Reductionism and Holism, Chance and Selection, Mechanism and Mind Ursula Goodenough Washington University in St Louis, [email protected]
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Washington University St. Louis: Open Scholarship Washington University in St. Louis Washington University Open Scholarship Biology Faculty Publications & Presentations Biology 6-2005 Reductionism and Holism, Chance and Selection, Mechanism and Mind Ursula Goodenough Washington University in St Louis, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/bio_facpubs Part of the Biology Commons, Ethics in Religion Commons, and the Evolution Commons Recommended Citation Goodenough, Ursula, "Reductionism and Holism, Chance and Selection, Mechanism and Mind" (2005). Biology Faculty Publications & Presentations. 88. https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/bio_facpubs/88 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Biology at Washington University Open Scholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Biology Faculty Publications & Presentations by an authorized administrator of Washington University Open Scholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Reductionism and Holism, Chance and Selection, Mechanism and Mind Ursula Goodenough Department of Biology Washington University Draft of article published in Aygon 40:369-380 (2005) Abstract Despite its rich and deepening panoply of empirical support, evolutionary theory continues to generate widespread concern. Some of this concern can be attributed to misunderstandings of the original concept, some to unfamiliarity with its current trajectories, and some to strongly held fears that it strips the human of cherished attributes. This essay seeks to deconstruct such misunderstandings, lift up current concepts of what evolution entails, and address some of the existential issues it generates. Key Words: Evolution, neo-Darwinism, emergence, free will Author: Ursula Goodenough is Professor of Biology in the Department of Biology, Washington University, St. Louis MO 63130; email [email protected] A philosopher friend recently asked me the following questions: 1) What is your understanding of evolution and its religious relevance? 2) Might you address the deep question as to whether the worldview implied by most standard science is mechanistic? Is it possible to 1 show that Neo-Darwinism does not affirm the mechanistic world view, that it provides for the causal efficacy of free and purposive action? Or, how you do see the worldview assumed and affirmed by mainstream science? 3) Can Neo-Darwinism itself be reformulated so as to make much clearer than is normally done that it has room for more dimensions of the total life process? These questions have stimulated the remarks I offer below. I offer them in the context of a paper that Terry Deacon and I recently published in Zygon (1) wherein we consider various aspects of the evolutionary process, and human evolution in particular, from the perspective of emergence, with a focus on the moral facet of religious response. It is my hope that these two essays will illustrate that present-day “mainstream” evolutionary concepts are exciting, multi- dimensional, and have much to offer to the religious life. I also grapple, in this essay, with the question of why these concepts are so often misunderstood and so often the target of vilification. Neo-Darwinism I realized in starting out that I didn’t know what Neo-Darwinism is. So I entered it in www.google.com. The #1 hit was to a site criticizing Neo-Darwinism and favoring the panspermia theory wherein life comes in from other planets. The next 3 hits were critiques offered by creationist/intelligent design organizations. As I continued to read, I came to understand that the term Neo-Darwinism serves as code for views of the evolutionary process that a variety of persons and groups are not comfortable with. The original term, neo-Darwinian theory, was not an -ism. Rather, it referred to the coupling of two understandings: 1) the 19th- century Darwinian understanding that selection acting on heritable variation would produce evolutionary change and 2) the early 20th- century understanding that heritable variants arise by the apparently random process of gene mutation. While features of this synthesis have been summarized in various short phrases, the original version of the theory, in Julian Huxley’s Evolution: the Modern Synthesis (1942), was book-length, and multiple additional layers of 2 understanding of the relationship between genetics and evolution have been accumulating in the ensuing 60 years. Particularly interesting is that whereas there appears to be broad appreciation that atomic theory, for example, has deepened profoundly since its original articulation, bringing us quarks and strong and weak nuclear forces and the like, neo-Darwinian theory is described by Neo-Darwinism detractors in much the form that it was originally set forth. The additional layers of understanding -- the evolutionary role of gene duplications and of mutations in genetic regulatory elements, for example – are hard to find in web-site treatises on Neo-Darwinism. So why is it the case that atomic theory has not become “Atomism” and its “Atomist” adherents the target of critical websites, whereas neo-Darwinian theory has become the nefarious Neo- Darwinism practiced by reductionistic materialistic know-it-all Neo- Darwinists? Why are there no proposals that “overturn” Atomism while proposals abound that “expose the fatal flaws” of a 60-year-old version of evolutionary theory called Neo-Darwinism? The answer, I can only presume, is that atomic theory does not seem to generate existential concerns while neo-Darwinian theory clearly does. I will take up the matter of existential concern below. But at this juncture, given that the term Neo-Darwinism has come to carry such baggage, I suggest that it be jettisoned and that we just talk about present-day theories of biological evolution. With that said, we can go on to examine the pejoratives “reductionistic” and “materialistic,” which will lead us into our philosopher’s question about “mechanistic.” Reductionism and Holism I am a bench scientist, a molecular geneticist/cell biologist, and have devoted my career to the study of a eukaryotic single-celled green alga called Chlamydomonas. My colleagues and I have made contributions to an understanding of how the organism carries out photosynthesis, how it swims, how it forms its cell wall, how it conducts its sexual cycle, and how the genes that encode various 3 sexual traits have diverged when two closely related Chlamydomonas species are compared. Our experiments are “reductionistic” in the sense that they focus on genes and proteins and not the whole organism or its ecological context. From a physicist’s perspective, of course, our experiments are not reductionist at all since we pay no attention to individual atoms or quarks, albeit we are fully aware that these levels of organization are “down there” and have everything to do with what we attend to; indeed, their existence is fully implicit in our experimental design and interpretation. By the same token, we are fully aware that the molecular facets of Chlamydomonas that we are studying have everything to do with the whole organism and its ecological context, and should we obtain an experimental result that is inconsistent with these “larger” understandings – e.g. if our data indicate that a protein operates in a certain way after boiling and we know that Chlamydomonas is killed by boiling -- we would conclude that this property of the protein, albeit of possible interest for some reason, is irrelevant to the organism as a whole. Again, by the same token, scientists studying the ecology of Chlamydomonas try to keep what is known about its genes and proteins fully in view as they ask their “larger” questions, just as they also understand that the Chlamydomonas ecosystem is but a tiny part of an enormous biosphere which is but a miniscule part of an enormous universe. That is, the ecologists are also reductionists. So who are the “holists”? I would respond that no scientist, and no scholar in any field for that matter, is a holist when asking a specific question, since specificity is by definition focused on some facet of the whole. But I would also respond that all scientists are holists in that we are all aware, when making a specificity move at whatever “level,” that the specifics reside in wholes, where wholes are emergent from parts and hence have different properties from individual parts. Systems Thinking A critique that is often leveled at molecular-level biologists is that we have ignored the existence of complex systems in our reductionistic fervor to analyze genes and proteins, that we eschew 4 the “holistic” concepts articulated in complexity theory and its synonyms. Without in any way disparaging the important theoretical contributions made to our understanding of complex systems by the likes of Prigogene and Kauffman, an understanding that organisms are made up of complex systems has been a core understanding of biology since the inception of the field. Metabolic pathways, embryology, neural networks, animal behavior, and so on can only be understood as complex systems, and as a graduate student 40 years ago this was the implicit grounding of everything that I was taught. But once the modern-day principles of complex systems thinking are grasped – once one understands the thermodynamic constraints and possibilities, the importance of initial and boundary conditions and the interdependence of events – biologists in recent decades have gone ahead and sought to understand a specific system by studying its parts: How does microtubule sliding participate in the emergent system called flagellar motility? How does cell migration participate in the formation of a nervous system during embryology? How does sequential expression of homeobox genes set out the animal body plan? In asking such questions we have in no way lost sight of the system as a whole; rather, we are asking questions of the system that allow us to better understand how it acquires its holistic properties.