Luck Egalitarianism, Harshness, and the Rule of Rescue

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Luck Egalitarianism, Harshness, and the Rule of Rescue Luck egalitarianism, harshness, and the rule of rescue Nir Eyal Abstract Luck egalitarians consider it somewhat fairer when relative disadvantage results from the disadvantaged party’s own choice or fault—when it is “option luck” not “brute luck”. The most famous objection to luck egalitarianism is the harshness objection. It points out that when someone is at grave risk through their own choice or fault, refusing to rescue them on the ground that they are responsible for their own plight would, intuitively, be too harsh. A strong version of the objection adds that intuitively it is harsh even to weigh her personal responsibility for her plight against rescuing her. In defense of luck egalitarianism, I point out that grave risk is known to bring out the so-called “rule of rescue” mentality, and related biases. These biases incline us to deny that there is any sound reason against rescuing the person identified as at grave risk. That fact, I propose, provides an alternative causal account of our intuition that rescue is mandated and that considerations of personal responsibility against rescue would be harsh and inappropriate. In support of this alternative account, when the propriety of holding people responsible for avoidable risk raking is assessed outside immediate rescue situations, our intuitions are far more accepting of the relevance of personal responsibility for disadvantage, and hence, of luck egalitarianism. Background: Luck-egalitarianism, the harshness objection, and democratic equality According to luck egalitarianism,i When deciding whether or not justice (as opposed to charity) requires redistribution, the egalitarian asks if someone with a disadvantage could have 1 avoided it... If he could have avoided it, he has no claim to compensation, from an egalitarian point of view…ii A paramount objection to luck egalitarianism is that it endorses a harsh allocation of resources. Critics Marc Fleurbaey, Elizabeth Anderson, Dan Wikler, Sam Scheffler, and Norm Daniels accuse luck egalitarianism of supporting the harsh abandonment of reckless drivers who hit trees, of gluttons whose unhealthy diets lead to chronic disease, and of bons vivants whose taste for unprotected sex results in their infection (Fleurbaey 1995, Anderson 1999, Scheffler 2005, Wikler 2006, Daniels 2011). Elizabeth Anderson famously writes, Consider an uninsured driver who negligently makes an illegal turn that causes an accident with another car. Witnesses call the police, reporting who is at fault; the police transmit this information to emergency medical technicians. When they arrive at the scene and find that the driver at fault is uninsured, they leave him to die by the side of the road...iii The objection is that luck egalitarianism allows society to abandon the negligent (or “imprudent”, or “reckless”, as they are also called in this literature), say, for no special reason or in order to cut costs, to deter others from being negligent, or to stop the negligent from dumping their slack on others. Luck egalitarianism allegedly must say that society would be in its right, at least in terms of justice, if it abandoned them. Anderson and fellow critics of luck egalitarianism preempt some apologies on behalf of luck egalitarianism, according to which luck egalitarianism has the resources to justify rescuing negligent victims of bad option luck. For example, Anderson agrees that it is inexpedient to leave decisions on health coverage to ambulance drivers and emergency physicians. However, the expediency defense fails for harsh decisions made by hospital administrators and insurers. Likewise, the critics judge that abandoning negligent individuals would often penalize patients who have had an underprivileged upbringing, which generally correlates with lower medical compliance. But Fleurbaey, who had raised the harshness objection before Anderson did, was careful to emphasize that the victim he discussed “received a normal and balanced upbringing” (Fleurbaey 1995). Luck egalitarians have proposed a number of responses, most of which seek to clarify why they can consistently endorse a duty to save the imprudent. Pluralist luck egalitarians adduce our many other potential reasons to save the imprudent, such as our complementary (not alternative) reasons to satisfy people’s basic needs. In pluralist luck egalitarian Shlomi Segall’s words, “The 2 concern for basic needs… overrides luck egalitarian distributive justice and mandates meeting the basic medical needs of the prudent and the imprudent alike.”iv However, a sophisticated champion of the harshness objection could respond that intuition rebels against the implications of this position too. For example, an ambulance driver who saved only the prudent when there was a reckless driver and a backseat passenger and only one spot in the ambulance, rather than flip a coin, would intuitively act wrongly (compare Segall 2010, 71-72). Nor is abandoning the imprudent as such something that, intuitively, should even cross the minds of decent ambulance drivers or doctors. Ones who thought that the imprudent had lost their just claim to their services and should be aided out of sheer charitable concern for their basic medical needs would intuitively be guilty, not of making the wrong choice but of flawed background phenomenology. Anderson hints at this “strong version” of the harshness objection (as we may call this version) when she complains that on luck egalitarianism, the post office “can with justice turn away the guide dogs of faulty drivers who lost their sight in a car accident” (Anderson 1999, 296, added italics). Anderson and some other critics of luck-egalitarianism use its alleged harshness to motivate an alternative egalitarian theory, namely, democratic equality. That theory states: Negatively, egalitarians seek to abolish oppression—that is, forms of social relationship by which some people dominate, exploit, marginalize, demean, and inflict violence upon others… Positively, egalitarians seek a social order in which persons stand in relations of equality. They seek to live together in a democratic community, as opposed to a hierarchical one (Anderson 1999, 313). Democratic equality is said to be immune to the harshness objection because it guarantees “effective access to a package of capabilities sufficient for standing as an equal over the course of an entire life. It is not a starting-gate theory, in which people could lose their access to equal standing through bad option luck” (Anderson 1999, 319, and see also p. 328: “Democratic equality … guarantees a set of capabilities necessary to functioning as a free and equal citizen and avoiding oppression”). Remaining “capable of standing as an equal in civil society requires,” among other things, ambulatory services in the event of a car accident, regardless of the causes of disability; post office disabled access, regardless of its causes (Anderson 1999, 246); lung transplantation to overcome certain lung cancers regardless of their causes; and protection against other very bad brute or option luck. These rights to basic protection are inalienable because society has a duty to protect the standing of each member as a Kantian fundamental 3 equal. This right is as inalienable as are the freedoms from slavery and from any other violation of citizens’ Kantian dignity (Anderson 1999, 319). Put differently, Anderson argues that what is wrong with the alleged luck egalitarian denial of medical care to the neglectful is that it robs them of their capacity for full democratic participation in politics and civil society on equal terms, and that that capacity matters because Kantian dignity does. Daniels and Scheffler espouse the grounding in equal democratic status (Daniels 2011, Scheffler 2005). Daniels adds that such denial of medical care also robs the neglectful of their fair share of opportunity, a related fundamental right (Daniels 2007, 2011). Even Luck egalitarian Shlomi Segall concedes that democratic equality “easily averts the abandonment objection”; he merely insists that, with moral acrobatics, luck egalitarians can avert that objection as well (Segall 2010, but see Segall forthcoming). Like Segall, I am sympathetic to pluralist luck egalitarianism. But I take a more radical stance against the harshness objection than he does. The three sections of this chapter will argue, respectively: 1. Harshness objections arise for democratic equality as well. 2. A central reason why either luck egalitarian recommendations or democratic egalitarian ones seem too harsh may well be the potentially distracting influence of the unrelated and irrelevant “rule of rescue” mentality. That mentality, which I shall lay out, makes us not only prioritize greatly individuals who are identified as being in great danger, but also, crucially, “deeply exclude” (as I shall put it) any reasons to de-prioritize them, sound or unsound. I shall also explain the notion of deep exclusion. 3. Indeed, outside immediate rescue situations, the force of the harshness objection wanes and personal responsibility intuitively feels much more relevant. I shall conclude that, in truth, personal responsibility always matters somewhat, but that this truth is sometimes too harsh for us to admit—even to ourselves. 1. Harshness objections to democratic equality In its own ways, democratic equality is harsh as well, in some ways more than luck egalitarianism. Elsewhere I laid out several ways in which it is harsh, but let me feature one—its harshness toward identified victims. Anderson cites
Recommended publications
  • BROCHER SUMMER ACADEMY in GLOBAL POPULATION HEALTH 2010 Geneva, Switzerland, 12Th July - 16Th July
    BROCHER SUMMER ACADEMY IN GLOBAL POPULATION HEALTH 2010 Geneva, Switzerland, 12th July - 16th July Measurement and Ethical Evaluation of Health Inequalities Deadline May 7th 2010 Application form is available at : http://www.brocher.ch/pages/programme.asp Organized by THE BROCHER FOUNDATION, THE HARVARD UNIVERSITY PROGRAM IN ETHICS & HEALTH, & THE UNIVERSITY OF GENEVA INSTITUTE FOR BIOMEDICAL ETHICS SUMMER SCHOOL PROGRAMME The Brocher Summer Academy in Global Population Health aims to introduce graduate students and researchers to population-level bioethics. The Academy hopes to stimulate high-level academic work on ethical issues in population health and global health and to bring ethical dimensions of population and global health to the attention of policy makers and practitioners. The Academy’s seminars will draw on the resources of many disciplines to identify the key ethical issues, and to apply a variety of problem-solving strategies to their resolution. Ethical analysis and reasoning thus joins the methods of the social and biological sciences in contributing to the global project of relieving the burden of disease. The 2010 Academy in Global Population Health will focus on “Measurement and Ethical Evaluation of health Inequalities”. A substantive focus will be given to the following topics: • How should we rank distributions of health across populations in order of inequality? • What are the ethical implications of using different measures of health inequalities? • Which -if any- of the common measures of economic inequality are informative when applied to health? • Are all health inequalities morally objectionable or unjust? Should we measure health inequalities across groups, across individuals, or both? · What priority should reduction in health inequalities have among prominent goals of health policy? SPECIAL EVENT, BROCHER LECTURE Thursday, July 15th Measuring health inequality and health inequity Prof.
    [Show full text]
  • Johann Frick
    JOHANN FRICK Department of Philosophy (609) 258-9494 (office) 212 1879 Hall (857) 399-5709 (cell) Princeton University (609) 258-1502 (fax) Princeton, New Jersey 08544- [email protected] 1006 AREAS OF SPECIALIZATION Normative Ethics; Practical Ethics (including Bioethics); Political Philosophy. AREAS OF COMPETENCE Metaethics; Philosophy of Law; Metaphysics; Philosophy of Action; Wittgenstein. EMPLOYMENT Feb 2015 – Assistant Professor in the Department of Philosophy and the Present Center for Human Values, Princeton University. Feb 2014 – Instructor in the Department of Philosophy and the Center for Jan 2015 Human Values, Princeton University. EDUCATION 2008 - 2014 Ph.D. in Philosophy, Harvard University. • Dissertation: “Making People Happy, Not Making Happy People: A Defense of the Asymmetry Intuition in Population Ethics”; Committee: T.M. Scanlon, Frances Kamm, Derek Parfit. 2005 - 2008 BPhil degree in Philosophy, Merton College, Oxford University. • Distinction in both the written examinations and the BPhil thesis. • BPhil thesis: “Morality and the Problem of Foreseeable Non- Compliance”; advisor: Derek Parfit. • Specialization in Moral Philosophy (tutor: Ralph Wedgwood); Political Philosophy (tutors: Joseph Raz and John Tasioulas); Wittgenstein (tutor: Stephen Mulhall). 2006 - 2007 Visiting student at the École Normale Supérieure (ENS) in Paris. • Courses and seminars at the ENS, the Institut Jean Nicod, and the Collège de France; tutor: François Recanati. 2002 - 2005 BA (Hons.) degree in Philosophy, Politics & Economics, St. John’s College, Oxford University. • First Class Honours in the Final Examinations (June 2005). • Distinction in the Preliminary Examination (June 2003). PUBLICATIONS “Future Persons and Victimless Wrongdoing” in Markus Rüther and Sebastian Muders (eds.), Aufsätze zur Philosophie Derek Parfits (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, forthcoming).
    [Show full text]
  • Making Fair Choices on the Path to Universal Health Coverage: Applying Principles to Difficult Cases Article (Accepted Version) (Refereed)
    A. Voorhoeve, T. Tan-Torres Edejer, L. Kapiriri, O. Frithjof Norheim, J. Snowden, O. Basenya, D. Bayarsaikhan, I. Chentaf, N. Eyal, A. Folsom, R. H. Tun Hussein, C. Morales, F. Ostmann, T. Ottersen, P. Prakongsai, C. Saenz, K. Saleh, A. Sommanustweechai, D. Wikler, A. Zakariah Making fair choices on the path to universal health coverage: applying principles to difficult cases Article (Accepted version) (Refereed) Original citation: Voorhoeve, Alex and Edejer, Tessa T. T. and Kapiriri, Lydia and Norheim, Ole Frithjof and Snowden, James and Basenya, Olivier and Bayarsaikhan, Dorjsuren and Chentaf, Ikram and Eyal, Nir and Folsom, Amanda and Hussein, Rozita Halina Tun and Morales, Cristian and Ostmann, Florian and Ottersen, Trygve and Prakongsai, Phusit and Saenz, Carla and Saleh, Karima and Sommanustweechai, Angkana and Wikler, Daniel and Zakariah, Afisah (2017) Making fair choices on the path to universal health coverage: applying principles to difficult cases. Health Systems & Reform, 3 (4). ISSN 2328-8604 DOI: 10.1080/23288604.2017.1324938 Reuse of this item is permitted through licensing under the Creative Commons: © 2017 The Authors CC BY 4.0 This version available at: http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/75183/ Available in LSE Research Online: September 2017 LSE has developed LSE Research Online so that users may access research output of the School. Copyright © and Moral Rights for the papers on this site are retained by the individual authors and/or other copyright owners. You may freely distribute the URL (http://eprints.lse.ac.uk) of the
    [Show full text]
  • Legal-Graphics 9-7 COVID
    Days since first COVID-19 Events sign of virus Indonesia North Carolina 24 Pennsylvania 26 Countries Affected Wyoming Madagascar 49 Ecuador Massachusetts India New Hamshire 25 South Carolina 32 Kyrgyzstan Philippines Feb. 18, 2020 Chile North Dakota Montserrat Zimbabwe 56 Country Name 62 Macau Nepal Illinois Ireland 31 Barbados El Salvador Washington 53 Italy Russia Georgia 28 So. Africa Peru Missouri Nebraska Bolivia 13 15 California Worldwide Argentina New Mexico Montana New Caledonia Papau or Coronavirus Deaths Austria Netherlands 19 17 Minnesota 19 Arizona 24 Kansas 23 13 Gambia Mauritius Taiwan Hong Kong Malaysia Sri Lanka India UK New York New Jersey Tennessee 25 Connecticut 14 Turkey Michigan Mississippi 21 Maine 20 >5,000 Deaths* over 2,000 Nicaragua Cape Verde Wisconsin Pakistan 19 13 South Korea Vietnam Australia Cambodia UAE Spain Switzerland Oregon 24 Florida 31 Colorado 21 Maryland 25 Kentucky Utah Virginia Vermont 26 Ohio 14 South Dakota Delaware 13 Idaho 12 Montenegro Bermuda or East Timor China France Thailand Japan US Singapore Canada Germany Finland Sweden Belgium Egypt Iran Israel Iraq Brazil Mexico Rhode Island 27 Texas 29 Nevada 27 Hawaii 17 Indiana 17 Oklahoma 15 Iowa Lousiana 13 St. Vincent Arkansas Alaska 15 Alabama 22 St. Maarten Djibouti West Virginia 6 Number of countries Uganda # France ? reporting on same day 11 5 4 8 3 (symbol is linked to 20 9 7 6 page with more detail) 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67 68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84 85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94 95 96 97 98 99 100 101 102 103 104 105 106 107 108 109 110 111 112 113 114 115 116 117 118 119 120 121 122 123 124 125 US States Affected Nov.
    [Show full text]
  • The Petrie Flom Center for Health Law Policy, Biotechnology, and Bioethics
    The Petrie Flom Center for Health Law Policy, Biotechnology, and Bioethics Annual Report, Fiscal Year 2015 Executive Summary This year marks the close of the Petrie-Flom Center’s first decade of existence, and we are thrilled with what we have been able to accomplish in that time. The Center began with a focus on developing new scholars and scholarship in the fields of health law policy, biotechnology, and bioethics through fellowship programs for students and post-docs, as well as a handful of events and conferences. Since then, our goals have expanded dramatically to include not only these important academic pursuits, but also policy impact through sponsored research collaborations bridging legal, medical, and other disciplines. Most notably, we are no longer only a research program comprised solely of individuals working on their individual projects, but rather a true Center made up of collaborators working on Center-based research with high impact and visibility. In terms of sponsored research, we have made substantial progress this year on our work leading the Law and Ethics Initiative of the Football Players Health Study at Harvard. In addition to providing guidance regarding legal and ethical issues that arise in other aspects of the study, we are drafting several reports and recommendations aimed at improving player health and well-being using the tools of law and ethics to complement clinical interventions. We have also continued our work with Harvard Catalyst’s Regulatory Foundations, Ethics, and Law Program, hosting an international conference to develop a research agenda around improving recruitment to clinical trials, developing guidance for the use of social media in recruitment efforts, and conducting empirical research regarding perceptions of offers of payment to research participants.
    [Show full text]
  • NIR EYAL, D. Phil • CURRICULUM VITAE • • December 26, 2015 Harvard TH Chan School of Public Health, Dept
    NIR EYAL, D. Phil • CURRICULUM VITAE • http://projects.iq.harvard.edu/nir_eyal • December 26, 2015 Harvard TH Chan School of Public Health, Dept. of Global Health and Population. Affiliations: Harvard Medical School Center for Bioethics, Harvard Law School Petrie Flom Center EDUCATION AND POST-DOCTORAL TRAINING 2004-2006 Harold T Shapiro Postdoctoral Fellowship in Bioethics, Princeton University Center for Human Values 2002-2004 Postdoctoral Fellow, National Institutes of Health, Department of Clinical Bioethics 1998-2003 DPhil, Politics (political philosophy), Oxford University 1994-1998 MA, Philosophy, Hebrew University 1991-1994 BA, Philosophy and History, Tel Aviv University ACADEMIC APPOINTMENTS 2015- Associate Professor, Dept. of Global Health and Population, Harvard TH Chan Sch of Public Health; Concentration in Global Health and Health Policy, FAS, Harvard University; Harvard University Program in Ethics and Health 2014-2015 Associate Professor, Center for Bioethics, Harvard Medical School; Dept. of Global Health and Population, Harvard TH Chan Sch of Public Health, Harvard University Program in Ethics and Health 2012-2013 Associate Professor, Division of Medical Ethics, Dept. of Global Health and Social Medicine, Harvard Medical School; Harvard University Program in Ethics and Health 2008-2012 Assistant Professor, Division of Medical Ethics, Dept. of Global Health and Social Medicine, Harvard Medical School; Harvard University Program in Ethics and Health 2009-2010 Faculty Fellow, EJ Safra Foundation Center for Ethics, Kennedy School of Government, Harvard U. 2006-2008 Instructor, Division of Medical Ethics, Dept. of Global Health and Social Medicine, Harvard Medical School; Harvard University Program in Ethics and Health PUBLICATIONS * Corresponding author 1. Lipsitch, M,* Eyal, N, Halloran, E, Hernán, MA, Longini, IM, Perencevich, EN, Grais, RF,* Vaccine testing: Ebola and beyond.
    [Show full text]
  • Department of Labor, Health and Human Services, and Education, and Related Agencies Appropriations for Fiscal Year 2018
    DEPARTMENT OF LABOR, HEALTH AND HUMAN SERVICES, AND EDUCATION, AND RELATED AGENCIES APPROPRIATIONS FOR FISCAL YEAR 2018 U.S. SENATE, SUBCOMMITTEE OF THE COMMITTEE ON APPROPRIATIONS, Washington, DC. [CLERK’S NOTE.—The subcommittee was unable to hold hearings on departmental and nondepartmental witnesses. The statements and letters of those submitting written testimony are as follows:] DEPARTMENTAL WITNESSES PREPARED STATEMENT OF THE CORPORATION FOR PUBLIC BROADCASTING Chairman Blunt, Ranking Member Murray, and distinguished members of the subcommittee, thank you for allowing me to submit this testimony on behalf of America’s public media service—public television and public radio—on-air, online and in the community. The Corporation for Public Broadcasting (CPB) requests level funding of $445 million for fiscal year 2020, $55 million in fiscal year 2018 for the replacement of the public broadcasting interconnection system, and $30 million for Ready To Learn at the Department of Education. As we mark the 50th anniversary of the passage of the Public Broadcasting Act, this uniquely American public-private partnership continues to keep its promise— to provide high-quality, trusted content that educates, inspires, informs and en- riches in ways that benefit our civil society. Through the nearly 1,500 locally owned and operated public radio and television stations across the country, public media reaches 99 percent of the American people from big cities to small towns and rural communities. At approximately $1.35 per citizen per year it is one of America’s best infrastructure investments—paying huge dividends in education, public safety and civic leadership for millions of Americans and their families.
    [Show full text]
  • Saving People from the Harm of Death Edited by Espen Gamlund and Carl Tollef Solberg Foreword by Jeff Mcmahan OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS Singer, Peter
    POPULATION-LEVEL BIOETHICS Ethics and the Public's Health Series Editors Nir Eyal, Harvard Medical School Dan Wilder, Harvard School of Public Health Saving People from the Editorial Board Dan Brock, Harvard University Harm of Death John Broome, Oxford University Norman Daniels, Harvard University Edited by Espen Gamlund Marc Fleurbaey, Princeton University and Julio Frenk, Harvard University Frances Kamm, Rutgers University Carl Tollef Solberg Daniel Hausman, University of Wisconsin-Madison Michael Marmot, University College, London With a Foreword by Jeff McMahan Christopher Murray, Institute for Health Metrics and Evaluation, University of Washington Amartya Sen, Harvard University Volumes in the Series Inequalities in Health: Concepts, Measures, and Ethics Edited by Nir Eyal, Samia A. Hurst, Ole F. Norheim, and Dan Wilder Valuing Health: Well-Being, Freedom, and Suffering Daniel M. Hausman Identified versus Statistical Lives: An Interdisciplinary Perspective Edited by I. Glenn Cohen, Norman Daniels, and Nir Eyal Saving People from the Harm of Death Edited by Espen Gamlund and Carl Tollef Solberg Foreword by Jeff McMahan OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS Singer, Peter. 1993. Practical Ethics, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Uniacke, Suzanne, and H. J. McCloskey. 1992. "Peter Singer and Non-Voluntary 'Euthanasia': Tripping Down the Slippery Slope." Journal of Applied Philosophy 9, 2: 203-219. Volk, Anthony A., and Jeremy A. Atkins. 2013. "Infant and Child Death in the Human Environment of Evolutionary Adaptation:' Evolution and Human Behavior 34, 3: 182-192. Wright, Robert. 1994. The Moral Animal: Why We Are the Way We Are. London: Abacus. Putting a Number on the Harm of Death Joseph Millum 1. Introduction Donors to global health programs and policymakers within national health systems have to make difficult decisions about how to spend scarce health care dollars.
    [Show full text]
  • Three Case Studies in Making Fair Choices on the Path to Universal Health Coverage
    HHr Health and Human Rights Journal Three Case Studies in Making Fair Choices on theHHR_final_logo_alone.indd Path 1 10/19/15 10:53 AM to Universal Health Coverage alex voorhoeve, tessa t.t. edejer, lydia kapiriri, ole f. norheim, james snowden, olivier basenya, dorjsuren bayarsaikhan, ikram chentaf, nir eyal, amanda folsom, rozita halina tun hussein, cristian morales, florian ostmann, trygve ottersen, phusit prakongsai, carla saenz, karima saleh, angkana sommanustweechai, daniel wikler, and afisah zakariah Alex Voorhoeve, PhD, is Associate Professor in the Department of Philosophy, Logic, and Scientific Method, London School of Economics, London, UK and Visiting Scholar in the Department of Bioethics at the National Institutes of Health, Bethesda, US. Tessa Tan-Torres Edejer, MD, is Coordinator of Costs, Effectiveness, Expenditure and Priority Setting, Health Systems Governance and Financing, and Health Systems and Innovation, World Health Organization, Geneva, Switzerland. Lydia Kapiriri, PhD, is Associate Professor in the Department of Health, Aging, and Society, McMaster University, Hamilton, Ontario, Canada. Ole Frithjof of Norheim, MD, PhD, is Director of Global Health Priorities in the Department of Global Public Health and Primary Care University of Bergen, Bergen, Norway. James Snowden, MSc, is Research Analyst at Giving What We Can, Centre for Effective Altruism, Oxford, UK. Olivier Basenya, MD, MSc, is Performance-Based Financing Expert in the Ministry of Health, Bujumbura, Burundi. Dorjsuren Bayarsaikhan, MPH, is Health Economist in the Department of Health Systems Governance and Financing, World Health Organization, Geneva, Switzerland. Ikram Chentaf, MBA, is International and Intergovernmental Cooperation Program Manager in the Cooperation Division at the Ministry of Health, Rabat, Morocco.
    [Show full text]
  • NIR EYAL, D. Phil • CURRICULUM VITAE • • August 10, 2017
    NIR EYAL, D. Phil • CURRICULUM VITAE • http://projects.iq.harvard.edu/nir_eyal • August 10, 2017 Harvard TH Chan School of Public Health, Dept. of Global Health and Population. Affiliations: HMS Center for Bioethics, FAS Concentration in Global Health and Health Policy, HU Program in Ethics & Health, HLS Petrie Flom Center. EDUCATION AND POST-DOCTORAL TRAINING 2004-2006 Harold T Shapiro Postdoctoral Fellowship in Bioethics, Princeton University Center for Human Values 2002-2004 Postdoctoral Fellow, National Institutes of Health, Department of Clinical Bioethics 1998-2003 DPhil, Politics (political philosophy), Oxford University 1994-1998 MA, Philosophy, Hebrew University 1991-1994 BA, Philosophy and History, Tel Aviv University ACADEMIC APPOINTMENTS 2015- Associate Professor, Dept. of Global Health and Population, Harvard TH Chan School of Public Health; Concentration in Global Health and Health Policy, FAS, Harvard University; Harvard University Program in Ethics and Health. 2014-2015 Associate Professor, Center for Bioethics, Harvard Medical School; Dept. of Global Health and Population, Harvard TH Chan School of Public Health, Harvard University Program in Ethics and Health. 2012-2013 Associate Professor, Division of Medical Ethics, Dept. of Global Health and Social Medicine, Harvard Medical School; Harvard University Program in Ethics and Health. 2008-2012 Assistant Professor, Division of Medical Ethics, Dept. of Global Health and Social Medicine, Harvard Medical School; Harvard University Program in Ethics and Health. 2009-2010 Faculty Fellow, EJ Safra Foundation Center for Ethics, Kennedy School of Government, Harvard U. 2006-2008 Instructor, Division of Medical Ethics, Dept. of Global Health and Social Medicine, Harvard Medical School; Harvard University Program in Ethics and Health.
    [Show full text]
  • Nudging by Shaming, Shaming by Nudging Editorial
    http://ijhpm.com Int J Health Policy Manag 2014, 3(2), 53–56 doi 10.15171/ijhpm.2014.68 Editorial Nudging by shaming, shaming by nudging Nir Eyal* Correspondence to: Nir Eyal, Email: [email protected] culminating in widespread response. In the cafeteria example, Copyright: © 2014 by Kerman University of Medical Sciences exceeding laziness or hyperbolic discounting makes most of Citation: Eyal N. Nudging by shaming, shaming by nudging. Int J Health Policy us disproportionately averse to taking a few steps to the back Manag 2014; 3: 53–56. doi: 10.15171/ijhpm.2014.68 Received: 10 July 2014, Accepted: 24 July 2014, ePublished: 25 July 2014 of the cafeteria, or our appetite concentrates only around what we see first and blocks appetite for alternatives. This is not a rational response on our parts but the result is that we pick the Nudging first item we see. In both developing and developed countries, health ministries This editorial does not question or defend this understanding closely examine use of so-called nudges to promote population of some nudges’ mechanism of action. Instead it advances health and welfare. Cass Sunstein and Richard Thaler, who two hypotheses regarding the connection between nudging developed the concept, define a nudge as “any aspect of the so characterized and shame, understood broadly to include choice architecture that alters people’s behavior in a predictable embarrassment, stigma effects, and any compunction in way without forbidding any options or significantly changing general. One hypothesis I advance is that shame can serve their economic incentives. To count as a nudge, the intervention in nudging.
    [Show full text]
  • APA Newsletter on Philosophy and Medicine, Vol. 15, No. 2, Spring 2016
    NEWSLETTER | The American Philosophical Association Philosophy and Medicine SPRING 2016 VOLUME 15 | NUMBER 2 Rosamond Rhodes FROM THE EDITORS Removing Patients from the ICU: Is It Ever Mary Rorty and Mark Sheldon Morally Justifiable? FROM THE CHAIR Trevor Hedberg Nir Eyal Unraveling the Asymmetry in Procreative When Is It Best to Die? Ethics Dana Howard SUBMISSION GUIDELINES Response to Hedberg ARTICLES Kyle Fruh Luke Gelinas Moral Heroism, Living Organ Donation, Skeptical Worries for ICU Rationing and the Problem of Winning by Donating Leonard M. Fleck Lisa Fuller Just Rationing in the ICU: What Benefits Heroism, Meaning, and Organ Donation: Count? A Reply to Fruh Timothy F. Murphy What Does Admission to the Intensive BOOK REVIEW Care Unit Mean, Morally Speaking? Dr. Susan Love’s Breast Book, Sixth Edition Marion Danis, M.D. Reviewed by Felicia Nimue Ackerman The Moral Permissibility of Removing Patients from Intensive Care VOLUME 15 | NUMBER 2 SPRING 2016 © 2016 BY THE AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL ASSOCIATION ISSN 2155-9708 APA NEWSLETTER ON Philosophy and Medicine MARY RORTY AND MARK SHELDON, CO-EDITORS VOLUME 15 | NUMBER 2 | SPRING 2016 living more from being good for you. It can make living FROM THE EDITORS more bad for you. This does not mean that you would be wise to commit suicide, or that your friends or doctor should Mary Rorty help you do that—these are more complicated decisions. STANFORD UNIVERSITY What it means is, roughly, that if you died painlessly now, that event would be good for you. Mark Sheldon NORTHWESTERN UNIVERSITY Assuming that such degree of badness in a period of one’s life can exist, the question arises what that degree is.
    [Show full text]