Amartya Sen and the Math- Ematics of Collective Choice

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Amartya Sen and the Math- Ematics of Collective Choice RESEARCH I NEWS Amartya Sen and the Math­ traced back to the mathematical analysis of elections and committee decisions which ematics of Collective Choice started roughly two centuries ago. Various authors, including Charles Lutwidge Bhaskar Duua Dodgson (alias Lewis Carrol, the author of Alice in Wonderland) had discussed proper­ Sen's work on the causes offamines, gender dis­ ties of different voting systems with the aim crimination and social and economic issues deal­ of proving the superiority of one voting sys­ ing with upliftment of the poor is largely known. tem over another. However, he is better known among professional economists for his contributions in social choice Their interest in this line of research was theory. motivated by the following problem. Given the various individual preferences of mem­ AMARTYA Sen has been a very well-known bers of a society (or committee or collective), economist even amongst laypersons long be­ how do we arrive at a collective or social fore the decision of the Royal Swedish Acad­ choice between various options? Various vot­ emy to award him the 1998 Nobel Prize for ing methods are obviously ways of aggregat­ Economics. His fame has been largely due to ing individual preferences into a social deci­ his influential work on issues which are of sion. However, it was realized long ago that interest to all concerned citizens. Some ex­ the method of majority rule, which is per­ amples are: the causes of famines, gender haps the most common voting method, could discrimination, and more generally social and lead to inconsistencies of the following kind. economic issues dealing with the upliftment of the poor. Not for nothing has he been Example: Consider a committee N = (1,2,3) labelled the 'conscience-keeper' amongst which has to choose one option out of the economists. feasible setA = {a, b, c}. Suppose that the pre­ ferences of individuals in N are as follows: The social relevance of his less technical work cannot be overestimated. However, profes­ I : abc sional economists hold him in high esteem 2: b c a mainly because of his theoretical contribu­ 3: cab tions in social choice theory and the related areas of measurement of inequality and pov­ (Here, preferences are indicated by the order erty. The purpose of this essay is to provide a from left to right; so, 1 prefers a to b to c, and brief introduction to social choice theory for so on.) the non-economist, focusing on Sen's contri­ If majority rule is used to derive the commi­ butions. ttee's (binary) preference relation over pairs The origins of social choice theory can be of alternatives, then a is preferred to b since I R-E-S-O-N-A-N-C-E--I-J-u-ne--2-0-0-0--------------~-------------------------------- RESEARCH I NEWS and 3 prefer a to b, and only 2 prefers b to a. Similarly, the committee must prefer b to c and c to a. Hence, there is no obvious 'best' Let 9\ be the set of all possible orderings choice for the committee since the commi­ over A. ttee's preferences cycle over {a, b, c}. Definition: An Arrow social welfare function The birth of modern social choice theory is is a mappingf:9i n --t R. due to Kenneth Arrow, the Nobel Laureate The interpretation is that an Arrow social for Economics in 1971. In what has been welfare function is a procedure which maps rather inappropriately named the 'general every logically possible n-tuple of individual possibility theorem', Arrow showed that ev­ preferences into a social preference ordering. ery 'reasonable' method of aggregating indi­ It will be convenient to use the following vidual preferences to a social preference or­ notation in the subsequent discussion. Given dering suffered from the same problem of , any n-tuple of individual preferences (Rp R 2 inconsistency associated with the majority ... ,Rn) and an Arrow social welfare function rule. Here is a brief description of what has f, let us use R E 9\ to denote the social been called the Arrowian framework. preference orderingf(Rl' R 2, ... ,Rn). Simi­ larly, R' will denote the social preference Let N be a finite set of individuals, with IN I orderingJtR'p R' 2' ... , R'n)' Just as Pi is used = n ~ 2, andA be a set of feasible alternatives to denote the asymmetric factor of Ri' let us or options with IA I ~ 3. I will assume that A use P and P' to denote the asymmetric is finite, purely for heuristic convenience. However, much of the subsequent discus­ factors Rand R'. sion depends crucially on the assumption Arrow imposed the following relatively mild that N is finite. Each individual in N has a conditions onf preference ordering Ri over A. A binary rela­ tion B on a set X is called an ordering if (i) for Condition 1 (Independence of irrelevant alterna­ tives): For any two n-tuples (Rp R , .•. , Rn) all x,y E X, xBy andyBx (the connectedness 2 and (R'pR'2' ... ,R'n) in the domain off, and condition); and (ii) for any x, y, Z E X, xBy and yBz implies xBz (transitivity). Let us any pair of options x and y such that xRjY if and only if xR'j y, we must have xRy if and interpret R j as the 'weak' preference relation 'at least as good as'. With each Ri is associated only if xR'y. a strict preference relation Pi) the so-called Condition I says that the social preference asymmetric factor of R i, which stands for between any pair x andy should depend only 'strictly better than'; namely xPiy for x,Y E A on the individual preferences between x ifxR.y but notyR.x. The symmetric factor of ! ! andy. 1., R.,t denoted t stands for the relation 'is in- different to'. So, for any x,y E A,xIiy holds if Condition D (Non-dictatorship): There is no ________AAA~AA,~-- ____ 98 ~v V VV V v RESONANCE I June 2000 RESEARCH I NEWS i E N such that for all CRp R z' ... ,Rn) E 9\n, Much of modern social choice theory can be for all pairs x andy inA,xPy holds whenever viewed as attempts to see whether consistent xPjy. decision-making is possible if the original conditions are relaxed. Sen has been one of Condition D rules out the existence of an the leading researchers in this area. individual whose preference dictates social preference between every pair of alternatives. For instance, it can be argued that consistent decision-making is possible even when the Condition P (Pareto): For any CRp R z' ... , Rn) social preference relation is not an ordering. E 9\n and x,y E A if xPjy for all i then xPy. What is required for consistent social choice Arrow Impossibility Theorem: There is no Ar­ is the existence of an alternative which is the row social welfare function satisfying condi­ 'best' in the feasible set in terms of the social tions I, D and P. preference relation. So, let R be any social preference relation, and A' ~ A. Define the Remark: Notice that the restriction that A choice set CCA',R) = {x E A' IxRy for ally E contains at least three elements is crucial. For A'}. That is, the choice set consists of the if A contains only two elements, then major­ pairwise-best elements inA' according to the ity rule satisfies all of Arrow's conditions. binary relation R. Indeed, all sensible voting rules will yield the same social preference relation in this case. Now, consider the notion of ' quasi-transitiv­ The reason why the impossibility theorem ity', which means that the strict preference requires A to contain at least three alterna­ relation is transitive. Formally, tives is that transitivity becomes a vacuous Definition: The binary relation R is quasi­ concept if there are only two elements. transitive over A iffor x,y,z EA,xPy andyPz This theorem posed aformal challenge to the implies xPz. possibility of arriving at consistent social de­ Now, the set of socially optimal outcomes cisions in a democracy. A 'democratic' gov­ can be taken to be the choice set correspond­ ernment should be responsive to the com­ ing to the social preference relation R, and mon will of its citizens. Hence, it will want to this set will be non-empty if R is connected evaluate various policy options from the and quasi-transitive. standpoint of the 'representative' citizen, where the representative citizen's preference It can be seen that given an n-tuple CRt' ... , ordering combines or aggregates the views of Rn) of individual preference orderings of the all the citizens in the society. Unfortunately, n members, we can define a quasi-transitive one interpretation of the Arrow theorem is social preference relation by the so-called that the representative citizen's preferences Pareto extension rule: given x, YEA, xPy if cannot be represented as an ordering. and only if xPjy for all i = 1, ... , n. -RE-S-O-N-A-N-C-E--I-J-u-ne---20-0-0--------------~-------------------------------99- RESEARCH I NEWS The Pareto-extension rule declares the alter­ plausible assumptions can then be used to native x to be socially preferred to y only if restrict the domain of the aggregation proce­ everyone in the society prefers x to y. This dure. rule, and more generally relaxation of the requirement of transitivity of the social pref­ One preference restriction which has been erence to quasi-transitivity, provides a route used in a number of applications is called to escape the Arrow impossibility result.
Recommended publications
  • Optimal Taxation and the Equal-Sacrifice Social Welfare
    Optimal Taxation and the Equal-Sacrice Social Welfare Function Kristoer Berg and Paolo G. Piacquadio October 21, 2019 (Preliminary and incomplete: any comment is welcome!) Abstract A prominent principle of fairness in taxation is the equal-sacrice principle: the tax burden ought to be shared so that each tax-payer makes the same sacrice. J.S. Mill (1848) immediately realized that equality of sacrice, like other standards of perfection, cannot be completely realized: in second-best settings, it would lead to inecient policies. In this paper, we propose and axiomatically characterize a family of welfare criteria that captures both the fairness principle of equal sacrice as well as eciency concerns. Society ought to maximize the sum of specic indices of each individual's well-being, which depend on how society measures sacrice. We then apply the criterion to the standard Mirrlees optimal taxation problem and highlight how the second-best tax implications of the equal-sacrice social welfare function dier from those of utilitarianism. JEL: D60, D63, H21, H23, I38. Keywords: equal-sacrice principle; optimal income taxation; welfare criterion. 1 Introduction The equal-sacrice principle is a central principle of fairness in taxation. Following Mill (1848), the equal- sacrice principle requires sharing the tax burden so that each tax-payer makes the same sacrice. This principle has a strong intuitive appeal and is supported by a large share of the population (Weinzierl, 2014). Unfortunately, the principle has shown evasive for the purpuse of characterizing the optimal income tax schedule. Two issues seem crucial. The rst relates to the measurement of sacrice (see Musgrave, 1959).
    [Show full text]
  • Social Choice
    SOCIAL CHOICE Lecture 2 14.42/14.420 Hunt Allcott MIT Department of Economics II. Social Choice • A. Introduction and examples • Two basic questions in environmental economics are: • What is the right balance between environmental protection and use? (we focus on this question for the next few lectures) • How do we induce economic agents to use the environment in a fashion that we have determined is desirable? • Some specific questions: • How much land should be set aside to protect endangered species of plants and animals? • What level of air pollution should be acceptable? • The key issue in all of these questions is that they are societal decisions. They reflect many individuals’ preferences, some of whom care deeply about the environment and some who don’t care at all. • How can we translate diverse individual preferences regarding the environment into a group or societal choice? • We need to find a way to translate every individual’s opinion, regardless of how strange it may seem, into the appropriate environmental policy. II. Social Choice • Agenda for Today: • Examples of social choices • Classifying individual preferences • Different types of individual utility functions • Aggregating individual preferences to group decisions • Different types of social welfare functions • Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem • There is no perfect way of voting • Sustainability • Question: Why are these “social choices” instead of “individual choices”? • i.e. why is this topic not in micro/consumer theory? II. Social Choice • 3 examples: • Air Pollution in Santiago, Chile • Severe air pollution; diesel bases are a big problem. • Question: should we force bus owners to pay for emission control? • Reduction in diesel will raise cost of transport.
    [Show full text]
  • Welfare Economy
    Welfare Economy Chapter 1 Welfare, an individual and collective concept We present what is welfare for economists, we elaborate the bedrock of normative economics Winter 2019 Université de Tours - A. Chassagnon Welfare Economics Welfare economics aims to define and to measure social welfare, and to provide evaluations of public policies. A typical question : between different economic situations, more precisely, between different resource allocations, which is the best ? It follows that a deep critical analysis of the instruments is required in that field. Individual and collective welfare First, the welfare should be defined at the individual level. There are many measures It could be a declarative measure : how do you feel your welfare is ? It could be the utility of consumption : What bundle do you prefer ? Second, the welfare should be defined at the collective level There are many measures From a qualitative point of vue, definition of the Pareto optimal allocations From a quantitative point of vue, consider weighted average of the utilities Vocabulary All of those words should be reviewed (in textbooks or in wikipedia) • declarative measure • Bundle (of goods) • weighted average • qualitative measure • quantitative measure • Welfare • Utility function • Allocation (of resources) Map of the talk 1) Individual welfare Declarative welfare, Happiness, Utility functions Time and Inter-country comparisons 2) Collective welfare Pareto optimal (or efficient) allocations Social Welfare Functions and utilities 1a. Individual welfare Declarative welfare, Happiness, Happiness Given its very nature, reported happiness is subjective. It is difficult to compare one person’s happiness with another’s It can be especially difficult to compare happiness across cultures One concern has always been the accuracy and reliability of people’s responses to happiness surveys.
    [Show full text]
  • Social Choice Josh Cohen 1. the Voting Paradox the Puzzles in The
    Social Choice Josh Cohen 1. The Voting Paradox The puzzles in the area of social choice begin with the paradox of voting. So suppose we as a group are trying to decide when the course should meet: 9, 10, or 11. Suppose that choosing rationally (whether for a group or person) is choosing the best alternative from a consistently ordered set of feasible alternatives, and that the group ranking is fixed by majority support: A is ranked higher than B by the group iff A is ranked higher than B by a majority of group members. Assume finally that consistency is a matter of transitivity of “better than”: that if A is better than B and B is better than C, then A is better than C (we will see later that there are ways to weaken this notion). Assume that we divide into three groups of equal size: Best Second Worst I 9 10 11 II 11 9 10 III 10 11 9 Lets ask how the group ranks the three possibilities, using majority rule as the procedure for group ranking: 9 beats 10, 10 beats 11, and 11 beats 9. Group rationality (i.e. transitivity) requires that 9 beat 11. But 11 is a majority rule winner over 9. In fact matters are worse: putting aside the failure of transitivity, notice that each alternative loses to another alternative. Thus we have not just a failure of transitivity, but further a failure of acyclicity, which is an even more minimal condition of rational decision: Acyclicity: If x1Px2Px3...xn-1Pxn, then not xnPx1 A violation of acyclicity means that the feasible set contains no best element.
    [Show full text]
  • Interpersonal Comparisons Without a Social Welfare Function
    NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES THE INEQUALITY DEFLATOR: INTERPERSONAL COMPARISONS WITHOUT A SOCIAL WELFARE FUNCTION Nathaniel Hendren Working Paper 20351 http://www.nber.org/papers/w20351 NATIONAL BUREAU OF ECONOMIC RESEARCH 1050 Massachusetts Avenue Cambridge, MA 02138 July 2014 I am deeply indebted to conversations with Louis Kaplow for the inspiration behind this paper, and to Sarah Abraham, Alex Bell, Alex Olssen, and Evan Storms for excellent research assistance. I also thank Daron Acemoglu, Raj Chetty, Amy Finkelstein, Ben Lockwood, Henrik Kleven, Patrick Kline, Jim Poterba, Emmanuel Saez, Matthew Weinzierl, Glen Weyl, Ivan Werning, and Floris Zoutman, along with seminar participants at Berkeley, Harvard, MIT, Michigan, and Stanford for very helpful comments. The opinions expressed in this paper are those of the author alone and do not necessarily reflect the views of the Internal Revenue Service or the U.S. Treasury Department. This work is a component of a larger project examining the effects of tax expenditures on the budget deficit and economic activity, and this paper in particular provides a general characterization of the welfare impact of changes in tax expenditures relative to changes in tax rates (illustrated in Section 6). The empirical results derived from tax data that are reported in this paper are drawn from the SOI Working Paper "The Economic Impacts of Tax Expenditures: Evidence from Spatial Variation across the U.S.", approved under IRS contract TIRNO-12-P-00374. The views expressed herein are those of the author and do not necessarily reflect the views of the National Bureau of Economic Research. NBER working papers are circulated for discussion and comment purposes.
    [Show full text]
  • Prioritarianism and Optimal Taxation Matti Tuomala1 Matthew Weinzierl2 December 31, 2020
    Prioritarianism and Optimal Taxation Matti Tuomala1 Matthew Weinzierl2 December 31, 2020 Note: This text is forthcoming as Chapter 4 in Prioritarianism in Practice, Matthew Adler and Ole Norheim (editors), Cambridge University Press. Abstract Prioritarianism has been at the center of the formal approach to optimal tax theory since its modern starting point in Mirrlees (1971), but most theorists’ use of it is motivated by tractability rather than explicit normative reasoning. We characterize analytically and numerically the implications of a more explicit use of prioritarianism in optimal tax theory. We also examine prevailing tax policies and surveys on tax preferences to gauge the influence of prioritarianism in practice. We conclude that optimal policy is highly sensitive to many key modeling choices and parameter assumptions, and these choices interact in complicated ways, but that a substantial shift in policy results if the social objective moves from utilitarian to prioritarian. When looking at existing policy and preferences, we find only limited evidence of prioritarian reasoning. We conclude with suggestions on the future of prioritarianism in optimal tax theory. Keywords Prioritarianism, Optimal Taxation, Utilitarianism, Redistribution, Inverse-optimum In this chapter, we trace out the implications of adopting prioritarianism as the normative standard for the design of labor income taxation, and we examine the extent to which prevailing tax policies fit with those implications. Labor income taxation embodies, perhaps more directly and with broader reach than any other policy decision, social judgments on the proper role of government and distribution of economic resources.3 The design of "optimal" taxation therefore depends critically on what we assume optimality entails.
    [Show full text]
  • Extra-Welfarism
    This is a repository copy of Welfarism vs. extra-welfarism. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/3789/ Article: Brouwer, Werner B. F., Culyer, Anthony J., van Exel, N. Job A. et al. (1 more author) (2008) Welfarism vs. extra-welfarism. Journal of health economics. pp. 325-338. ISSN 0167-6296 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jhealeco.2007.07.003 Reuse Items deposited in White Rose Research Online are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved unless indicated otherwise. They may be downloaded and/or printed for private study, or other acts as permitted by national copyright laws. The publisher or other rights holders may allow further reproduction and re-use of the full text version. This is indicated by the licence information on the White Rose Research Online record for the item. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ promoting access to White Rose research papers Universities of Leeds, Sheffield and York http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ This is an author produced version of a paper published in Journal of Health Economics. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/3789/ Published paper Brouwer, W.B.F., Culyer, A.J., van Exel, N.J.A. and Rutten, F.F.H. (2008) Welfarism vs. extra-welfarism, Journal of Health Economics, Volume 27 (2), 325 – 338.
    [Show full text]
  • An Economics-Based Rationale for the Rawlsian Social Welfare Program
    A Service of Leibniz-Informationszentrum econstor Wirtschaft Leibniz Information Centre Make Your Publications Visible. zbw for Economics Stark, Oded Working Paper An economics-based rationale for the Rawlsian social welfare program University of Tübingen Working Papers in Business and Economics, No. 137 Provided in Cooperation with: University of Tuebingen, Faculty of Economics and Social Sciences, School of Business and Economics Suggested Citation: Stark, Oded (2020) : An economics-based rationale for the Rawlsian social welfare program, University of Tübingen Working Papers in Business and Economics, No. 137, University of Tübingen, Faculty of Economics and Social Sciences, Tübingen, http://dx.doi.org/10.15496/publikation-48257 This Version is available at: http://hdl.handle.net/10419/224660 Standard-Nutzungsbedingungen: Terms of use: Die Dokumente auf EconStor dürfen zu eigenen wissenschaftlichen Documents in EconStor may be saved and copied for your Zwecken und zum Privatgebrauch gespeichert und kopiert werden. personal and scholarly purposes. Sie dürfen die Dokumente nicht für öffentliche oder kommerzielle You are not to copy documents for public or commercial Zwecke vervielfältigen, öffentlich ausstellen, öffentlich zugänglich purposes, to exhibit the documents publicly, to make them machen, vertreiben oder anderweitig nutzen. publicly available on the internet, or to distribute or otherwise use the documents in public. Sofern die Verfasser die Dokumente unter Open-Content-Lizenzen (insbesondere CC-Lizenzen) zur Verfügung gestellt haben sollten, If the documents have been made available under an Open gelten abweichend von diesen Nutzungsbedingungen die in der dort Content Licence (especially Creative Commons Licences), you genannten Lizenz gewährten Nutzungsrechte. may exercise further usage rights as specified in the indicated licence.
    [Show full text]
  • Arrow's Theorem with a Fixed Feasible Alternative*
    Soc Choice Welfare (1987) 4:105-115 Social Choice .dWelfare © Springer-Verlag 1987 Arrow's Theorem with a Fixed Feasible Alternative* Allan Gibbard 1, Aanund Hylland 2, and John A. Weymark 3 1 Department of Philosophy, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, MI 48109, USA 2 Department of Economics, University of Oslo, P.O. Box 1095, Blindern, N-0317 Oslo, Norway 3 Department of Economics, University of British Columbia, Vancouver, B.C., Canada V6T 1Y2 Received June 4, 1986/Accepted in revised form January 15, 1987 Abstract. Arrow's Theorem, in its social choice function formulation, assumes that all nonempty finite subsets of the universal set of alternatives is potentially a feasible set. We demonstrate that the axioms in Arrow's Theorem, with weak Pareto strengthened to strong Pareto, are consistent if it is assumed that there is a prespecified alternative which is in every feasible set. We further show that if the collection of feasible sets consists of all subsets of alternatives containing a prespecified list of alternatives and if there are at least three additional alternatives not on this list, replacing nondictatorship by anonymity results in an impossibility theorem. 1. Introduction Arrow's [2] Impossibility Theorem is usually expressed in terms of social welfare functions; a social welfare function assigns a social preference ordering to each admissible profile of individual orderings of a set of alternatives. The theorem, though, can also be expressed in terms of social choice functions. A social choice function does the following: for each set of alternatives that might turn out to be feasible, and for each admissible preference profile, a social choice function specifies a nonempty subset of the feasible set - the choice set.
    [Show full text]
  • Arrow's Impossibility Theorem
    Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem: Two Simple Single-Profile Versions Brown University Department of Economics Working Paper Allan M. Feldman Department of Economics, Brown University Providence, RI 02912 USA [email protected] http://www.econ.brown.edu/fac/allan_feldman Roberto Serrano Department of Economics, Brown University and IMDEA-Social Sciences Providence, RI 02912 USA [email protected] http://www.econ.brown.edu/faculty/serrano This revision: March 5, 2008 Abstract In this paper we provide two simple new versions of Arrow’s impossibility theorem, in a model with only one preference profile. Both versions are transparent, requiring minimal mathematical sophistication. The first version assumes there are only two people in society, whose preferences are being aggregated; the second version assumes two or more people. Both theorems rely on assumptions about diversity of preferences, and we explore alternative notions of diversity at some length. Our first theorem also uses a neutrality assumption, commonly used in the literature; our second theorem uses a neutrality/monotonicity assumption, which is stronger and less commonly used. We provide examples to illustrate our points. Keywords: Arrow’s theorem, single-profile. JEL classifications: D60, D70, D71. Acknowledgements: We want to thank Kenneth Arrow for having suggested the questions that led us to write this paper. 1. Introduction. In 1950 Kenneth Arrow (1950, 1963) provided a striking answer to a basic abstract problem of democracy: how can the preferences of many individuals be aggregated into social preferences? The starkly negative answer, known as Arrow’s impossibility theorem, was that every conceivable aggregation method has some flaw. That is, a handful of reasonable-looking axioms, which one thinks an aggregation procedure should satisfy, lead to impossibility: the axioms are mutually inconsistent.
    [Show full text]
  • Economics 2450A: Public Economics Section 2: Introduction to Optimal Income Taxation
    Economics 2450A: Public Economics Section 2: Introduction to Optimal Income Taxation Matteo Paradisi September 18, 2016 In today’s section we will introduce the problem of optimal income taxation. We will set up the government problem and derive optimal taxes. We will study optimal linear tax rate, optimal top tax rate and the revenue maximizing tax rate. 1 The Income Taxation Problem Our goal for most of this class is to derive the properties of optimal taxes in di↵erent context. We will define the tax in a flexible way using the mathematical object T (z), where z is the income reported by the agent. The tax T (z) generates the retention function R (z)=z T (z). R (z) measures how much the agent can retain out of total income z. We denote transfers to− income z with T (z) so that the transfer T (0) to non-working individuals is the intercept of the retention function. − − If T (z) is di↵erentiable, T 0 (z)representsthemarginal tax rate. It measures how much the agent gets taxed out of one additional dollar of income. In order to study the extensive margin decision between working and remaining unemployed, we need T (z) T (0) to know the participation tax rate ⌧p = −z . It is the fraction of income that an agent pays in taxes when she moves from 0 income to z. 2 Taxation in a Model With No Behavioral Responses We start with a simple version of an optimal income taxation problem that ignores the labor supply response to taxation.
    [Show full text]
  • Can a Rawlsian and a Utilitarian Social Planner See Eye To
    ZEF-Discussion Papers on Development Policy No. 211 Oded Stark and Marcin Jakubek Can a concern for status reconcile diverse social welfare programs? Bonn, April 2016 The CENTER FOR DEVELOPMENT RESEARCH (ZEF) was established in 1995 as an international, interdisciplinary research institute at the University of Bonn. Research and teaching at ZEF address political, economic and ecological development problems. ZEF closely cooperates with national and international partners in research and development organizations. For information, see: www.zef.de. ZEF – Discussion Papers on Development Policy are intended to stimulate discussion among researchers, practitioners and policy makers on current and emerging development issues. Each paper has been exposed to an internal discussion within the Center for Development Research (ZEF) and an external review. The papers mostly reflect work in progress. The Editorial Committee of the ZEF – DISCUSSION PAPERS ON DEVELOPMENT POLICY includes Joachim von Braun (Chair), Christian Borgemeister, and Eva Youkhana. Tobias Wünscher is the Managing Editor of the series. Oded Stark and Marcin Jakubek, Can a concern for status reconcile diverse social welfare programs? ZEF – Discussion Papers on Development Policy No. 211, Center for Development Research, Bonn, April 2016, pp. 11. ISSN: 1436-9931 Published by: Zentrum für Entwicklungsforschung (ZEF) Center for Development Research Walter-Flex-Straße 3 D – 53113 Bonn Germany Phone: +49-228-73-1861 Fax: +49-228-73-1869 E-Mail: [email protected] www.zef.de The authors: Oded Stark, Center for Development Research (ZEF). Contact: [email protected] Marcin Jakubek, Polish Academy of Sciences. Contact: [email protected] Acknowledgements We are indebted to an anonymous referee for kind words and sound advice.
    [Show full text]