum to Classical—Revisited Wojciech H. Zurek This paper has a somewhat unusual origin and, as a consequence, an unusual struc- ture. It is built on the principle embraced by families who outgrow their dwellings and decide to add a few rooms to their existing structures instead of starting from scratch. These additions usually “show,” but the whole can still be quite pleasing to the eye, combining the old and the new in a functional way. What follows is such a “remodeling” of the paper I wrote a dozen years ago for Physics Today (1991). The old text (with some modifications) is interwoven with the new text, but the additions are set off in boxes throughout this article and serve as a commentary on new developments as they relate to the original. The references appear together at the end. In 1991, the study of decoherence was still a rather new subject, but already at that time, I had developed a feeling that most implications about the system’s “immersion” in the environment had been discovered in the preceding 10 years, so a review was in order. While writing it, I had, however, come to suspect that the small gaps in the land- scape of the border territory between the quantum and the classical were actually not that small after all and that they presented excellent opportunities for further advances. Indeed, I am surprised and gratified by how much the field has evolved over the last decade. The role of decoherence was recognized by a wide spectrum of practicing physicists as well as, beyond physics proper, by material scientists and philosophers.
    [Show full text]
  • Decoherence Rhapsody in the Photosynthesis Process
    DECOHERENCE RHAPSODY IN THE PHOTOSYNTHESIS PROCESS CLAUDIA NEGULESCU Abstract. It is said that classical theories are sometimes inappropriate to describe very efficient biological processes in nature, which seem to be better understood via quantum mechanical models. We are however still very far from understanding how quantum fea- tures can survive in open quantum systems. In this paper the author shall present a simple mathematical model for the illustration of the excitation energy transfer in photo- synthesis complexes, and shall study numerically the environmental induced decoherence effect and its influence on the emergence of classicality in nature. The model is based on the Schr¨odinger equation, describing the propagation of an absorbed excitation through a spin-chain towards a reaction center, and this in permanent interaction with a vibrational environment. Keywords: Quantum mechanics, system-environment entanglement, decoherence, re- duced density matrix, Schr¨odinger equation, numerical simulation, photosynthesis, spin- boson model, excitation energy transfer, spin-chain, harmonic-oscillator chain. 1. Background and motivation Biological processes present facilities and performances which are very impressive and cannot be adequately explained with the only use of traditional (classical) approaches. A certain amount of quantum coherent properties is thought to be used by Nature in order to enhance the efficiency of the underlying processes. For example, the property of non-locality (correlations between distant atoms/molecules) can
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1404.2635V2 [Quant-Ph] 20 Nov 2019 B
    The quantum-to-classical transition and decoherence Maximilian Schlosshauer Department of Physics, University of Portland, 5000 North Willamette Boulevard, Portland, Oregon 97203, USA I give a pedagogical overview of decoherence and its role in providing a dynamical account of the quantum-to-classical transition. The formalism and concepts of decoherence theory are reviewed, followed by a survey of master equations and decoherence models. I also discuss methods for mitigating decoherence in quantum information processing and describe selected experimental investigations of decoherence processes. Note: Please see arXiv:1911.06282 [quant-ph] (published as Phys. Rep. 831, 1{57, 2019) for a much more extensive and up-to-date review of decoherence. CONTENTS I. INTRODUCTION I. Introduction1 Realistic quantum systems are never completely iso- lated from their environment. When a quantum system II. Basic formalism and concepts2 interacts with its environment, it will in general become A. Decoherence and interference damping2 entangled with a large number of environmental degrees B. Environmental monitoring and information of freedom. This entanglement influences what we can transfer3 locally observe upon measuring the system. In partic- C. Environment-induced superselection and ular, quantum interference effects with respect to cer- decoherence-free subspaces4 tain physical quantities (most notably, \classical" quan- 1. Pointer states and the commutativity tities such as position) become effectively suppressed, criterion5 making them prohibitively difficult to observe in most 2. Decoherence-free subspaces6 cases of practical interest. This is the process of deco- D. Proliferation of information and quantum herence, sometimes also called dynamical decoherence or Darwinism6 environment-induced decoherence [1{10]. Stated in gen- E.
    [Show full text]
  • The Decoherence and Interference of Cosmological Arrows of Time for a De Sitter Universe with Quantum Fluctuations
    Article The Decoherence and Interference of Cosmological Arrows of Time for a de Sitter Universe with Quantum Fluctuations Marcello Rotondo * ID and Yasusada Nambu ID Department of Physics, Graduate School of Science, Nagoya University, Chikusa, Nagoya 464-8602, Japan; [email protected] * Correspondence: [email protected] Received: 7 May 2018; Accepted: 8 June 2018; Published: 11 June 2018 Abstract: We consider the superposition of two semiclassical solutions of the Wheeler–DeWitt equation for a de Sitter universe, describing a quantized scalar vacuum propagating in a universe that is contracting in one case and expanding in the other, each identifying the opposite cosmological arrow of time. We discuss the suppression of the interference terms between the two arrows of time due to environment-induced decoherence caused by modes of the scalar vacuum crossing the Hubble horizon. Furthermore, we quantify the effect of the interference on the expectation value of the observable field mode correlations, with respect to an observer that we identify with the spatial geometry. Keywords: quantum cosmology; Wheeler–DeWitt equation; de Sitter universe; quantum decoherence; arrow of time 1. Introduction Resting on the assumption that the laws of Nature are fundamentally quantum, quantum cosmology is the attempt to extend the quantum formalism to the whole universe. This attempt must naturally accommodate the properties of the classical universe we observe, and it should as well provide predictions about the conditions of the very early universe where a drastic divergence from the classical theory might be expected. One of the main approaches to quantum gravity and cosmology, the canonical one, starts with the quantization of the Hamiltonian formulation of general relativity, resulting in a momentum constraint enforcing the diffeomorphism invariance of the theory and a Hamiltonian constraint encoding the dynamics of the geometry [1].
    [Show full text]