The Invisible Hand — Invisible Because It Does Not Exist?∗

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Invisible Hand — Invisible Because It Does Not Exist?∗ The Invisible Hand | Invisible Because It Does Not Exist?∗ Adam Brandenburgery Harborne Stuartz Version 12/08/13 Abstract We argue that the application of game theory to economics leads to a serious challenge to the supposed benevolence of Adam Smith's Invisible Hand. The usual view in economics is that the Invisible Hand works, i.e., individualistic behavior leads to the largest economic pie, unless market imperfections or failures are present. Starting from a game-theoretic approach, all interdependencies are a priori present in an economic system, and to be sure that the Invisible Hand will work, one must be sure that various interdependencies are absent. This analytical reversal | from a question of presence to a question of absence | reverses the burden of proof. The presumption is now that the Invisible Hand does not work, unless it can be shown that interdependencies are limited in the appropriate way. We explain that, while game theory has long been applied to economics, this key insight has been obscured by the fact that it has been applied in a piecemeal rather than holistic fashion. We end with a brief reference to the biological view that members of our species have prosocial as well as self-interested tendencies | and to some additional issues this raises for an analysis of the Invisible Hand. 1 Game Theory vs. The Invisible Hand There is a well-known scene in the movie A Beautiful Mind 1 in which the young game theorist John Nash and his fellow male Princeton students are watching some women who have just entered the Princeton bar. Should they all compete for the attentions of the most attractive one? Nash's fellow students appear to think so. Indeed, proud of their erudition, they invoke Adam Smith's Invisible Hand to claim that it is even to the common good that they do so. Looking up suddenly from his pile of books, Nash strongly disagrees:2 ∗We owe this line to Ben Polak, who shared it with us some years ago. A seminar audience at the National University of Singapore Business School, students in the NYU class The Project, and Amar Bhide, Robert Frank, Jonathan Haidt, Jessy Hsieh, Geoffrey Miller, Stephen Miller, Aurelie Ouss, Alex Peysakhovich, Paul Romer, Clay Shirky, Richard Sylla, Natalya Vinokurova, Shellwyn Weston, and Bernie Yeung provided valuable input. As always, in thanking someone we do not mean to suggest that person necessarily shares the views we express here. Financial support from the NYU Stern School of Business is gratefully acknowledged. tih-12-08-13 yAddress: Stern School of Business, New York University, 44 West 4th Street, New York, NY 10012, [email protected], http://www.stern.nyu.edu/%7Eabranden. zAddress: Stern School of Business, New York University, 44 West 4th Street, New York, NY 10012, hstu- [email protected], http://www.stern.nyu.edu/%7Ehstuart. “Adam Smith said the best outcome for the group comes from everyone trying to do what's best for himself. Incorrect. The best outcome results from everyone trying to do what’s best for himself and the group.” Nash lays out an alternative | and, to his mind, superior | strategy for him and his colleagues to follow to gain the attentions of the women. This is, of course, a fictional account, so it provides no information about what the real John Nash might say about the Invisible Hand. But is the fictional Nash correct? Does game theory really tell us, in some general and profound way, that if everyone follows the prescription of doing the best for oneself, the result may well not be the best group or social outcome? If so, this would be a striking proposition. A belief that the Invisible Hand works much of the time underlies the presumption in favor of unfettered markets that is prevalent in economics today. In this essay, we will argue that in an interdependent world, game theory should seriously un- dermine confidence in the benevolence of the Invisible Hand. 2 Game Theory and the Pie If game theory really undermines the Invisible Hand, why is this fact not widely known?3 After all, game theory is a widely used mathematical tool | used extensively in modern economics, in particular. We will argue that while there is indeed a lot of game theory in economics nowadays, the way game theory has been used serves to obscure this fundamental issue. Do'not' confess' Confess' 1'Year' 0'Years' Do'not' confess' 1'Year' 20'Years' 20'Years' 5'Years' Confess' 0'Years' 5'Years' Figure 1 We start with the most famous game model of all, the Prisoner's Dilemma.4 See Figure 1. The story is well known. There is sufficient evidence to convict both suspects, Alice and Bob, of a minor crime (1-year sentence each), but insufficient evidence to convict the suspects of a more serious crime (5-year sentence each) unless at least one of them confesses. The police offer a carrot (no time served) and a stick (20-year sentence) in such a way that each suspect is better off confessing, regardless of what the other suspect decides to do. In this game, when each player makes the best individual choice (\Confess"5), they fail to arrive at the best joint outcome for them (which would be a 1-year sentence each). 2 All this is clear and is well known. What is not so clear is whether the outcome in which Alice and Bob both confess is good or bad under some appropriate measure of the overall worth of the game | what can be called the overall \pie." Perhaps, society is best off if Alice and Bob are each kept out of circulation for 5 years. Perhaps not, because they have families which depend on them. The point is that the Prisoner's Dilemma model does not provide enough information for us to decide. What is missing is a definition of the overall pie | and a way of saying how the players' actions in a game affect this pie. We need a game theory that talks about these concepts. Turning to economics, if we want to use game theory to understand whether or not the Invisible Hand works, we need to be able to pose within game theory the question: When players follow their individual interests, do the choices they make lead to the largest overall economic pie? We need a game theory that includes a definition of the overall economic pie and that also contains a principle that explains how players' actions affect the size of this pie. 3 A Patchwork of Models This is not the game theory that has, for the very large part, been used in economics. To see this, start where economics starts, which is with the so-called perfect market as depicted by the usual supply-and-demand diagram. The largest possible pie is the area between the supply and demand curves. This is precisely the pie that will result if the market price is the one that goes through the intersection of the two curves, and sellers and buyers transact at this price. In the language of economics, the outcome is efficient.6 The next step is to analyze markets which depart from this one, because of the presence of \imperfections" such as market power (monopoly, oligopoly, etc.), externalities (also termed \market failures"), or other features. This is the point at which game theory enters the picture. But, the way game theory enters is via a patchwork of models. For each feature, there is a large repertoire of purpose-built game models used to examine it. For example, for oligopoly, there is the Cournot model, the Bertrand model, and many others. Textbooks often contain literally dozens of different such models.7 For each specific model, we can analyze how that model works and answer the question of whether or not the outcome is economically efficient. But, this case-by-case approach does not allow us to answer the question: What are the general conditions under which economic efficiency does or does not result? An answer that says efficiency results in this model, but not in that model, and so on, is not very illuminating. What is needed is a general game model of the pie and of how the players’ actions affect the size of the pie. This model needs to be capable of describing a wide variety of markets. With such a model, we can hope to identify general factors that determine whether or not the Invisible Hand works. 3 4 Preview There is such a game model. It can be built by going back to the early days of game theory and looking at how John von Neumann (in his seminal 1928 Mathematische Annalen paper8) and then von Neumann together with Oskar Morgenstern (in their 1944 book Theory of Games and Economic Behavior 9) began to develop a theory of how \value" (i.e., the pie) is created by and divided among the players in a game. We will apply this general model (more precisely, a development of it) to the question of when is it true that players, following their individual interests, make choices that lead to the largest overall pie. Our answer is a complete reversal of the usual one. The usual answer is that the Invisible Hand works, unless various kinds of market imperfections or failures are present. This is the natural answer when one starts with the perfect market and works outwards from it, so to speak. But, when we start with the general game model, there is a striking reversal.
Recommended publications
  • Game Theory- Prisoners Dilemma Vs Battle of the Sexes EXCERPTS
    Lesson 14. Game Theory 1 Lesson 14 Game Theory c 2010, 2011 ⃝ Roberto Serrano and Allan M. Feldman All rights reserved Version C 1. Introduction In the last lesson we discussed duopoly markets in which two firms compete to sell a product. In such markets, the firms behave strategically; each firm must think about what the other firm is doing in order to decide what it should do itself. The theory of duopoly was originally developed in the 19th century, but it led to the theory of games in the 20th century. The first major book in game theory, published in 1944, was Theory of Games and Economic Behavior,byJohnvon Neumann (1903-1957) and Oskar Morgenstern (1902-1977). We will return to the contributions of Von Neumann and Morgenstern in Lesson 19, on uncertainty and expected utility. Agroupofpeople(orteams,firms,armies,countries)areinagame if their decision problems are interdependent, in the sense that the actions that all of them take influence the outcomes for everyone. Game theory is the study of games; it can also be called interactive decision theory. Many real-life interactions can be viewed as games. Obviously football, soccer, and baseball games are games.Butsoaretheinteractionsofduopolists,thepoliticalcampaignsbetweenparties before an election, and the interactions of armed forces and countries. Even some interactions between animal or plant species in nature can be modeled as games. In fact, game theory has been used in many different fields in recent decades, including economics, political science, psychology, sociology, computer science, and biology. This brief lesson is not meant to replace a formal course in game theory; it is only an in- troduction.
    [Show full text]
  • Prisoners of Reason Game Theory and Neoliberal Political Economy
    C:/ITOOLS/WMS/CUP-NEW/6549131/WORKINGFOLDER/AMADAE/9781107064034PRE.3D iii [1–28] 11.8.2015 9:57PM Prisoners of Reason Game Theory and Neoliberal Political Economy S. M. AMADAE Massachusetts Institute of Technology C:/ITOOLS/WMS/CUP-NEW/6549131/WORKINGFOLDER/AMADAE/9781107064034PRE.3D iv [1–28] 11.8.2015 9:57PM 32 Avenue of the Americas, New York, ny 10013-2473, usa Cambridge University Press is part of the University of Cambridge. It furthers the University’s mission by disseminating knowledge in the pursuit of education, learning, and research at the highest international levels of excellence. www.cambridge.org Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781107671195 © S. M. Amadae 2015 This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published 2015 Printed in the United States of America A catalog record for this publication is available from the British Library. Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Amadae, S. M., author. Prisoners of reason : game theory and neoliberal political economy / S.M. Amadae. pages cm Includes bibliographical references and index. isbn 978-1-107-06403-4 (hbk. : alk. paper) – isbn 978-1-107-67119-5 (pbk. : alk. paper) 1. Game theory – Political aspects. 2. International relations. 3. Neoliberalism. 4. Social choice – Political aspects. 5. Political science – Philosophy. I. Title. hb144.a43 2015 320.01′5193 – dc23 2015020954 isbn 978-1-107-06403-4 Hardback isbn 978-1-107-67119-5 Paperback Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of URLs for external or third-party Internet Web sites referred to in this publication and does not guarantee that any content on such Web sites is, or will remain, accurate or appropriate.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 16 Oligopoly and Game Theory Oligopoly Oligopoly
    Chapter 16 “Game theory is the study of how people Oligopoly behave in strategic situations. By ‘strategic’ we mean a situation in which each person, when deciding what actions to take, must and consider how others might respond to that action.” Game Theory Oligopoly Oligopoly • “Oligopoly is a market structure in which only a few • “Figuring out the environment” when there are sellers offer similar or identical products.” rival firms in your market, means guessing (or • As we saw last time, oligopoly differs from the two ‘ideal’ inferring) what the rivals are doing and then cases, perfect competition and monopoly. choosing a “best response” • In the ‘ideal’ cases, the firm just has to figure out the environment (prices for the perfectly competitive firm, • This means that firms in oligopoly markets are demand curve for the monopolist) and select output to playing a ‘game’ against each other. maximize profits • To understand how they might act, we need to • An oligopolist, on the other hand, also has to figure out the understand how players play games. environment before computing the best output. • This is the role of Game Theory. Some Concepts We Will Use Strategies • Strategies • Strategies are the choices that a player is allowed • Payoffs to make. • Sequential Games •Examples: • Simultaneous Games – In game trees (sequential games), the players choose paths or branches from roots or nodes. • Best Responses – In matrix games players choose rows or columns • Equilibrium – In market games, players choose prices, or quantities, • Dominated strategies or R and D levels. • Dominant Strategies. – In Blackjack, players choose whether to stay or draw.
    [Show full text]
  • Nash Equilibrium
    Lecture 3: Nash equilibrium Nash equilibrium: The mathematician John Nash introduced the concept of an equi- librium for a game, and equilibrium is often called a Nash equilibrium. They provide a way to identify reasonable outcomes when an easy argument based on domination (like in the prisoner's dilemma, see lecture 2) is not available. We formulate the concept of an equilibrium for a two player game with respective 0 payoff matrices PR and PC . We write PR(s; s ) for the payoff for player R when R plays 0 s and C plays s, this is simply the (s; s ) entry the matrix PR. Definition 1. A pair of strategies (^sR; s^C ) is an Nash equilbrium for a two player game if no player can improve his payoff by changing his strategy from his equilibrium strategy to another strategy provided his opponent keeps his equilibrium strategy. In terms of the payoffs matrices this means that PR(sR; s^C ) ≤ P (^sR; s^C ) for all sR ; and PC (^sR; sC ) ≤ P (^sR; s^C ) for all sc : The idea at work in the definition of Nash equilibrium deserves a name: Definition 2. A strategy s^R is a best-response to a strategy sc if PR(sR; sC ) ≤ P (^sR; sC ) for all sR ; i.e. s^R is such that max PR(sR; sC ) = P (^sR; sC ) sR We can now reformulate the idea of a Nash equilibrium as The pair (^sR; s^C ) is a Nash equilibrium if and only ifs ^R is a best-response tos ^C and s^C is a best-response tos ^R.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is Local Optimality in Nonconvex-Nonconcave Minimax Optimization?
    What is Local Optimality in Nonconvex-Nonconcave Minimax Optimization? Chi Jin Praneeth Netrapalli University of California, Berkeley Microsoft Research, India [email protected] [email protected] Michael I. Jordan University of California, Berkeley [email protected] August 18, 2020 Abstract Minimax optimization has found extensive application in modern machine learning, in settings such as generative adversarial networks (GANs), adversarial training and multi-agent reinforcement learning. As most of these applications involve continuous nonconvex-nonconcave formulations, a very basic question arises—“what is a proper definition of local optima?” Most previous work answers this question using classical notions of equilibria from simultaneous games, where the min-player and the max-player act simultaneously. In contrast, most applications in machine learning, including GANs and adversarial training, correspond to sequential games, where the order of which player acts first is crucial (since minimax is in general not equal to maximin due to the nonconvex-nonconcave nature of the problems). The main contribution of this paper is to propose a proper mathematical definition of local optimality for this sequential setting—local minimax—as well as to present its properties and existence results. Finally, we establish a strong connection to a basic local search algorithm—gradient descent ascent (GDA)—under mild conditions, all stable limit points of GDA are exactly local minimax points up to some degenerate points. 1 Introduction arXiv:1902.00618v3 [cs.LG] 15 Aug 2020 Minimax optimization refers to problems of two agents—one agent tries to minimize the payoff function f : X × Y ! R while the other agent tries to maximize it.
    [Show full text]
  • Game Theory: Basic Concepts and Terminology
    Leigh Tesfatsion 29 December 2019 Game Theory: Basic Concepts and Terminology A GAME consists of: • a collection of decision-makers, called players; • the possible information states of each player at each decision time; • the collection of feasible moves (decisions, actions, plays,...) that each player can choose to make in each of his possible information states; • a procedure for determining how the move choices of all the players collectively determine the possible outcomes of the game; • preferences of the individual players over these possible out- comes, typically measured by a utility or payoff function. 1 EMPLOYER CD C (40,40) (10,60) WORKER D (60,10) (20,20) Illustrative Modeling of a Work-Site Interaction as a \Prisoner's Dilemma Game" D = Defect (Shirk) C = Cooperate (Work Hard), (P1,P2) = (Worker Payoff, Employer Payoff) 2 A PURE STRATEGY for a player in a particular game is a complete contingency plan, i.e., a plan describing what move that player should take in each of his possible information states. A MIXED STRATEGY for a player i in a particular game is a probability distribution defined over the collection Si of player i's feasible pure strategy choices. That is, a mixed strategy assigns a nonnegative probability Prob(s) to each pure strategy s in Si, with X Prob(s) = 1 : (1) s2Si EXPOSITIONAL NOTE: For simplicity, the remainder of these brief notes will develop defi- nitions in terms of pure strategies; the unqualified use of \strategy" will always refer to pure strategy. Extension to mixed strategies is conceptually straightforward. 3 ONE-STAGE SIMULTANEOUS-MOVE N-PLAYER GAME: • The game is played just once among N players.
    [Show full text]
  • Nash Equilibrium and Mechanism Design ✩ ∗ Eric Maskin A,B, a Institute for Advanced Study, United States B Princeton University, United States Article Info Abstract
    Games and Economic Behavior 71 (2011) 9–11 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Games and Economic Behavior www.elsevier.com/locate/geb Commentary: Nash equilibrium and mechanism design ✩ ∗ Eric Maskin a,b, a Institute for Advanced Study, United States b Princeton University, United States article info abstract Article history: I argue that the principal theoretical and practical drawbacks of Nash equilibrium as a Received 23 December 2008 solution concept are far less troublesome in problems of mechanism design than in most Available online 18 January 2009 other applications of game theory. © 2009 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. JEL classification: C70 Keywords: Nash equilibrium Mechanism design Solution concept A Nash equilibrium (called an “equilibrium point” by John Nash himself; see Nash, 1950) of a game occurs when players choose strategies from which unilateral deviations do not pay. The concept of Nash equilibrium is far and away Nash’s most important legacy to economics and the other behavioral sciences. This is because it remains the central solution concept—i.e., prediction of behavior—in applications of game theory to these fields. As I shall review below, Nash equilibrium has some important shortcomings, both theoretical and practical. I will argue, however, that these drawbacks are far less troublesome in problems of mechanism design than in most other applications of game theory. 1. Solution concepts Game-theoretic solution concepts divide into those that are noncooperative—where the basic unit of analysis is the in- dividual player—and those that are cooperative, where the focus is on coalitions of players. John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern themselves viewed the cooperative part of game theory as more important, and their seminal treatise, von Neumann and Morgenstern (1944), devoted fully three quarters of its space to cooperative matters.
    [Show full text]
  • Microeconomics 2. Game Theory
    Microeconomics - 2.1 Strategic form games Description idsds Nash Rationalisability Correlated eq Microeconomics 2. Game Theory Alex Gershkov http://www.econ2.uni-bonn.de/gershkov/gershkov.htm 21. November 2007 1 / 41 Microeconomics - 2.1 Strategic form games Description idsds Nash Rationalisability Correlated eq Strategic form games 1.a Describing a game in strategic form 1.b Iterated deletion of strictly dominated strategies 1.c Nash equilibrium and examples 1.d Mixed strategies 1.e Existence of Nash equilibria 1.f Rationilazability 1.g Correlated equilibrium 2 / 41 Microeconomics - 2.1 Strategic form games Description idsds Nash Rationalisability Correlated eq 1.a Describing a game in strategic form Example: Entry game 1. 2 ice cream vendors decide whether or not to open an ice cream stand in a particular street 2. the decision is taken without observing the other vendor’s action 3. if only one stand is opened, this vendor earns $ 3 (the other vendor earns zero) 4. if both stands open, they share profits and earn $ 1.5 each 3 / 41 Microeconomics - 2.1 Strategic form games Description idsds Nash Rationalisability Correlated eq 1.a Describing a game in strategic form Let’s use a matrix to organise this information entry no entry entry 1.5,1.5 3,0 no entry 0,3 0,0 we use the following conventions 1. rows contain vendor 1’s decisions, columns contain vendor 2’s decisions 2. each outcome of the game is located in one cell of the matrix 3. outcomes (payoffs, profits) are given in expected utility in the form (u1, u2).
    [Show full text]
  • Volume 8 Issue 8+9 2020
    COSMOS + TAXIS Justice in the City: The history of ideas offers many examples of “ideal” solu- tions to real or perceived problems which generated much Georgist Insights initial enthusiasm but turned out to be disappointing in the end. Henry George (1839-1897) was an original thinker whose and their Limits economic analyses and suggestions for reforming the taxation system should be of interest to classical liberals considering that he was a firm believer in the virtues of free markets. This is a point I elaborate upon further below. But the conviction LAURENT DOBUZINSKIS he and his follower held that they had found the path toward abolishing poverty proved to be untenable. This is not to say Web: https://www.sfu.ca/politics/people/ profiles/dobuzins.html that his ideas ought to be dismissed and, in fact, they are be- ing rediscovered. The trend began quite a few years back in the academic community and by now the literature on Geor- gist idea is quite voluminous and still growing (without mak- ing any claim of this being an exhaustive list, see Backhaus 1997; Blaug 2000; Andelson 2003 and 2004; Bryson 2011; Nell 2019; see also many articles in the American Journal of Eco- nomics and Sociology). More recently, George’s land value tax has become an almost obligatory reference in commentaries (Bess 2018; Neklason 2019) about the extraordinary rise in the price of land in global cities such as New York, San Francisco, London, Toronto or Vancouver, where lots in practically any neighbourhood have reached prices that would have been un- imaginable two or three decades ago, making the purchase of a detached house out of reach for even well-off households.1 But this intellectual curiosity in unlikely to have much of an impact on policy-making beyond a few local initiatives.
    [Show full text]
  • John Von Neumann's Work in the Theory of Games and Mathematical Economics
    JOHN VON NEUMANN'S WORK IN THE THEORY OF GAMES AND MATHEMATICAL ECONOMICS H. W. KUHN AND A. W. TUCKER Of the many areas of mathematics shaped by his genius, none shows more clearly the influence of John von Neumann than the Theory of Games. This modern approach to problems of competition and cooperation was given a broad foundation in his superlative paper of 1928 [A].1 In scope and youthful vigor this work can be compared only to his papers of the same period on the axioms of set theory and the mathematical foundations of quantum mechanics. A decade later, when the Austrian economist Oskar Morgenstern came to Princeton, von Neumann's interest in the theory was reawakened. The result of their active and intensive collaboration during the early years of World War II was the treatise Theory of games and economic behavior [D], in which the basic structure of the 1928 paper is elaborated and extended. Together, the paper and treatise contain a remarkably complete outline of the subject as we know it today, and every writer in the field draws in some measure upon concepts which were there united into a coherent theory. The crucial innovation of von Neumann, which was to be both the keystone of his Theory of Games and the central theme of his later research in the area, was the assertion and proof of the Minimax Theorem. Ideas of pure and randomized strategies had been intro­ duced earlier, especially by Êmile Borel [3]. However, these efforts were restricted either to individual examples or, at best, to zero-sum two-person games with skew-symmetric payoff matrices.
    [Show full text]
  • Coalitional Rationalizability*
    Coalitional Rationalizability∗ Attila Ambrus This Version: September 2005 Abstract This paper investigates how groups or coalitions of players can act in their collective interest in non-cooperative normal form games even if equilibrium play is not assumed. The main idea is that each member of a coalition will confine play to a subset of their strategies if it is in their mutual interest to do so. An iterative procedure of restrictions is used to define a non-cooperative solution concept, the set of coalitionally rational- izable strategies. The procedure is analogous to iterative deletion of never best response strategies, but operates on implicit agreements by different coalitions. The solution set is a nonempty subset of the rationalizable strategies. ∗I thank Dilip Abreu for support and extremely valuable comments at all stages of writingthispaper.Iwouldalsoliketothank Drew Fudenberg, Faruk Gul, Wolfgang Pesendorfer, Ariel Rubinstein and Marciano Siniscalchi for useful comments and dis- cussions. Finally, I would like to thank Eddie Dekel, Haluk Ergin, Erica Field, Jozsef Molnar, Wojciech Oszlewski, Hugo Sonnenschein, Andrea Wilson, seminar participants at various universities for useful comments. 1 I. Introduction The main solution concept in noncooperative game theory, Nash equilibrium, requires stability only with respect to individual deviations by players. It does not take into account the possibility that groups of players might coordinate their moves, in order to achieve an outcome that is better for all of them. There have been several attempts to incorporate this consideration into the theory of noncooperative games, starting with the pioneering works of Schelling [1960] and Aumann [1959]. The latter offered strong Nash equilibrium, the first for- mal solution concept in noncooperative game theory that takes into account the interests of coalitions.
    [Show full text]
  • Determinacy for Infinite Games With
    Determinacy for in¯nite games with more than two players with preferences Benedikt LÄowe Institute for Logic, Language and Computation, Universiteit van Amsterdam, Plantage Muidergracht 24, 1018 TV Amsterdam, The Netherlands, [email protected] Abstract We discuss in¯nite zero-sum perfect-information games with more than two players. They are not determined in the traditional sense, but as soon as you ¯x a preference function for the players and assume common knowledge of rationality and this preference function among the players, you get determinacy for open and closed payo® sets. 2000 AMS Mathematics Subject Classi¯cation. 91A06 91A10 03B99 03E99. Keywords. Perfect Information Games, Coalitions, Preferences, Determinacy Ax- ioms, Common Knowledge, Rationality, Gale-Stewart Theorem, Labellings 1 Introduction The theory of in¯nite two-player games is connected to the foundations of mathematics. Statements like \Every in¯nite two-player game with payo® set in the complexity class ¡ is determined, i.e., one of the two players has a winning strategy" 1 The author was partially ¯nanced by NWO Grant B 62-584 in the project Verza- melingstheoretische Modelvorming voor Oneindige Spelen van Imperfecte Infor- matie and by DFG Travel Grant KON 192/2003 LO 834/4-1. He would like to ex- tend his gratitude towards Johan van Benthem (Amsterdam), Boudewijn de Bruin (Amsterdam), Balder ten Cate (Amsterdam), Derrick DuBose (Las Vegas NV), Philipp Rohde (Aachen), and Merlijn Sevenster (Amsterdam) for discussions on many-player games. are called determinacy axioms (for two-player games). When we sup- plement the standard (Zermelo-Fraenkel) axiom system for mathematics with determinacy axioms, we get a surprisingly ¯ne calibration of very interesting logical systems.
    [Show full text]