Formal Methods in Software Engineering

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Formal Methods in Software Engineering Machines can be required to maintain information about relationships on the information contained within them. Relation between sets If S and T are two sets, then their Cartesian product SxT is the set of all pairs (s, t) of elements from S and T respectively. This is defined as follows: s↦t pronounced s maps to t It exactly means the same as (s,t). it is a pair whose first element is s and whose second element is t. A relation R between sets S and T expresses a relationship between elements in S and elements in T. It is captured as a set of pairs (s, t) with s∈ S and t ∈ T representing those elements which are related. PHOTOGRAPHER={anna, bob, chris, dave, elizabeth, francis} and CAMERA={canon, kodak ,hasselblad ,minolta, olympus ,pentax} The relation owns detailing the ownership relation between photographers and their cameras can be defined as follows Owns={(anna, canon), (bob, canon), (bob, kodak), (chris, hasselblad), (chris, kodak), (chris, pentax), (dave, pentax), (elizabeth, pentax),(elizabeth, minolta)} Or using the notation map Owns={(anna ↦ canon), (bob ↦ canon), (bob ↦ kodak), (chris ↦ hasselblad), (chris ↦ kodak), (chris ↦ pentax), (dave ↦ pentax), (elizabeth ↦ pentax),(elizabeth ↦ minolta)} A relation between S and T is a subset of SxT or an element of P(SxT). The notation S⟷T denotes the set of relations between S and T. Hence S↦T is an abbreviation for the set of all substes of SxT S⟷T=P(SxT) To specify that R is a relation between S and T we write R∈S⟷T. In this case set S is said to be the source of R and the set T is said to be the target. For example owns ∈ PHOTOGRAPHER⟷CAMERA The statement that (dave, pentax) ∈ owns states that dave is related to pentax in the relation owns. dave↦pentax also states that dave is related to pentax. If owns records the cameras that are owned by the photographers, then this corresponds to the information that dave owns a pentax camera. When producing specifications, we are generally interested in extracting information from the relations our machines maintain, To answer particular questions such as: Does Bob own a camera? How many cameras does Elizabeth own? Who owns a Hasselblad camera? Which cameras are used by both Chris and Dave? How many cameras does Anna own? Is there anyone that does not have a camera? There are constructs for extracting the information required for questions to be expressed in relations. Extracting the domain and range of a relation Domain restriction: restricting the relation to a particular domain of interest Range restriction: restricting the relation to a particular range of interest Identifying the elements related to some item in a given set. Relational inverse the relation the opposite way round The domain of a relation R∈ S ↔T is the set of elements of S that R relates to something in T. Items in the source set that are related to something, it is written dom(R) Dom(owns)= {anna,bob, chris, dave, elizabeth} The range is the set of elements of T that are related to some element of S. it is written ran(R) For example Ran(owns)={canon, kodak, hasselblad, minolta, pentax} A relation R∈ S↔ T can be projected onto a particular domain U⊆S. Only the relationship for items in U is of interest. The result is those pairs in R whose first element is in U. It is written U⊲ R. This is domain restriction. U⊲ R={S ↦ t | s ↦ t ∈ R ∧ S ∈ U} For example To consider only the cameras that chris owns, the relation owns can be restricted to the set {chris}. A complementary restriction removes all pairs whose first element is in U. This is written U ⩤ R Domain anti restriction U ⩤ R= { S↦ t | t ∈R ∧ s ∉ U} The target set can also be restricted. The range restriction R⊳ V gives all pairs in R whose second element is in V⊆ T. For example, to consider only those photographers who have a kodak camera the relation owns can be range restricted to {kodak} Range anti restriction R⩥V gives all pairs apart from those whose second element is in V To identify all the elements in the target T that are related to some elements U of the source. If 푈 ⊆ 푆, then the set of elements in T related to U is called the relational image of U. It is written as R[U]. It is same as R[U]=ran(U⊲ R) R[U]={t | s↦t∈ 푅 ∧ 푠 ∈ 푈} The relational image of {chris, elizabeth} through owns; This is written owns{chris, elizabeth} R-1 it is the type T⟷S R-1={t↦s | s↦t ∈ 푅} The inverse of the owns relation could be called by ownedby It is concerned with the conjunction of relations. If s is related to t, and t is related to u, then it is often useful to put these two relations together and observe that s is related to u. If s↦t ∈ 푅0 푎푛푑 푡 ↦ 푢 ∈ 푅1 , 푡ℎ푒푛 푠 ↦u ∈ R0;R1 A relation might have a same set S and T Identity relation Written as id(S) and is of type S⟷ S A pair (s,t) will be in the identity relation if and only if s=t. thus Id(S)={(s,t)| s∈ 푆 ∧ 푡 ∈ 푆 ∧ 푠 = 푡} The identity relation is reflexive. Furthermore, it is the smallest reflexive relation on S: a relation is reflexive if and only if id(S)⊆R A relation R∈ 푆 ⟷ 푆 is symmetric, if it relates s1 to s0 and s0 to s1. The order of two elements does not matter. Example Relation id(S) is symmetric Relation R is symmetric if R=R-1 A relation R∈ 푆 ⟷ 푆 is anti-symmetric, if it relates two distinct elements in at most one way. For s0≠ 푠1. 푓 푠0 ↦ 푠1 ∈ 푅, 푡ℎ푒푛푠1 ↦ 푠0 ∉ 푅 It happens when R⋂R-1-id(S)={} If a relation relates two elements at most one way. This is equivalent to the property R⋂R-1={}. It follows that R cannot intersect at all with id(S): that R⋂id(S)={} Whenever s0↦s1 ∈ 푅 and s1 ↦s2 ∈ 푅 then s0 ↦s2 ∈ 푅 reflexive: For every element a in A, (a,a) is in R. symmetric: If an ordered pair (a,b) in R, (b,a) is in R. transitive: If ordered pairs (a,b) and (b,c) in R, (a,c) is in R. My name is ………………….. I remember ……………………… If a relation R: S⟷ S is reflexive, symmetric, and transitive, then it is called as equivalence relation. It means set S can be considered as the union of a collection of pairwise disjoint equivalence classes. Example If X is the set of all cars, and the equivalence relation is“ has the same color as", then one particular equivalence class consists of all green cars. For example, if A = {1, 2, 3}, we can define a relation R = {(1,2), (2,3), (3,1), (3,2)}. R = {(1,2), (2,3), (3,1), (3,2)}. For R to be reflexive it must contain (1,1), (2,2), and (3,3). Since R doesn't even contain (1,1), it is not reflexive. Here is an equivalence relation R2 on A: R2 = {(1,1), (1,3), (2,2), (3,1), (3,3)}. If a relation R: S⟷ S on elements of a set S can be composed with itself. The relation R;R is well defined. For example If parent∈ 푃퐸푅푆푂푁 ⟷ 푃퐸푅푆푂푁 then grandeparent= parent;parent grandgrandparent-=parent3 Using mathematical induction A transitive relation with itself can be written as If s0↦s1∈ 푅 and s1↦s2∈ R and s0 ↦ 푠2 ∈R. This is equivalent to the property R;R⊆R. For example the subset relation is transitive A reflexive relation R relates two elements of S, when there is some iterate of R including R0 which relates them. This is written as R* and it is defined as follows If R is symmetric then R* is an equivalence relation It excludes the 0th iteration of R and relates two elements of S, when there is iterate of R which relates them. Example succeeds∈ 푃퐸푅푆푂푁 ⟷ 푃퐸푅푆푂푁 The relation follows =succeeds+ holds between a person and any person anywhere behind him in the queue. in this example, a person is considered not to follow himself A relation R0 ∈ 푆 ⟷ 푇 푎푛푑 A relation 1R ∈ 푆 ⟷ 푇 Then the relational override R0 R1 Example Chris disposes off his camera collection and then buys an Olympus, the resulting relationship between photographers and their cameras will be given by This relation will be given by Functions are a particular kind of relations. For a relation to be a function, it must have one further property that it relates elements of S to no more than one element of T. If s is related to some element by the function f, then f(s) denotes the value of the function on s.(unique element that is related to s) It is defined only for those elements which are related to some value in T. Function from S to T is a relation which relates each element in S to at most one element in T. Some elements of S might not be related to anything, if they are related to some element then that element is unique. It generalizes the concept of a function ƒ: X → Y by not forcing f to map every element of X to an element of Y (only some subset X' of X The set of partial function is defined by S ⇸ T.
Recommended publications
  • The Partial Function Computed by a TM M(W)
    CS601 The Partial Function Computed by a TM Lecture 2 8 y if M on input “.w ” eventually <> t M(w) halts with output “.y ” ≡ t :> otherwise % Σ Σ .; ; Usually, Σ = 0; 1 ; w; y Σ? 0 ≡ − f tg 0 f g 2 0 Definition 2.1 Let f :Σ? Σ? be a total or partial function. We 0 ! 0 say that f is a partial, recursive function iff TM M(f = M( )), 9 · i.e., w Σ?(f(w) = M(w)). 8 2 0 Remark 2.2 There is an easy to compute 1:1 and onto map be- tween 0; 1 ? and N [Exercise]. Thus we can think of the contents f g of a TM tape as a natural number and talk about f : N N ! being a recursive function. If the partial, recursive function f is total, i.e., f : N N then we ! say that f is a total, recursive function. A partial function that is not total is called strictly partial. 1 CS601 Some Recursive Functions Lecture 2 Proposition 2.3 The following functions are recursive. They are all total except for peven. copy(w) = ww σ(n) = n + 1 plus(n; m) = n + m mult(n; m) = n m × exp(n; m) = nm (we let exp(0; 0) = 1) 1 if n is even χ (n) = even 0 otherwise 1 if n is even p (n) = even otherwise % Proof: Exercise: please convince yourself that you can build TMs to compute all of these functions! 2 Recursive Sets = Decidable Sets = Computable Sets Definition 2.4 Let S Σ? or S N.
    [Show full text]
  • Iris: Monoids and Invariants As an Orthogonal Basis for Concurrent Reasoning
    Iris: Monoids and Invariants as an Orthogonal Basis for Concurrent Reasoning Ralf Jung David Swasey Filip Sieczkowski Kasper Svendsen MPI-SWS & MPI-SWS Aarhus University Aarhus University Saarland University [email protected][email protected] [email protected] [email protected] rtifact * Comple * Aaron Turon Lars Birkedal Derek Dreyer A t te n * te A is W s E * e n l l C o L D C o P * * Mozilla Research Aarhus University MPI-SWS c u e m s O E u e e P n R t v e o d t * y * s E a [email protected] [email protected] [email protected] a l d u e a t Abstract TaDA [8], and others. In this paper, we present a logic called Iris that We present Iris, a concurrent separation logic with a simple premise: explains some of the complexities of these prior separation logics in monoids and invariants are all you need. Partial commutative terms of a simpler unifying foundation, while also supporting some monoids enable us to express—and invariants enable us to enforce— new and powerful reasoning principles for concurrency. user-defined protocols on shared state, which are at the conceptual Before we get to Iris, however, let us begin with a brief overview core of most recent program logics for concurrency. Furthermore, of some key problems that arise in reasoning compositionally about through a novel extension of the concept of a view shift, Iris supports shared state, and how prior approaches have dealt with them.
    [Show full text]
  • Enumerations of the Kolmogorov Function
    Enumerations of the Kolmogorov Function Richard Beigela Harry Buhrmanb Peter Fejerc Lance Fortnowd Piotr Grabowskie Luc Longpr´ef Andrej Muchnikg Frank Stephanh Leen Torenvlieti Abstract A recursive enumerator for a function h is an algorithm f which enu- merates for an input x finitely many elements including h(x). f is a aEmail: [email protected]. Department of Computer and Information Sciences, Temple University, 1805 North Broad Street, Philadelphia PA 19122, USA. Research per- formed in part at NEC and the Institute for Advanced Study. Supported in part by a State of New Jersey grant and by the National Science Foundation under grants CCR-0049019 and CCR-9877150. bEmail: [email protected]. CWI, Kruislaan 413, 1098SJ Amsterdam, The Netherlands. Partially supported by the EU through the 5th framework program FET. cEmail: [email protected]. Department of Computer Science, University of Mas- sachusetts Boston, Boston, MA 02125, USA. dEmail: [email protected]. Department of Computer Science, University of Chicago, 1100 East 58th Street, Chicago, IL 60637, USA. Research performed in part at NEC Research Institute. eEmail: [email protected]. Institut f¨ur Informatik, Im Neuenheimer Feld 294, 69120 Heidelberg, Germany. fEmail: [email protected]. Computer Science Department, UTEP, El Paso, TX 79968, USA. gEmail: [email protected]. Institute of New Techologies, Nizhnyaya Radi- shevskaya, 10, Moscow, 109004, Russia. The work was partially supported by Russian Foundation for Basic Research (grants N 04-01-00427, N 02-01-22001) and Council on Grants for Scientific Schools. hEmail: [email protected]. School of Computing and Department of Mathe- matics, National University of Singapore, 3 Science Drive 2, Singapore 117543, Republic of Singapore.
    [Show full text]
  • Division by Zero in Logic and Computing Jan Bergstra
    Division by Zero in Logic and Computing Jan Bergstra To cite this version: Jan Bergstra. Division by Zero in Logic and Computing. 2021. hal-03184956v2 HAL Id: hal-03184956 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-03184956v2 Preprint submitted on 19 Apr 2021 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. DIVISION BY ZERO IN LOGIC AND COMPUTING JAN A. BERGSTRA Abstract. The phenomenon of division by zero is considered from the per- spectives of logic and informatics respectively. Division rather than multi- plicative inverse is taken as the point of departure. A classification of views on division by zero is proposed: principled, physics based principled, quasi- principled, curiosity driven, pragmatic, and ad hoc. A survey is provided of different perspectives on the value of 1=0 with for each view an assessment view from the perspectives of logic and computing. No attempt is made to survey the long and diverse history of the subject. 1. Introduction In the context of rational numbers the constants 0 and 1 and the operations of addition ( + ) and subtraction ( − ) as well as multiplication ( · ) and division ( = ) play a key role. When starting with a binary primitive for subtraction unary opposite is an abbreviation as follows: −x = 0 − x, and given a two-place division function unary inverse is an abbreviation as follows: x−1 = 1=x.
    [Show full text]
  • Division by Zero: a Survey of Options
    Division by Zero: A Survey of Options Jan A. Bergstra Informatics Institute, University of Amsterdam Science Park, 904, 1098 XH, Amsterdam, The Netherlands [email protected], [email protected] Submitted: 12 May 2019 Revised: 24 June 2019 Abstract The idea that, as opposed to the conventional viewpoint, division by zero may produce a meaningful result, is long standing and has attracted inter- est from many sides. We provide a survey of some options for defining an outcome for the application of division in case the second argument equals zero. The survey is limited by a combination of simplifying assumptions which are grouped together in the idea of a premeadow, which generalises the notion of an associative transfield. 1 Introduction The number of options available for assigning a meaning to the expression 1=0 is remarkably large. In order to provide an informative survey of such options some conditions may be imposed, thereby reducing the number of options. I will understand an option for division by zero as an arithmetical datatype, i.e. an algebra, with the following signature: • a single sort with name V , • constants 0 (zero) and 1 (one) for sort V , • 2-place functions · (multiplication) and + (addition), • unary functions − (additive inverse, also called opposite) and −1 (mul- tiplicative inverse), • 2 place functions − (subtraction) and = (division). Decimal notations like 2; 17; −8 are used as abbreviations, e.g. 2 = 1 + 1, and −3 = −((1 + 1) + 1). With inverse the multiplicative inverse is meant, while the additive inverse is referred to as opposite. 1 This signature is referred to as the signature of meadows ΣMd in [6], with the understanding that both inverse and division (and both opposite and sub- traction) are present.
    [Show full text]
  • On Extensions of Partial Functions A.B
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector Expo. Math. 25 (2007) 345–353 www.elsevier.de/exmath On extensions of partial functions A.B. Kharazishvilia,∗, A.P. Kirtadzeb aA. Razmadze Mathematical Institute, M. Alexidze Street, 1, Tbilisi 0193, Georgia bI. Vekua Institute of Applied Mathematics of Tbilisi State University, University Street, 2, Tbilisi 0143, Georgia Received 2 October 2006; received in revised form 15 January 2007 Abstract The problem of extending partial functions is considered from the general viewpoint. Some as- pects of this problem are illustrated by examples, which are concerned with typical real-valued partial functions (e.g. semicontinuous, monotone, additive, measurable, possessing the Baire property). ᭧ 2007 Elsevier GmbH. All rights reserved. MSC 2000: primary: 26A1526A21; 26A30; secondary: 28B20 Keywords: Partial function; Extension of a partial function; Semicontinuous function; Monotone function; Measurable function; Sierpi´nski–Zygmund function; Absolutely nonmeasurable function; Extension of a measure In this note we would like to consider several facts from mathematical analysis concerning extensions of real-valued partial functions. Some of those facts are rather easy and are accessible to average-level students. But some of them are much deeper, important and have applications in various branches of mathematics. The best known example of this type is the famous Tietze–Urysohn theorem, which states that every real-valued continuous function defined on a closed subset of a normal topological space can be extended to a real- valued continuous function defined on the whole space (see, for instance, [8], Chapter 1, Section 14).
    [Show full text]
  • Associativity and Confluence
    Journal of Pure and Applied Mathematics: Advances and Applications Volume 3, Number 2, 2010, Pages 265-285 PARTIAL MONOIDS: ASSOCIATIVITY AND CONFLUENCE LAURENT POINSOT, GÉRARD H. E. DUCHAMP and CHRISTOPHE TOLLU Institut Galilée Laboratoire d’Informatique de Paris-Nord Université Paris-Nord UMR CNRS 7030 F-93430 Villetaneuse France e-mail: [email protected] Abstract A partial monoid P is a set with a partial multiplication × (and total identity 1P ), which satisfies some associativity axiom. The partial monoid P may be embedded in the free monoid P ∗ and the product × is simulated by a string rewriting system on P ∗ that consists in evaluating the concatenation of two letters as a product in P, when it is defined, and a letter 1P as the empty word . In this paper, we study the profound relations between confluence for such a system and associativity of the multiplication. Moreover, we develop a reduction strategy to ensure confluence, and which allows us to define a multiplication on normal forms associative up to a given congruence of P ∗. Finally, we show that this operation is associative, if and only if, the rewriting system under consideration is confluent. 2010 Mathematics Subject Classification: 16S15, 20M05, 68Q42. Keywords and phrases: partial monoid, string rewriting system, normal form, associativity and confluence. Received May 28, 2010 2010 Scientific Advances Publishers 266 LAURENT POINSOT et al. 1. Introduction A partial monoid is a set equipped with a partially-defined multiplication, say ×, which is associative in the sense that (x × y) × z = x × ()y × z means that the left-hand side is defined, if and only if the right-hand side is defined, and in this situation, they are equal.
    [Show full text]
  • Wheels — on Division by Zero Jesper Carlstr¨Om
    ISSN: 1401-5617 Wheels | On Division by Zero Jesper Carlstr¨om Research Reports in Mathematics Number 11, 2001 Department of Mathematics Stockholm University Electronic versions of this document are available at http://www.matematik.su.se/reports/2001/11 Date of publication: September 10, 2001 2000 Mathematics Subject Classification: Primary 16Y99, Secondary 13B30, 13P99, 03F65, 08A70. Keywords: fractions, quotients, localization. Postal address: Department of Mathematics Stockholm University S-106 91 Stockholm Sweden Electronic addresses: http://www.matematik.su.se [email protected] Wheels | On Division by Zero Jesper Carlstr¨om Department of Mathematics Stockholm University http://www.matematik.su.se/~jesper/ Filosofie licentiatavhandling Abstract We show how to extend any commutative ring (or semiring) so that di- vision by any element, including 0, is in a sense possible. The resulting structure is what is called a wheel. Wheels are similar to rings, but 0x = 0 does not hold in general; the subset fx j 0x = 0g of any wheel is a com- mutative ring (or semiring) and any commutative ring (or semiring) with identity can be described as such a subset of a wheel. The main goal of this paper is to show that the given axioms for wheels are natural and to clarify how valid identities for wheels relate to valid identities for commutative rings and semirings. Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 Why invent the wheel? . 3 1.2 A sketch . 4 2 Involution-monoids 7 2.1 Definitions and examples . 8 2.2 The construction of involution-monoids from commutative monoids 9 2.3 Insertion of the parent monoid .
    [Show full text]
  • Dividing by Zero – How Bad Is It, Really?∗
    Dividing by Zero – How Bad Is It, Really?∗ Takayuki Kihara1 and Arno Pauly2 1 Department of Mathematics, University of California, Berkeley, USA [email protected] 2 Département d’Informatique, Université Libre de Bruxelles, Belgium [email protected] Abstract In computable analysis testing a real number for being zero is a fundamental example of a non- computable task. This causes problems for division: We cannot ensure that the number we want to divide by is not zero. In many cases, any real number would be an acceptable outcome if the divisor is zero - but even this cannot be done in a computable way. In this note we investigate the strength of the computational problem Robust division: Given a pair of real numbers, the first not greater than the other, output their quotient if well-defined and any real number else. The formal framework is provided by Weihrauch reducibility. One particular result is that having later calls to the problem depending on the outcomes of earlier ones is strictly more powerful than performing all calls concurrently. However, having a nesting depths of two already provides the full power. This solves an open problem raised at a recent Dagstuhl meeting on Weihrauch reducibility. As application for Robust division, we show that it suffices to execute Gaussian elimination. 1998 ACM Subject Classification F.2.1 Numerical Algorithms and Problems Keywords and phrases computable analysis, Weihrauch reducibility, recursion theory, linear algebra Digital Object Identifier 10.4230/LIPIcs.MFCS.2016.58 1 Introduction We cannot divide by zero! is probably the first mathematical impossibility statement everyone encounters.
    [Show full text]
  • Additive Decomposition Schemes for Polynomial Functions Over Fields Miguel Couceiro, Erkko Lehtonen, Tamas Waldhauser
    Additive decomposition schemes for polynomial functions over fields Miguel Couceiro, Erkko Lehtonen, Tamas Waldhauser To cite this version: Miguel Couceiro, Erkko Lehtonen, Tamas Waldhauser. Additive decomposition schemes for polyno- mial functions over fields. Novi Sad Journal of Mathematics, Institut za matematiku, 2014, 44(2), pp.89-105. hal-01090554 HAL Id: hal-01090554 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01090554 Submitted on 18 Feb 2017 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. This paper appeared in Novi Sad J. Math. 44 (2014), 89{105. ADDITIVE DECOMPOSITION SCHEMES FOR POLYNOMIAL FUNCTIONS OVER FIELDS MIGUEL COUCEIRO, ERKKO LEHTONEN, AND TAMAS´ WALDHAUSER Abstract. The authors' previous results on the arity gap of functions of several vari- ables are refined by considering polynomial functions over arbitrary fields. We explicitly describe the polynomial functions with arity gap at least 3, as well as the polynomial functions with arity gap equal to 2 for fields of characteristic 0 or 2. These descriptions are given in the form of decomposition schemes of polynomial functions. Similar descrip- tions are given for arbitrary finite fields. However, we show that these descriptions do not extend to infinite fields of odd characteristic.
    [Show full text]
  • Title Note on Total and Partial Functions in Second-Order Arithmetic
    Note on total and partial functions in second-order arithmetic Title (Proof Theory, Computation Theory and Related Topics) Author(s) 藤原, 誠; 佐藤, 隆 Citation 数理解析研究所講究録 (2015), 1950: 93-97 Issue Date 2015-06 URL http://hdl.handle.net/2433/223934 Right Type Departmental Bulletin Paper Textversion publisher Kyoto University 数理解析研究所講究録 第 1950 巻 2015 年 93-97 93 Note on total and partial functions in second-order arithmetic Makoto Fujiwara* Takashi Sato Mathematical Institute Mathematical Institute Tohoku University Tohoku University 6-3, Aramaki Aoba, Aoba-ku Sendai, Miyagi, Japan [email protected] Abstract We analyze the total and partial extendability for partial functions in second-order arith- metic. In particular, we show that the partial extendability for consistent set of finite partial functions and that for consistent sequence of partial functions are equivalent to WKL (weak K\"onig's lemma) over $RCA_{0}$ , despite the fact that their total extendability derives ACA (arith- metical comprehension). 1 Introduction The mainstream of reverse mathematics has been developed in second-order arithmetic, whose language is set-based and functions are represented as their graphs [4]. For this reason, some results on partial functions in reverse mathematics do not correspond to those in computability theory while many results in computability theory can be transformed into the corresponding results in reverse mathematics straightforwardly. For example, it is known in computability theory that every computable partial $\{0$ , 1 $\}$ -valued function has a total extension with low degree, and also that there exists a computable partial $\{0$ , 1 $\}$ -valued function which has no computable total extension (cf.
    [Show full text]
  • The Mobius Inverse Monoid
    JOURNAL OF ALGEBRA 200, 428]438Ž. 1998 ARTICLE NO. JA977242 The MobiusÈ Inverse Monoid Mark V. Lawson School of Mathematics, Uni¨ersity of Wales, Bangor, Gwynedd LL57 1UT, United Kingdom Communicated by Peter M. Neumann Received March 20, 1997 We show that the MobiusÈ transformations generate an F-inverse monoid whose maximum group image is the MobiusÈ group. We describe the monoid in terms of McAlister triples. Q 1998 Academic Press 1. INTRODUCTION MobiusÈ transformations can be handled in two ways. The naive way views them as partial functions defined on the complex plane, whereas the sophisticated way views them as functions defined on the extended com- plex plane. In the first part of this paper, I shall view MobiusÈ transforma- tions from the naive standpoint. Formally, a MobiusÈ transformation is a partial function a of the complex plane, C, having the following form: aŽ.z s Žaz q b .Žr cz q d .where a, b,c, d are complex numbers and ad y bc / 0. Of course, there are many ways to write the function a because multiplying a, b, c, and d by a non-zero complex number results in a different form but the same func- tion. This must always be borne in mind in the sequel. MobiusÈ transformations are partial functions rather than functions because of their denominators; if the coefficient c is non-zero then there is one value of z satisfying cz q d s 0. Thus the transformations are of two types: the functions in which c s 0, and the partial functions in which c / 0.
    [Show full text]