How to Measure Inclusive Fitness, Revisited

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

How to Measure Inclusive Fitness, Revisited Anim. Behav., 1996, 51, 225–228 COMMENTARIES How to measure inclusive fitness, revisited JEFFREY R. LUCAS*, SCOTT R. CREEL† & PETER M. WASER* *Department of Biological Sciences, Purdue University †Rockefeller University Field Research Center (Received 14 September 1994; initial acceptance 31 October 1994; final acceptance 13 March 1995; MS. number: -1136) An individual’s inclusive fitness is derived by verbal definition) is equal to its Darwinian fitness augmenting its traditional Darwinian fitness by stripped of the effects of helpers. This is equival- certain components, and stripping it of others ent to the reproductive success of a breeder in (Hamilton 1964). The component to be added is an unaided pair. But in obligately cooperative the sum of all effects of the individual on his species, unaided pairs cannot rear young (e.g. neighbours, weighted by the coefficient of genetic dwarf mongooses, Helogale parvula: Creel 1990a; relationship (r) between them. In the original African wild dogs, Lycaon pictus: Malcolm & derivation of inclusive fitness, the component to Marten 1982). Under the original verbal definition be subtracted was verbally defined as ‘all compo- of e0, the inclusive fitness of breeders in groups of nents which can be considered as due to the any size would therefore be zero. Bringing the individual’s social environment’ (Hamilton 1964). verbal definition of e0 into line with its original It is not widely appreciated that this verbal defi- algebraic definition resolves the bizarre problem nition of the component to be subtracted does not of zero inclusive fitness for breeders. But as we agree with its algebraic definition. Creel (1990a) discuss here, it raises two new and conceptually used Hamilton’s algebraic definition of inclusive thorny issues. fitness to show that the component to be sub- (1) Calculation of e0 is not always irrelevant tracted, e0, is actually equal to the average effect when using Hamilton’s rule. Creel (1990a) sug- of one individual on others’ fitness (dT0,in gested that Hamilton’s rule (that help is favoured Hamilton’s 1964 formulation). Thus, the calcu- when rb>c, where b is the effect of a helper lation of e0 requires that we know the fraction of on breeder reproductive success, r is the genetic individuals in the population that provide help relatedness between helper and breeder, and c is and the mean amount of help provided per helper. the cost of helping to the helper) is unaffected by e0 is simply the product of these two numbers (see the definition of e0, because e0 is stripped from the below). Subtracting e0 resolves what has become inclusive fitness of both breeders and helpers. known as the ‘double accounting’ problem Thus ‘e0 drops out of an inequality comparing (Grafen 1984; Brown 1987). inclusive fitness for alternative strategies’ (Creel The verbal definition of e0 is important, because 1990a). The implication is that the correct defi- it is primarily the verbal definition of inclusive nition of e0 is not relevant to a correct calculation fitness that has been put to empirical use (Grafen of Hamilton’s rule. However, this statement does 1982, 1984). The flaw in the original verbal defi- not hold if inclusive fitness effects are summed nition of e0 can be seen by applying it to the case over more than a single reproductive season and if of a breeder in an obligately cooperative species alternative decisions differ in their risk of mortal- (Creel 1990a). In a group with a single breeding ity. This is true because e0 is subtracted from each pair, the breeder’s inclusive fitness (using the old individual’s fitness each time during its lifespan that direct or indirect fitness components are Correspondence: J. R. Lucas, Department of Biological measured, that is, once every breeding season. We 0 Sciences, Purdue University, West Lafayette, IN 47907- can illustrate why e will not cancel out using a 1392, U.S.A. (email: [email protected]). simple example. 0003–3472/96/010225+04 $12.00/0 ? 1996 The Association for the Study of Animal Behaviour 225 226 Animal Behaviour, 51, 1 Assume that if an individual dispersed it would Therefore the helper’s inclusive fitness is produce, on average, 0.5 offspring as a breeder in (r"p)#b. This will be negative whenever the a new group the current year but would have zero coefficient of relationship is less than the pro- probability of surviving another year. The inclu- portion of individuals in the population that are sive fitness of this individual would be 0.5"e0. non-breeding helpers. Alternatively, assume that the individual could From published demographic data (e.g. Stacey remain in its current group, and if it did so it & Koenig 1990) it appears that negative inclusive would survive the current year as a helper, helping fitness for helpers will be common, unless helpers its sibling produce 0.5 more offspring than it often obtain hidden direct reproduction. For 12 otherwise would have produced. Also, assume cooperatively breeding species ranging from lions, that this helper then bred the next year, pro- Panthera leo, to splendid fairy wrens, Malurus ducing 1.0 offspring and dying thereafter. The splendens, mean helper–breeder relatedness falls lifetime inclusive fitness of this option is between 0.23 and 0.47 (Macdonald 1980; (0.5#r"e0)+(1.0"e0). In this case, the fitness Woolfenden & Fitzpatrick 1984; Austad & components to be subtracted from dispersers’ and Rabenold 1985; Emlen & Wrege 1988; Mills 1990; non-dispersers’ fitnesses will not cancel out. More Packer et al. 1991; Creel & Waser 1994; also see generally, differences in mortality risks between Stacey & Koenig 1990). If the dichotomy between alternatives will cause differences in expected helping and breeding were absolute, this range of longevity, which will in turn cause differences in r-values would yield negative fitness for helpers in the relative weighting of e0 on lifetime inclusive groups larger than 2.6 (for r=0.23) to 3.8 (for fitness. We emphasize that since e0 relates to the r=0.47). Many cooperatively breeding mammals average ability of individuals to give (or equiva- live in group sizes large enough to yield negative lently to receive) help, it should be calculated on a fitness for helpers (e.g. African wild dogs with per-breeding-season basis, as we use it here. mean adult pack size of 11: Fuller et al. 1992). A number of recent analyses have shown that Modal group size for most cooperatively breeding future effects are important components in the birds is less than four (two, in most cases: Stacey estimation of inclusive fitness (e.g. Brown 1987; & Koenig 1990), but even for these species Mumme et al. 1989; Creel 1990b; Lucas et al., in many helpers will have a negative fitness unless press). In addition, differences in mortality risks relatedness is high. between alternative behaviour patterns (e.g. dis- Of course, the calculation of inclusive fitness is persal versus non-dispersal, or helping versus non- affected by direct fitness effects. Direct production helping) are likely to be nearly ubiquitous (Brown of offspring by helpers has recently been dis- 1987; Waser et al. 1994). Together, these data covered in several species (e.g. dwarf mongooses: suggest that an accurate evaluation of e0 is Keane et al. 1994; stripe-backed wrens: Rabenold warranted. et al. 1990). This direct reproduction will obvi- (2) Helpers often will have negative inclusive ously increase the inclusive fitness of helpers, but fitness. Applying the definition of e0 in a dynamic at least in dwarf mongooses, the number of young optimization analysis of dispersal decisions in produced by helpers is insufficient to give them cooperatively breeding dwarf mongooses, Lucas positive inclusive fitness (Lucas et al., in press). et al. (in press) found that subordinate helpers The role of the indirect component of inclusive of many age–sex classes had negative inclusive fitness on the evolution of helping behaviour has fitness. To illustrate this, assume that helpers do been controversial. Some authors argue that in- not breed (and breeders do not help), so that a direct effects are relatively unimportant (Zahavi helper’s fitness is entirely indirect (Brown 1987). 1974; Ligon 1981; Walters et al. 1992); others Indirect fitness is the product of a helper’s effect suggest that indirect effects cannot be overlooked on breeder reproductive success (b) multiplied by (Mumme et al. 1989; Emlen & Wrege 1991; Creel its relatedness to the breeder (r). Inclusive fitness is & Waser 1994). Although we have shown here obtained by stripping e0 from this indirect fitness, that the inclusive fitness of helpers can actually be where e0 is the product of an average helper’s negative, we want to emphasize that this does not effect on breeder reproductive success (b) multi- mean that indirect fitness effects will be unimport- plied by the proportion of individuals in the ant in the evolution of helping behaviour in these population that are helpers (p) (Creel 1990a). species. For example, we show elsewhere that, Commentaries 227 despite negative indirect fitness for subordinate ness to other group members, and so on. The dwarf mongooses, indirect effects can play a alternative genotypes that compete in the real major role in the evolution of social behaviour in world are likely to be more complicated, this species (Lucas et al., in press). and might for example influence their bearers’ Non-breeders will likely suffer negative fitness, tendencies to disperse conditional on some com- irrespective of their choice of behaviour, if the bination of, for example, dominance and related- frequency of helpers in a population is large. ness. An approach that explicitly allows the Indeed, the inclusive fitness of non-helping non- modelling of such conditional traits is dynamic breeders will always be negative whenever helping optimization; we have presented a model of exists.
Recommended publications
  • Inclusive Fitness As a Criterion for Improvement LSE Research Online URL for This Paper: Version: Accepted Version
    Inclusive fitness as a criterion for improvement LSE Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/104110/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Birch, Jonathan (2019) Inclusive fitness as a criterion for improvement. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C :Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 76. ISSN 1369-8486 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsc.2019.101186 Reuse This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial-NoDerivs (CC BY-NC-ND) licence. This licence only allows you to download this work and share it with others as long as you credit the authors, but you can’t change the article in any way or use it commercially. More information and the full terms of the licence here: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/ [email protected] https://eprints.lse.ac.uk/ Inclusive Fitness as a Criterion for Improvement Jonathan Birch Department of Philosophy, Logic and Scientific Method, London School of Economics and Political Science, London, WC2A 2AE, United Kingdom. Email: [email protected] Webpage: http://personal.lse.ac.uk/birchj1 This article appears in a special issue of Studies in History & Philosophy of Biological & Biomedical Sciences on Optimality and Adaptation in Evolutionary Biology, edited by Nicola Bertoldi. 16 July 2019 1 Abstract: I distinguish two roles for a fitness concept in the context of explaining cumulative adaptive evolution: fitness as a predictor of gene frequency change, and fitness as a criterion for phenotypic improvement. Critics of inclusive fitness argue, correctly, that it is not an ideal fitness concept for the purpose of predicting gene- frequency change, since it relies on assumptions about the causal structure of social interaction that are unlikely to be exactly true in real populations, and that hold as approximations only given a specific type of weak selection.
    [Show full text]
  • Coevolution to the Edge of Chaos: Coupled Fitness Landscapes, Poised States, and Coevolutionary Avalanches
    J. theor. Biol. (1991) 149, 467-505 Coevolution to the Edge of Chaos: Coupled Fitness Landscapes, Poised States, and Coevolutionary Avalanches STUART A. KAUFFMANt and SONKE JOHNSEN Department of Biochemistry and Biophysics, School of Medicine, University of Pennsylvania and Sante Fe Institute, Sante Fe, New Mexico, U.S.A. (Received on 20 April 1990, Accepted in revised form on 8 August 1990) We introduce a broadened framework to study aspects of coevolution based on the NK class of statistical models of rugged fitness landscapes. In these models the fitness contribution of each of N genes in a genotype depends epistatically on K other genes. Increasing epistatic interactions increases the rugged multipeaked character of the fitness landscape. Coevolution is thought of, at the lowest level, as a coupling of landscapes such that adaptive moves by one player deform the landscapes of its immediate partners. In these models we are able to tune the ruggedness of landscapes, how richly intercoupled any two landscapes are, and how many other players interact with each player. All these properties profoundly alter the character of the coevolutionary dynamics. In particular, these parameters govern how readily coevolving ecosystems achieve Nash equilibria, how stable to perturba- tions such equilibria are, and the sustained mean fitness of coevolving partners. In turn, this raises the possibility that an evolutionary rnetadynamics due to natural selection may sculpt landscapes and their couplings to achieve coevolutionary systems able to coadapt well. The results suggest that sustained fitness is optimized when landscape ruggedness relative to couplings between landscapes is tuned such that Nash equilibria just tenuously form across the ecosystem.
    [Show full text]
  • Fitness Maximization Jonathan Birch
    Fitness maximization Jonathan Birch To appear in The Routledge Handbook of Evolution & Philosophy, ed. R. Joyce. Adaptationist approaches in evolutionary ecology often take it for granted that natural selection maximizes fitness. Consider, for example, the following quotations from standard textbooks: The majority of analyses of life history evolution considered in this book are predicated on two assumptions: (1) natural selection maximizes some measure of fitness, and (2) there exist trade- offs that limit the set of possible [character] combinations. (Roff 1992: 393) The second assumption critical to behavioral ecology is that the behavior studied is adaptive, that is, that natural selection maximizes fitness within the constraints that may be acting on the animal. (Dodson et al. 1998: 204) Individuals should be designed by natural selection to maximize their fitness. This idea can be used as a basis to formulate optimality models [...]. (Davies et al. 2012: 81) Yet there is a long history of scepticism about this idea in population genetics. As A. W. F. Edwards puts it: [A] naive description of evolution [by natural selection] as a process that tends to increase fitness is misleading in general, and hill-climbing metaphors are too crude to encompass the complexities of Mendelian segregation and other biological phenomena. (Edwards 2007: 353) Is there any way to reconcile the adaptationist’s image of natural selection as an engine of optimality with the more complex image of its dynamics we get from population genetics? This has long been an important strand in the controversy surrounding adaptationism.1 Yet debate here has been hampered by a tendency to conflate various different ways of thinking about maximization and what it entails.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is Inclusive Fitness Theory, and What Is It For?
    This is a repository copy of What is inclusive fitness theory, and what is it for?. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/110451/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Marshall, J.A.R. orcid.org/0000-0002-1506-167X (2016) What is inclusive fitness theory, and what is it for? Current Opinion in Behavioral Sciences, 12. pp. 103-108. ISSN 2352-1546 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cobeha.2016.09.015 Article available under the terms of the CC-BY-NC-ND licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/) Reuse This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs (CC BY-NC-ND) licence. This licence only allows you to download this work and share it with others as long as you credit the authors, but you can’t change the article in any way or use it commercially. More information and the full terms of the licence here: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/ Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ 1 What is inclusive fitness theory, and what is it for? 2 3 James A. R. Marshall 4 5 Department of Computer Science and Department of Animal and Plant Sciences 6 University of Sheffield 7 Regent Court 8 211 Portobello 9 Sheffield S1 4DP 10 UNITED KINGDOM 11 12 Abstract: 13 Inclusive fitness theory is a cornerstone of modern evolutionary biology, yet 14 critics contend it is not general but subject to serious limitations, and is ripe for 15 replacement, for example by multilevel selection theory.
    [Show full text]
  • The Theory of Inclusive Fitness
    THE THEORY OF INCLUSIVE FITNESS David C. Queller Department of Biology, WasHington University in St. Louis EMAIL: [email protected] A review of SOCIAL EVOLUTION AND INCLUSIVE FITNESS THEORY: AN INTRODUCTION. By James A. R. Marshall. Princeton: Princeton University Press. $39.95. xvii + 195 p. Index. ISBN: 9780691161563. 2015. This is a pre-copyedit version of: Queller, D.C. The theory of inclusive fitness. Book review of "Social Evolution and Inclusive Fitness Theory: An Introduction” by J.A.R. Marshall. Quarterly Review of Biology 91:343-347. 1 W. D. Hamilton was responsible for two major innovations in the early 1960’s (Hamilton, 1964). First, He invented, formalized, and made a strong case for tHe importance of kin selection, tHe idea tHat genetic alleles will be selected in part via their effects on others who share the allele. His otHer main contribution was tHe idea of inclusive fitness, a general and intuitive way of analyzing tHis kind of selection. THougH Hamilton’s ideas Have been Hugely influential, tHere Has been no book focused on the topic of inclusive fitness theory. That gap has now been filled by James MarsHall’s “Social Evolution and Inclusive Fitness THeory”. There are various ways to approach inclusive fitness. MarsHall’s main theoretical approach appeals to me because it is one that I initiated earlier in my career (Queller, 1992), using the Price equation. MarsHall’s Chapter 3 provides a nice introduction to this equation, well worth reading in its own right because of the ever-expanding utility of the Price equation in evolutionary research.
    [Show full text]
  • Evolution of Cooperation Cooperation Vs
    Cooperation Main points for today Cooperation • Sociality, cooperation, mutualism, altruism - definitions • Kin selection – Hamilton’s rule, how to calculate r Why is it surprising and • Group selection – the price equation, green beards, and assortment how does it evolve • Classic examples – alarm calls, helpers at the nest, social insects, predator inspection, food sharing Definitions ‘Social behavior’ is NOT cooperative behavior Cooperation: Displaying a behavior that benefits another Group living vs. cooperation individual. (If both benefit that's mutualism.) Sociality-no- Altruism: cooperation Displaying a behavior that benefits another and individual at a cost to oneself. cooperation- Sociality/social behavior: no-sociality Living in a group/behavior in interactions with conspecifics I define ‘sociality’ as living with other individuals of the same species at least semi-permanently. Why individuals do not sacrifice themselves The evolutionary mystery for the good of the group How can altruism evolve? • If the recipient of the cooperative/altruistic act benefits, it is going to leave more offspring . • The actor however is not going to leave more offspring, or even fewer offspring – fewer altruists in the next generation . If such behavior is heritable, and it goes on over many generations, it will ultimately die out. 1 The evolutionary mystery Evolution of altruism Altruism: 5 possible Group selection explanations The Price equation : shows how variance partitioned among individuals and groups leads to selection • Group selection
    [Show full text]
  • INCLUSIVE FITNESS and ALTRUISM Psychological Aspects
    Psychological aspects of 1 Running head: INCLUSIVE FITNESS AND ALTRUISM Psychological aspects of adaptations for kin directed altruistic helping behaviors Daniel J. Kruger Daniel J. Kruger, Ph.D. [email protected] www-personal.umich.edu/~kruger Please cite this paper as: Kruger, D. J. (2001). Psychological aspects of adaptations for kin directed altruistic helping behaviors. Social Behavior and Personality, 29, 323-330. Psychological aspects of 2 Abstract A questionnaire study sheds light on the psychological component of kin selecting tendencies predicted by Hamilton’s (1964b) inclusive fitness theory of discriminatory altruistic behavior based on genetic similarity. Participants rated donations of assistance aiding survival and material wealth as more rational and ethical when these actions were performed for closer relatives. Participants also felt a greater obligation to perform these acts for a close relation. A comparison condition where assistance was unlikely to affect survival or reproductive success did not exhibit these tendencies. Psychological aspects of 3 Psychological aspects of adaptations for kin directed altruistic helping behaviors Speculation on altruism reflects on the fundamental character of human nature. Philosophers throughout the ages have debated the question of whether humans actually intend to perform actions that are beneficial to others and costly to themselves, without any clear resolution (Cialdini, Brown, Lewis, Luce, & Neuberg, 1997). Social psychologists continue this debate. Although some argue that the experience of empathy for others leads to truly altruistic actions (Batson et al., 1997), others believe that conditions leading to empathic concern also lead to a greater sense of self-other overlap (Cialdini et al., 1997). Thus, helping others leads to a more favorable mental state because it is at least partially self-directed.
    [Show full text]
  • Inclusive Fitness Theory for the Evolution of Religion Animal
    SPECIAL ISSUE: KIN SELECTION Animal Behaviour xxx (2014) 1e11 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Animal Behaviour journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/anbehav Special issue: Kin Selection Inclusive fitness theory for the evolution of religion Bernard Crespi a,*, Kyle Summers b a Department of Biological Sciences, Simon Fraser University, Burnaby, BC, Canada b Department of Biology, East Carolina University, Greenville, NC, U.S.A. article info We describe and evaluate an integrative hypothesis for the origin and evolution of human religious fi Article history: cognition and behaviour, based on maximization of inclusive tness. By this hypothesis, the concept of Received 11 October 2013 God is represented by one’s circle of kin and social salience, such that serving God and serving this circle Initial acceptance 14 January 2014 become synonymous. The theory is supported by data from anthropology, evolutionary theory, psy- Final acceptance 6 February 2014 chology, neuroscience, psychiatry, endocrinology and genetics. It is largely compatible with, yet can Available online xxx subsume, previous theories of religion that are also based on adaptation and natural selection. MS. number: ASI-13-00853 Ó 2014 The Association for the Study of Animal Behaviour. Published by Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved. Keywords: inclusive fitness kinship religious behaviour There is something sacred about kinship, as most social anthro- In this article we describe and analyse an integrative theory, pologists who have studied its operation in the field are prepared to based on inclusive fitness maximization, for understanding the admit (Myers, 1975) origin and evolution of religious behaviour and the concepts of God and supernatural agents.
    [Show full text]
  • Natural Selection and the Maximization of Fitness
    Jonathan Birch Natural selection and the maximization of fitness Article (Accepted version) (Refereed) Original citation: Birch, Jonathan (2016) Natural selection and the maximization of fitness. Biological Reviews, 91 (3). pp. 712-727. ISSN 1469-185X DOI: 10.1111/brv.12190 © 2015 Cambridge Philosophical Society This version available at: http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/61885/ Available in LSE Research Online: May 2015 LSE has developed LSE Research Online so that users may access research output of the School. Copyright © and Moral Rights for the papers on this site are retained by the individual authors and/or other copyright owners. Users may download and/or print one copy of any article(s) in LSE Research Online to facilitate their private study or for non-commercial research. You may not engage in further distribution of the material or use it for any profit-making activities or any commercial gain. You may freely distribute the URL (http://eprints.lse.ac.uk) of the LSE Research Online website. This document is the author’s final accepted version of the journal article. There may be differences between this version and the published version. You are advised to consult the publisher’s version if you wish to cite from it. Natural selection and the maximization of fitness Jonathan Birch*,† Christ’s College, University of Cambridge, St Andrew’s Street, Cambridge, CB2 3BU, UK *E-mail:[email protected]; Tel.: +44 (0)20 7107 7334. †Present address: Department of Philosophy, Logic and Scientific Method, London School of Economics and Political Science, Houghton Street, London, WC2A 2AE, UK.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Sociobiology: Inclusive Fitness and the Core Genome Herbert Gintis
    An Introduction to Sociobiology: Inclusive Fitness and the Core Genome Herbert Gintis June 29, 2013 The besetting danger is ...mistaking part of the truth for the whole...in every one of the leading controversies...both sides were in the right in what they affirmed, though wrong in what they denied John Stuart Mill, On Coleridge, 1867 A Mendelian populationhas a common gene pool, whichis itscollective or corporate genotype. Theodosius Dobzhansky, Cold Springs Harbor Symposium, 1953. The interaction between regulator and structural genes... [reinforces] the concept that the genotype of the individual is a whole. Ernst Mayr, Populations, Species and Evolution, 1970 Abstract This paper develops inclusive fitness theory with the aim of clarifying its appropriate place in sociobiological theory and specifying the associated principles that render it powerful. The paper introduces one new concept, that of the core genome. Treating the core genome as a unit of selection solves problems concerning levels of selection in evolution. 1 Summary Sociobiology is the study of biological interaction, both intragenomic, among loci in the genome, and intergenomic, among individuals in a reproductive popula- tion (Gardner et al. 2007). William Hamilton (1964) extended the theory of gene frequencies developed in the first half of the Twentieth century (Crow and I would like to thank Samuel Bowles, Eric Charnov, Steven Frank, Michael Ghiselin, Peter Godfrey-Smith, David Haig, David Queller, Laurent Lehmann, Samir Okasha, Peter Richerson, Joan Roughgarden, Elliot Sober, David Van Dyken, Mattijs van Veelen and Edward O. Wilson for advice in preparing this paper. 1 Kimura 1970, B¨urger 2000, Provine 2001) to deal with such behavior.
    [Show full text]
  • Invasion Fitness, Inclusive Fitness, and Reproductive Numbers In
    bioRxiv preprint doi: https://doi.org/10.1101/036731; this version posted January 15, 2016. The copyright holder for this preprint (which was not certified by peer review) is the author/funder, who has granted bioRxiv a license to display the preprint in perpetuity. It is made available under aCC-BY-NC 4.0 International license. Invasion fitness, inclusive fitness, and reproductive numbers in heterogeneous populations Laurent Lehmann,∗ Charles Mullon,y Erol Ak¸cay,z and Jeremy Van Clevex Wednesday 13th January, 2016 ∗Department of Ecology and Evolution, University of Lausanne, Switzerland. yDepartment of Ecology and Evolution, University of Lausanne, Switzerland. zDepartment of Biology, University of Pennsylvania, USA. xDepartment of Biology, University of Kentucky, USA. 1 bioRxiv preprint doi: https://doi.org/10.1101/036731; this version posted January 15, 2016. The copyright holder for this preprint (which was not certified by peer review) is the author/funder, who has granted bioRxiv a license to display the preprint in perpetuity. It is made available under aCC-BY-NC 4.0 International license. Abstract 2 How should fitness be measured to determine which phenotype or \strategy" is unin- vadable when evolution occurs in subdivided populations subject to local demographic and 4 environmental heterogeneity? Several invasion fitness measures, such as basic reproductive number, lifetime dispersal success of a local lineage, or inclusive fitness have been proposed 6 to address this question, but the relationships between them and their generality remains unclear. Here, we ascertain uninvadability (all mutant strategies always go extinct) in terms 8 of the growth rate of a mutant allele arising as a single copy in a population.
    [Show full text]
  • Kin Selection and Sexual Selection
    Downloaded from rstb.royalsocietypublishing.org on July 16, 2012 Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B (2012) 367, 2314–2323 doi:10.1098/rstb.2011.0281 Review The sociobiology of sex: inclusive fitness consequences of inter-sexual interactions Tommaso Pizzari1,* and Andy Gardner2,3 1Edward Grey Institute, Department of Zoology and 2Department of Zoology, University of Oxford, South Parks Road, Oxford OX1 3PS, UK 3Balliol College, University of Oxford, Broad St., Oxford OX1 3BJ, UK The diversity of social interactions between sexual partners has long captivated biologists, and its evolution has been interpreted largely in terms of ‘direct fitness’ pay-offs to partners and their des- cendants. Inter-sexual interactions also have ‘indirect effects’ by affecting the fitness of relatives, with important consequences for inclusive fitness. However, inclusive fitness arguments have received limited consideration in this context, and definitions of ‘direct’ and ‘indirect’ fitness effects in this field are often inconsistent with those of inclusive fitness theory. Here, we use a sociobiology approach based on inclusive fitness theory to distinguish between direct and indirect fitness effects. We first consider direct effects: we review how competition leads to sexual conflict, and discuss the conditions under which repression of competition fosters sexual mutualism. We then clarify indirect effects, and show that greenbeard effects, kin recognition and population viscosity can all lead to episodes of indirect selection on sexual interactions creating potential for sexual altruism and spite. We argue that the integration of direct and indirect fitness effects within a sociobiology approach enables us to consider a more diverse spectrum of evolutionary outcomes of sexual interactions, and may help resolving current debates over sexual selection and sexual conflict.
    [Show full text]