<<

Stable Facts, Relative Facts

Andrea Di Biagio1, ∗ and Carlo Rovelli2, 3, 4, † 1Dipartimento di Fisica, Universit`aLa Sapienza, I-00185 Roma, EU 2AMU Universit´e,Universit´ede Toulon, CNRS, CPT, F-13288 Marseille, EU 3Perimeter Institute, 31 Caroline Street N, Waterloo ON, N2L2Y5, Canada 4The Rotman Institute of Philosophy, 1151 Richmond St. N London N6A5B7, Canada (Dated: June 28, 2020) We define and characterise two kinds of facts that play a role in theory: stable and relative. We describe how stable facts emerge in a world of relative facts and then discuss the respective roles they play in connecting the theory and the world. The distinction between relative and stable facts resolves the difficulties pointed out by the no-go theorems of Frauchiger and Renner, Brukner, and Bong et. al.. Basing the ontology of the theory on relative facts clarifies the role of decoherence in bringing about the classical world and solves the apparent incompatibility between the ‘linear evolution’ and ‘projection’ postulates.

I. FACTS IN QUANTUM THEORY or cannot be extended to systems with an infinite num- ber of degrees of freedom [3], or else. But the universal The common textbook presentation of quantum theory success of the theory and all current empirical evidence assumes the existence of a classical world. A measure- strongly suggest that real physical objects are ‘classical’, ment involves an interaction between the classical world meaning they do not display quantum properties, only and a quantum system. The measurement produces a approximatively. There are no exactly classical objects, definite result, for instance a dot on a screen. The result strictly speaking, as everything we interact with is made is a fact by itself, but also establishes a fact about a quan- of atoms and photons, which obey quantum theory. tum system. For instance, a certain measurement result- In formulating the fundamental theory of nature, the ing in a definite record establishes that at some time the use of effective concepts valid only within an approxi- ~ mation is unconvincing. Therefore the attempts to in- z-component of the of an is Lz = 2 . This is a fact. terpret quantum theory as a universal theory, such as Quantum are probabilities for facts, given Many Worlds, Hidden Variables, and others do not rely other facts. The facts are therefore entries of which the on postulating classical objects. A possibility to interpret amplitudes are function. In particular, facts quantum theory as a universal theory neither postulating are used as conditionals for computing probabilities of classical objects, nor postulating unobservable worlds, other facts. For instance, if the spin of the electron men- unobservable variables, or unobserved physics, is Rela- tioned above is then immediately measured in a direction tional Quantum (RQM) [4,5]. RQM bases at an angle θ from the z-axis, the probability to find the the interpretation of the theory on a larger ensemble of ~ ~ facts, of which stable facts are only a subset. These are value Lθ = 2 (a fact), given the fact that Lz = 2 , is ~ ~  2 called relative facts. P Lθ = 2 | Lz = 2 = cos (θ/2). Hence, facts are what is about. Facts ascertained in a conventional measurement are A. Relative facts stable in the following sense. If we know that one of N mutually exclusive facts ai (i = 1 ...N) has happened, the probability P (b) for a fact b to happen is given by Relative facts are defined to happen whenever a phys- ical system interacts with another physical system. Con- X P (b) = P (b|ai)P (ai), (1) sider two systems S and F. If an interaction affects F i in a manner that depends on the value of a certain vari- 1 able LS of S, then the value of LS is a fact relative to where P (ai) is the probability that ai has happened and F. This is true by definition irrespectively of whether F P (b|ai) is the probability for b given ai. We take equation is a classical system or not. That is, whenever the two (1) as a characterisation of stable facts. systems interact, the value of the variable LS becomes a This textbook presentation of quantum mechanics is fact relative to F. incomplete because it assumes the existence of a classi- The interaction with F is the context in which LS takes cal world. An exactly classical world might exist because a specific value; we call the system F, in this role, a current quantum theory has limited validity—for in- stance is violated by physical collapse mechanisms [1,2],

1 We use ‘variable’ to denote any quantity that in the classical the- ory is a function on phase pace. We prefer to avoid the expression ∗ [email protected]’, which is loaded with irrelevant extra baggage: the † [email protected] ideas of observation and a complex observer. 2

‘context’.2 The interaction with the context determines B. Decoherence the fact that a certain variable, LS , has a certain value. Stable facts are only a subset of relative facts, as Since stability is a characteristic feature of the classi- there are many relative facts that are not stable facts. cal world (whose facts invariably satisfy (1)), answering Quantum theory provides probabilities that relate rela- the questions above amounts to explaining in terms of tive facts, but these satisfy (1) only if b and the ai are relative facts what it takes for a system to be classical. facts relative to the same system. That is, if we label Various characterisations of a classical or semiclassical facts with the system they refer to, writing a(F) for a fact situation can be found in the literature: large quantum relative to the system F, it is always true that numbers, semiclassical wave packets or coherent states, macroscopic systems, large or infinite number of degrees (F) X (F) (F) (F) P (b ) = P (b |ai )P (ai ), (2) of freedom... All these features play a role in charac- i terising classical systems in specific situations. But the while it is in general false that key phenomenon that makes facts stable is decoherence [9–11]: the suppression of quantum interference that hap- (W) X (W) (F) (F) pens when some information becomes inaccessible. P (b ) = P (b |ai )P (ai ) (3) i Consider two systems F and E (E for ‘Environment’), and a variable LF of the system F. Let F ai be the (F) if W 6= F. When (3) holds, we say that the facts ai are eigenvalues of LF . A generic state of the coupled system stable with respect to W. F − E can be written in the form The failure of (3) is easily understood in terms of the X standard language of quantum theory. If F is sufficiently |ψi = ci |F aii ⊗ |ψii , (5) isolated it may be possible to maintain the quantum co- i herence of the coupled system S−F formed by S and F where |ψii are normalised states of E. Define together. The interaction entangles the two systems and 2 interference effects between different values of the vari-  = max | hψi|ψji | . (6) i,j able LS can later be detected in the measurements by an observer W. The probabilities for facts of the S −F Now, suppose that: (a)  is vanishing or very small and system relative to W, indeed, can be computed from an (b) a system W does not interact with E. Then the prob- entangled state of the form ability P (b) of any possible fact relative to W resulting from an interaction between F and W can be computed c1|a1i ⊗ |F a1i + c2|a2i ⊗ |F a2i (4) from the obtained tracing over E, that is 0 where ai are values of LS and F ai are values of F s X 2 ρ = TrE |ψihψ| = |ci| |F aiihF ai| + O(). (7) ‘pointer variable’ LF . Probabilities computed from this state feature interference terms, and this violates (3) be- i cause what sums is amplitudes, not probabilities. The (E) 2 By posing P (F ai ) = |ci| , we can then write value of LS , therefore, is not a stable fact. Hence facts relative to a system F cannot in general be (W) X (W) (E) (E) P (b ) = P (b |F ai )P (F ai ) + O(). (8) taken as conditionals for computing probabilities of facts i relative to a different system W. Equation (1) holds only Thus, probabilities for facts b relative to W calculated if b and ai are facts relative to the same system, but fails in general if used for facts relative to different systems. in terms of the possible values of LF satisfy (3) up to a The notation S for ‘system’, F for ‘Friend’ and W small deviation. Hence the fact LF = ai relative to E for ‘Wigner’ is meant to to evoke the famous Wigner’s is stable with respect to W to the extent to which one friend ideal experiment [8]; there is no assumption, how- ignores effects of order . In the limit  → 0, the variable ever, about the system F being quantum or classical, LF of the system F is exactly stable with respect to W. microscopic or macroscopic. The extensive theoretical work on decoherence [12] has Relative facts play a central role in the Relational In- shown that decoherence is practically unavoidable and terpretation of Quantum Mechanics (RQM) [4,5]. We extremely effective as soon as large numbers of degrees shall discuss this role in detail later on. First, how- of freedom are involved. The variables of F that deco- ever, we ask the following questions: what exactly char- here, namely the variables for which  becomes small, are acterises a stable fact, among the relative facts? What determined by the actual physical interactions between gives rise to stable facts? F and E, they are those that commute with the inter- action Hamiltonian. The decoherence time, namely the time needed for  to become so small that interference ef- fects become undetectable by given observational meth- 2 We use ‘context’ here in a sense similar to its use in [6]. The ods, can be computed and is typically extremely short for difference is that we do not require the context to be classical. macroscopic variables of macroscopic objects. All this is See [7]. well understood. 3

It is important for what follows to emphasise two sub- Already at stage 2, the observer might say that LS ‘has tle aspects of decoherence. First, decoherence is not an been measured’ and apply (3), since the interaction with absolute phenomenon, but a relative one: it depends on the inaccessible degrees of freedom greatly suppresses in- how the third system W interacts with the combined sys- terference terms. In other words: stability allows W to tem F−E. Indeed, assumption (b) above is just as crucial ‘de-label’ facts when they are facts relative to F. as assumption (a) in deriving (8). Another system W0 in- In the mathematical formalism, W can assume that teracting with F −E differently might be able to detect ‘the has collapsed’. The value of LS , still, interference effects. does not become a fact relative to the observer—and can- Second, decoherence implies that an event regarding not be known by the observer—until she actually inter- two systems F and E is stable with respect to at third acts with a variable correlated with it. system W. That is, the variable LF is stable relative It is the way that W, F and E couple to each other to W even if the latter has not interacted with it, so that make F a measuring apparatus for W. The stability there is no fact relative to W (yet). This allows us to of F with respect to W extends to all other variables that say that with respect to W the ‘state of the system F interact with S, hence W applying quantum mechanics, has collapsed into the state |F aii state with probability might say that F causes S to collapse. However another 2 0 P (F ai) = |ci| ’, even though W has not interacted F. system W that couples differently to these systems might These observations show that decoherence does not im- still be able to detect interference effects. ply that there is a perfectly classical world of absolute facts, but it does explain why (and when) we can reason In summary, we can distinguish two notions of facts in terms of stable, hence classical, facts. The ubiquity of that play a role in quantum theory: relative facts and decoherence makes very many facts largely stable with stable facts. respect to us. Quantum theory allows us to talk about relative facts and compute probabilities for them. Equation (2) holds but (3) does not. The violation of (3) is quantum inter- C. Measurements ference. Stable facts are a subset of the relative facts. They sat- If two systems S and F interact and their respective isfy (3). A relative fact about a system F is stable with respect to a system W if W has no access to a system variables LS and LF get entangled, and if LF is stable with respect to W, it follows immediately from the defini- E which is sufficiently entangled with F. But stability tions that the stability of L with respect to W extends is only approximate (in principle, no fact is exactly sta- F ble for any finite ) and relative (depends on how the to LS as well. This is precisely what happens in a typical quantum ‘observer’ system couples to the system and the environ- ment). measurement of a variable LS in a laboratory. Think- ing of S, F and W as, respectively, the system being measured, the apparatus and the experimenter, we can separate the measurement in three stages: II. FACTS AND

1. An interaction between the system and the appa- Up to now, we have given definitions of relative and ratus entangles LS with a pointer variable LF of stable facts, and studied their properties. In this section the apparatus. we discuss the roles of relative and stable facts for the interpretation of quantum theory, namely for the relation 2. LF gets correlated with a large number of micro- between the formalism and the reality it describes. scopic variables (forming E) that are inaccessible to the observer W. A. The link between the theory the world 3. The observer W interacts with the pointer variable LF to learn about LS . Let us compare advantages and difficulties of interpret- Let’s this same story in terms of relative facts: ing either stable or relative facts as the link between the- ory and reality. 1. A relative fact is established between S and F. Stable facts are taken as the link between the formal- ism and the world in textbook interpretations of quan- 2. A relative fact is established between F and E. tum theory. They are the conventional ‘measurement Since W does not interact with E, this stabilises outcomes’ in a macroscopic laboratory. They are similar the previous fact for W. to the facts of because in the world described by classical mechanics all facts (variables hav- 3. The value of LF becomes a fact for W and, since it ing certain values at certain times) are exactly stable: the is correlated with LS , the value of the variable LS (epistemic) probabilities for them to happen are always also becomes a fact with respect to W. exactly consistent with (1). In quantum mechanics, facts 4 stable with respect to us are ubiquitous because of the tions. A key assumption used to derive the contradiction ubiquity of decoherence. is the absolute nature of facts. This is Assumption (C) There are however two difficulties in taking stable facts in the paper, which can be stated as follows: “If W, as the of the quantum ontology. First, stability applying quantum theory, concludes that F knows that is relational. Facts are stable only relative to a system LS = a, then W can conclude that LS = a.” The au- that does not have sufficiently precise interactions with thors argue that this assumption is required to deem the an environment system. Therefore one does not avoid theory consistent because different agents using the same relationalism by restricting to stable facts. Second, more theory must arrive at the same conclusions. Let’s anal- seriously, stability is generically approximate only. The yse Assumption (C) in terms of relative facts: in this system and environment are still in a superposition with language, it reads: “If W, applying quantum theory, can respect to a third system. be certain that LS = a relative to F, then W can reason These are serious difficulties if we want to take stable as if LS = a was also relative to W”. Now, as we have facts as the only primary elements of reality. How stable shown, this holds only if every fact relative to F is stable does a fact need to be before it is real? And with re- with respect to W, which is not a given and depends on spect to which systems does it have to be stable, in order the physics. Therefore Assumption (C) only holds if S to be real? Any answer to these questions is bound to or F decohere with respect to W. This is not the case in be as unsatisfactory as the textbook interpretation that the protocol, since W is supposed to have full quantum requires a classical world. control on F and S. As pointed out in [22], no contradic- The alternative is to embrace the contextuality of the tion can be derived if one additionally assumes that what theory in full, and base its ontology on all relative facts. is decoherent for F is also decoherent for W. Hence the Relative facts form the basis of a realist interpretation contradiction follows from inappropriately mixing con- in Relational Quantum Mechanics (RQM). The funda- texts: forgetting that facts are relative and therefore (3) mental contextuality that characterises quantum theory does not hold in general. is interpreted in RQM as the discovery that facts about Another enlightening result is proven by Brukner in a system are always defined relative to another system, [20], and by Bong et. al. in [21]. These works show with which the first system interacts. that the conjunction of (a) observer independent facts In the early history of quantum theory it was recog- (b) locality and (c) no , leads to certain nised that every measurement involves an interaction, inequalities on the correlations in certain scenarios. Like and it was said that variables take values only upon mea- Bell’s inequalities [23, 24], these are derived in a theory- surement. RQM notices that every interaction is in a independent way, and then shown to be violated by the sense a measurement, in that it results in the value of a predictions of quantum theory. If we do not reject (b) variable to become a fact. These facts are not absolute, or (c), the universal validity of quantum theory implies they belong to a context; and there is no ‘special context’: that facts cannot all be observer independent3 [28]. any system can be a context for any other system. Remarkably, these inequalities have already been The (‘the wave function’) does not have shown experimentally to be violated for the case in which an ontic interpretation in RQM. The state is not a ‘thing’, Wigner’s friend is a single photon [21]. One might be nor a condition of a system. Rather, it is what a physicist tempted to dismiss the result on the ground that pho- uses to calculate probabilities for relative facts between tons do not generate facts, but this opens the problem physical systems to happen, given the relevant informa- of deciding which systems give rise to facts. If quantum tion she has. Unlike other epistemic interpretations of theory is universally valid, advances in quantum tech- quantum theory [13–18], the ontology of RQM is realist nologies will allow to perform the same experiment with in the sense that it is not about agents, beliefs, observers, increasingly complex ‘friends’. The predictions of quan- or experiences: it is about real facts of the world and rel- tum theory remain the same: the statistics are incompat- ative probabilities of their occurrence. The ontology is ible with the assumptions of observer independent facts. relational, in the sense that it is based on facts labelled Once again, therefore, the result confirms that the facts by physical contexts. quantum theory deals with are facts relative to systems. Relative facts, therefore, provide a relational but real- We only find language ‘observer-independent’ a bit ist interpretation to quantum theory which does not need misleading: ‘observers’ in the sense of complex systems to refer to complex agents. play no role in all this: facts happen in interactions with

B. No-go theorems for non-relative facts 3 While the word ‘locality’ means different things in different quan- A number of results have recently appeared in the liter- tum physics communities, most epistemic interpretations accept the notion used to prove the result of Bong et.al.. See [25] for an ature as no-go theorems for non-relative (absolute) facts in depth analysis on the notions of locality and superdetermin- [19–21]. ism in the context of the implications of Bell’s theorems. In [19], Frauchiger and Renner show that quantum the- For a discussion of the implications of the ontology of RQM to ory is inconsistent under a certain number of assump- Bell’s inequalities, see [26] and [27]. 5 any system. There are facts relative to any physical sys- The violation of (1) when used for facts relative to dif- tem, not just to special ‘observing’ systems. ferent systems sheds also some light on the underpinnings of . The violation of (1), indeed, has been interpreted as a violation of classical logic [29], as it can C. Conclusions and final comments be written as

The insight of Relational Quantum Mechanics (RQM) P (b and (a1 or a2)) 6= P ((b and a1) or (b and a2)), (9) is that recognising the relative nature of facts offers a straightforward solution to the . in contradiction with the classical logic theorem The measurement problem is the apparent incompati- bility between two postulates: the ‘projection’ and the b and (a1 or a2) = (b and a1) or (b and a2). (10) ‘linear evolution’ postulate. Both postulates can be cor- rect: they refer to facts relative to different systems. Say The apparent violation of logic is understood in RQM as that S interacts with F, so that a fact relative to F is a result of forgetting that facts are relative: labelled by a established. Then the projection postulate is used to up- context, as Bohr has repeatedly pointed out. Facts rela- date the state of S with respect to F, while the unitary tive to a context cannot be used, in general, to compute evolution postulate is used to update the state of S − F probabilities of facts related to other contexts because with respect to a third system W. what is a fact in a certain context is not necessarily a In a slogan: ‘Wigner’s facts are not necessarily his fact in other contexts. Friend’s facts’. As a final remark, observe that if the quantum state This by no means implies that when Wigner and his has no ontic interpretation, the only meaning of ‘being in friend compare notes they find contradictions [4]. Inter- a ’ is that interference effects are actions between S and F do have influence on the facts to be expected. To say ‘Friend is in a quantum super- relative to W. Indeed, after an interaction, S and F are position’ does not mean anything more than saying that entangled relative to W, meaning that in interacting with Wigner would be mistaken in using (3). It has no impli- the two systems, W will find the two correlated. There- cations on how Friend would ‘feel’ in being in a superpo- fore Wigner will always agree with his Friend about the sition. Friend sees a definite result of his measurement, a value of L once he too interacts with them. In this S fact, and this does not prevent Wigner from having the sense, relative facts correspond to real events, they have chance to see an interference effect in his facts. Wigner’s universal empirical consequences. friend does not stop being an observer simply because Still, accepting the relativity of all facts is a strong con- Wigner has a chance to detect interference effects in his ceptual step. It amounts giving up the absolute nature of facts. Schr¨odinger’s cat has no reason to feel ‘superim- facts, namely the existence of an absolute ‘macroreality’ posed’. and of ‘observer-independent facts’ in the language used in discussions of Bell’s inequalities [25]. Such a macro- reality only emerges approximately, relative to systems for which decoherence is sufficiently strong. ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Decoherence has always played a peculiar role in the discussions on the measurement problem. On the one CR thanks Cristian Mariani, Alexia Auff`eves, Philippe hand, it is simply a true physical phenomenon, obviously Grangier and all the participants at the reading group of relevant for shedding light on quantum measurement. On the Institut N´eelin Grenoble, for very stimulating dis- the other hand, there is consensus that decoherence alone cussions at the origin of this paper. is not a solution of the measurement problem, because it This work was made possible through the support of the does not suffice to provide a link between theory and FQXi Grant FQXi-RFP-1818 and of the ID# 61466 grant reality. Decoherence needs an ontology. Relative facts from the John Templeton Foundation, as part of the “The provide such a general ontology, which is well defined Structure of Spacetime (QISS)” with or without decoherence. Decoherence clarifies why Project (qiss.fr). The opinions expressed in this publi- a large class of relative facts become stable with respect cation are those of the authors and do not necessarily to us and form the stable classical world in which we live. reflect the views of the John Templeton Foundation.

[1] Giancarlo Ghirardi, Alberto Rimini, and Tullio Weber, [3] Philippe Grangier, ‘Completing the quantum formalism: ‘Unified dynamics for microscopic and macroscopic sys- why and how ?’ (2020), arXiv:2003.03121 [quant-ph]. tems,’ Physical Review D 34, 470–491 (1986). [4] Carlo Rovelli, ‘Relational quantum mechanics,’ Inter- [2] , ‘On gravity’s role in quantum state re- national Journal of Theoretical Physics 35, 1637–1678 duction,’ General Relativity and Gravitation 28, 581–600 (1996), arXiv:quant-ph/9609002 [quant-ph]. (1996). [5] Federico Laudisa and Carlo Rovelli, ‘Relational quantum 6

mechanics,’ in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Quantum theory as a hero’s handbook,’ (2016), edited by Edward N. Zalta (Metaphysics Research Lab, arXiv:1612.07308 [quant-ph]. Stanford University, 2019) winter 2019 ed. [19] Daniela Frauchiger and Renato Renner, ‘Quantum the- [6] P. Grangier and A. Auff`eves, ‘What is quantum in ory cannot consistently describe the use of itself,’ Nature quantum randomness?’ Philosophical Transactions of the Communications 9 (2018), 10.1038/s41467-018-05739-8, Royal Society A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineer- arXiv:1604.07422 [quant-ph]. ing Sciences 376, 20170322 (2018), arXiv:1804.04807 [20] Caslavˇ Brukner, ‘A no-go theorem for observer- [quant-ph]. independent facts,’ 20, 350 (2018), [7] Alexia Auff`eves and Philippe Grangier, ‘A generic model arXiv:1804.00749 [quant-ph]. for quantum measurements,’ Entropy 21, 904 (2019), [21] Kok-Wei Bong, Anibal Utreras-Alarcon, Farzad Ghafari, arXiv:1907.11261 [quant-ph]. Yeong-Cherng Liang, Nora Tischler, Eric G. Cavalcanti, [8] Eugene P. Wigner, ‘Remarks on the mind-body question,’ Geoff J. Pryde, and Howard M. Wiseman, ‘Testing the in The Scientist Speculates, edited by Irving John Good reality of wigner’s friend’s experience,’ AOS Australian (Basic Books, 1962). Conference on Optical Fibre Technology (ACOFT) and [9] H. Dieter Zeh, ‘On the interpretation of measurement in Australian Conference on Optics, Lasers, and Spec- quantum theory,’ Foundations of Physics 1, 69–76 (1970). troscopy (ACOLS) 2019 (2019), 10.1117/12.2540002, [10] Wojciech H. Zurek, ‘Pointer basis of quantum appara- arXiv:1907.05607 [quant-ph]. tus: Into what mixture does the wave packet collapse?’ [22] Marek Zukowski˙ and Marcin Markiewicz, ‘Even per- Physical Review D 24, 1516–1525 (1981). formed pre-measurements have no results,’ (2020), [11] Wojciech H. Zurek, ‘Environment induced superselection arXiv:2003.07464 [quant-ph]. rules,’ Physical Review D 26, 1862–1880 (1982). [23] J. S. Bell, ‘On the einstein podolsky rosen paradox,’ [12] Wojciech H. Zurek, ‘Decoherence and the transition from Physics Physique Fizika 1, 195–200 (1964). quantum to classical — revisited,’ [24] John S. Bell, ‘On the problem of hidden variables in quan- , 1–31 (2006), arXiv:quant-ph/0306072 [quant-ph]. tum mechanics,’ Reviews of Modern Physics 38, 447–452 [13] , ‘A foundational principle for quantum (1966). mechanics,’ Foundations of Physics 29, 631–643 (1999). [25] Howard M. Wiseman and Eric G. Cavalcanti, ‘Causarum [14] Lucien Hardy, ‘Quantum theory from five reasonable ax- investigatio and the two bell’s theorems of john bell,’ The ioms,’ (2001), arXiv:quant-ph/0101012 [quant-ph]. Frontiers Collection , 119–142 (2016), arXiv:1503.06413 [15] Caslavˇ Brukner and Anton Zeilinger, ‘Information and [quant-ph]. fundamental elements of the structure of quantum the- [26] Pierre Martin-Dussaud, Carlo Rovelli, and Federico Za- ory,’ in Time, Quantum and Information, edited by Lutz lamea, ‘The notion of locality in relational quantum Castell and Otfried Ischebeck (Springer, 2003) pp. 323– mechanics,’ Foundations of Physics 49, 96–106 (2019), 354, arXiv:quant-ph/0212084 [quant-ph]. arXiv:1806.08150 [quant-ph]. [16] Robert W. Spekkens, ‘Evidence for the epistemic view [27] Jacques Pienaar, ‘Comment on “the notion of locality in of quantum states: A toy theory,’ Physical Review relational quantum mechanics”,’ Foundations of Physics A 75 (2007), 10.1103/physreva.75.032110, arXiv:quant- 49, 1404–1414 (2019), arXiv:1807.06457 [quant-ph]. ph/0401052 [quant-ph]. [28] Eric Cavalcanti, ‘Implications of local friendliness viola- [17] Philipp Andres H¨ohn and Christopher S. P. Wever, tion ‘Quantum theory from questions,’ Physical Review A 95 to quantum causality,’ Presentation at Causality in a (2017), 10.1103/physreva.95.012102, arXiv:1511.01130 Quantum World Worksop (2019). [quant-ph]. [29] Garret Birkhoff and , ‘The logic of [18] Christopher A. Fuchs and Blake C. Stacey, ‘QBism: quantum mechanics,’ Annals of Mathematics 37, 823– 843 (1936).