Foundations of Finsler Spacetimes from the Observers' Viewpoint
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
universe Article Foundations of Finsler Spacetimes from the Observers’ Viewpoint Antonio N. Bernal 1, Miguel A. Javaloyes 2 and Miguel Sánchez 1,* 1 Departamento de Geometría y Topología, Facultad de Ciencias, Universidad de Granada, Campus Fuentenueva s/n, 18071 Granada, Spain; [email protected] 2 Departamento de Matemáticas, Universidad de Murcia, Campus de Espinardo, 30100 Espinardo, Murcia, Spain; [email protected] * Correspondence: [email protected] Received: 29 February 2020; Accepted: 13 April 2020; Published: 16 April 2020 Abstract: Physical foundations for relativistic spacetimes are revisited in order to check at what extent Finsler spacetimes lie in their framework. Arguments based on inertial observers (as in the foundations of special relativity and classical mechanics) are shown to correspond with a double linear approximation in the measurement of space and time. While general relativity appears by dropping the first linearization, Finsler spacetimes appear by dropping the second one. The classical Ehlers–Pirani–Schild approach is carefully discussed and shown to be compatible with the Lorentz–Finsler case. The precise mathematical definition of Finsler spacetime is discussed by using the space of observers. Special care is taken in some issues such as the fact that a Lorentz–Finsler metric would be physically measurable only on the causal directions for a cone structure, the implications for models of spacetimes of some apparently innocuous hypotheses on differentiability, or the possibilities of measurement of a varying speed of light. Keywords: Finsler spacetime; Ehlers–Pirani–Schild approach; Lorentz symmetry breaking; very special relativity; signature-changing spacetimes MSC: 53C60; 83D05; 83A05; 83C05 1. Introduction A plethora of alternatives to classical general relativity has been developed since its very beginning. Many of them were motivated by the search of a unified theory which solved disturbing issues of compatibility with quantum mechanics (Kaluza–Klein, M-theory, quantum field gravity, etc.) while, since the 90s, unexpected cosmological measurements led to further alternatives (cosmological constant, quintaessence, theories with varying speed of light, etc.). However, the possibility to consider a Finslerian modification of General Relativity has not settled in mainstream research, and it has been scarcely considered in the literature until recent times (some examples are References [1–15]). Certainly, the generality of Finsler geometry in comparison with the Riemannian setup (namely, analogous to the generality of the convex open subsets of an affine space in comparison with the ellipsoids) is a big drawback, as the number of new variables and parameters would seem immeasurable. Nevertheless, this is similar to the generality of general relativity in comparison with the special one (see Remark 13). Anyway, any Finslerian modification of general relativity would mean to drop the beloved Lorentz invariance not only at global and local levels (as it occurs in general relativity) but also infinitesimally, i.e. looking such an invariance as a limit symmetry around each event. However, from a fundamental viewpoint, this should not seem too strange: as physical measurements are always approximations, one would not be surprised if the symmetries of the models were only approximations to a more complex Universe 2020, 6, 55; doi:10.3390/universe6040055 www.mdpi.com/journal/universe Universe 2020, 6, 55 2 of 39 reality. Indeed, as we will explain, the existence of some symmetries among observers becomes a natural requirement in order to make direct measurements of space and time. There is no reason to assume that the physical reality will satisfy such requirements in an exact way—even though, certainly, the existence of such approximated symmetries are meaningful and useful for modeling. In the present article, a physical motivation to consider Finsler spacetimes as models of space and time is developed and quite a few of related ideas are discussed. We stress the following four guidelines. 1.1. Approach from the Foundations Viewpoint We develop an approach for the foundations of the theories of spacetime starting at the observers viewpoint in classical mechanics and special relativity (Sections2–4). Finsler spacetimes are shown to appear by dropping the symmetries of inertial observers in a natural way. Our approach follows the viewpoint in Reference [16] by López and by two of the authors in Sections2 and3, which includes the celebrated ideas by V. Ignatowski [17,18] about the foundations of special relativity. Specifically, we argue that the geometric models of spacetime appear from the notion of inertial observers by means of a double linearization of the measuring problem, namely, (1) there are inertial frames of reference (IFR) in which changes of coordinates are linear, and (2) the symmetries in the change of the time-like coordinate (and, independently, in the three spacelike ones) between two IFR’s are encoded in that linear structure. These assumptions lead to four classic linear 4-dimensional structures, namely Lorentz–Minkowski, Galilei–Newton, dual Galilei–Newton, and Euclidean (see Section2). Dropping (1) leads from special to general relativity (see Section3) as well as to other transitions for the other three structures. The latter are also briefly explained here, namely, from Galilean to Leibnizian spacetimes (see Section 3.4), including signature changing metrics (see Section 3.1), and the possibility of a pointwise varying speed of light (see Section 3.3). Dropping (2) leads to Lorentz–Minkowski norms and, then, to Finsler spacetimes, discussed both mathematically and physically in Section4. 1.2. Critical Revision of EPS Axiomatics The classical Ehlers, Pirani, and Schild (EPS) approach for general relativity [19,20] will be revisited (see Section5). We show that, certainly, this approach is compatible with the existence of Lorentz–Finsler metrics, a possibility already suggested by Tavakol and Van Den Bergh for Berwald spaces [15] (see the discussion in Section 5.2.5). Such a possibility was ignored in EPS because of a too restrictive development of two steps1, namely: • An artificial requirement of smoothability of some combination of radar coordinates, which would forbid null cone structures incompatible with Lorentzian metrics. This was recently pointed out by Lammërzhal and Perlick’s [11], and it is developed here in detail (see Section 5.2.1). • A deduction of the existence of a projective structure starting at a general version of the law of inertia. This would exclude the time-like pregeodesics for a Lorentz–Finsler metric (except those of Berwald-type), but again, the proof crucially relies on an argument of C2-differentiability, which is related to nontrivial issues on Finslerian metrics (see Section 5.2.2). 1.3. Precise Geometric Framework Along the article, a careful mathematical approach is carried out following Reference [10]. For the convenience of the reader, a brief mathematical summary on (Lorentz) Finsler concepts is also included 1 The reason relies on a classical result for any Finsler metric F: its square F2 is C2 at the zero section if and only if F comes from a Riemannian metric (see Remark5 (1) and Section 5.2). Universe 2020, 6, 55 3 of 39 in Section 4.1. This allows us to model and to discuss issues on Lorentz–Finsler metrics L which turn out to be important from the physical viewpoint such as the following: (1) Causal cone domain (Section4). The physically meaningful domain for L is only the causal cone of a cone structure C. Indeed, even in the classical relativistic case, only the future-directed causal directions for a cone C+ determined by the metric g contains the elements physically measurable for any (true or gedanken) experiment. In relativity, the Lorentzian scalar product gp at each event p is determined + by its value on the cone Cp (or on its time-like directions); therefore, a Lorentz metric g can be determined on the whole TM even if, actually, only its value on C+ can be measured. However, this is not by any means true for a Lorentz–Finsler metric L, where there is a huge freedom to extend the Lorentz–Finsler metric away from C. Therefore, our Lorentz–Finsler metrics will be defined only on a (causal) cone structure2. (2) Smoothness, i.e., differentiability up to some appropriate order. Usually, such a requirement is regarded as a harmless macroscopic approximation to the structure of the spacetime. However, the discussion on EPS above shows that this is not so trivial in the Finslerian case. Furthermore, other issues appear in the literature: • The possibility that the cone is smooth, and the Lorentz–Finsler metric is smooth only on the time-like directions but cannot be smoothly extended to the cone, which happens in metrics such as Bogoslovski in very special relativity [21] and others [22]; see Section 6.1. • The lack of differentiability outside the zero section of Finsler product spacetimes, which may lead to definitions of Finsler static spacetimes which are not smooth in the static direction [2], a fact which can be overcome with our approach to the space of observers; see Section 4.2 (item 5 (b)). (3) Anisotropic speed of light. Finsler spacetimes permit different possibilities for a speed of light which may vary not only with the point (an issue already considered even for relativistic spacetimes, Section 3.3) but also with the direction (Section 6.2). 1.4. Importance of the Space of Observers The relevance of the space of observers in special and general relativity, its links with the symmetries of the spacetime and the possibility to lift relativity to this space have been stressed by several authors [23,24] in the framework of Lorentz violation and Lorentz–Finsler geometry. It is worth emphasizing that the essential role of this space appears explicitly along our development. In the initial discussion of the linearized models, we start with the set S of inertial frames of reference (IFR), which permits even signature changing metrics (Section 3.1).