Aggregation Operators on Partially Ordered Sets and Their Categorical Foundations

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Aggregation Operators on Partially Ordered Sets and Their Categorical Foundations KYBERNETIKA—VOLUME 4 2 (2006), NUMBER 3, PAGES 261–277 AGGREGATION OPERATORS ON PARTIALLY ORDERED SETS AND THEIR CATEGORICAL FOUNDATIONS Mustafa Demirci In spite of increasing studies and investigations in the field of aggregation operators, there are two fundamental problems remaining unsolved: aggregation of L-fuzzy set- theoretic notions and their justification. In order to solve these problems, we will formu- late aggregation operators and their special types on partially ordered sets with universal bounds, and introduce their categories. Furthermore, we will show that there exists a strong connection between the category of aggregation operators on partially ordered sets with universal bounds (Agop) and the category of partially ordered groupoids with uni- versal bounds (Pogpu). Moreover, the subcategories of Agop consisting of associative aggregation operators, symmetric and associative aggregation operators and associative aggregation operators with neutral elements are, respectively, isomorphic to the subcate- gories of Pogpu formed by partially ordered semigroups, commutative partially ordered semigroups and partially ordered monoids in the sense of Birkhoff. As a justification of the present notions and results, some relevant examples for aggregations operators on partially ordered sets are given. Particularly, aggregation process in probabilistic metric spaces is also considered. Keywords: category theory, aggregation operator, associative aggregation operator, par- tially ordered groupoid, partially ordered semigroup, partially ordered monoid AMS Subject Classification: 18A15, 03G10, 06F05, 08C05, 03E72 1. INTRODUCTION Aggregation operators are an essential mathematical tool for the combination of several data as a single outcome. Although they have been studied intensively in the last years [4, 11, 15], there are still some fundamental questions remaining unan- swered. Because of the fact that aggregation operators have been formulated based on a particular partially ordered set ([0, 1], ) (or more generally, ([a, b], ) for some ≤ ≤ a, b R)[4, 11, 15], the present literature does not provide an aggregation process for L∈-fuzzy set theoretic notions that are playing a central role in the development of various branches of fuzzy mathematics [10], where L is a partial ordered set with universal bounds (posetu, for short) in general. This is one of the fundamental prob- lems. In order to solve this problem, we will formulate aggregation operators based 262 M. DEMIRC˙ I˙ on a posetu L, and extend the algebraic properties of symmetry, associativity and the neutral element of aggregation operators to this setting. Furthermore, we design some relevant examples, and show that aggregation operators on posetus are suffi- ciently rich and abstract notions for unifying various kinds of aggregation operator under the same framework. In addition to the above problem, since aggregation operators are some kinds of generalization of binary operation on L with some further properties, it is natural to ask the connections between aggregation operators and such binary operations on L. This question can also be stated for the connection between the subclass of ag- gregation operators consisting of symmetric aggregation operators (resp. associative aggregation operators, aggregation operators with neutral elements) and binary op- erations on L with some suitable algebraic properties. These questions lead us to the necessity for considering the category of aggregation operators on posetus (Agop) and its subcategories of associative aggregation operators (Asagop), of symmetric and associative aggregation operators (Smasagop), and of associative aggregation operators with neutral elements (or simply monoidal aggregation operators) ( Mon- agop). If we take into consideration the category of partially ordered groupoids with universal bounds (Pogpu) and its subcategories of partially ordered semigroups (Posmgu), of commutative partially ordered semigroups (Cmposmgu), and of partially ordered monoids (Pomonu), then the second main problem can be ab- stracted to the categorical relation between Agop (resp. Asagop, Smasagop and Monagop) and Pogpu (resp. Posmgu, Cmposmgu and Pomonu). All of these categories are summarized in Table 1. As an answer to this problem, we will prove that Pogpu is isomorphic to an isomorphism-closed and full subcategory of Agop. Furthermore, Asagop, Smasagop and Monagop are, respectively, isomorphic to Posmgu, Cmposmgu and Pomonu. In addition to these categorical connections, we will also look at subobjects and fibres in Agop towards the end of this paper, and establish a meaningful definition of subaggregation operator as a special subobject in Agop. 2. AGGREGATION OPERATORS ON PARTIALLY ORDERED SETS Let L = (L, , , ) denote a posetu, i. e. (L, ) is a partially ordered set (poset, for brevity)≤ with⊥ the> least element and the≤ greatest element . The ordering ⊥ > structure on L can be coordinatwisely extended to Ln (n N+), i. e. for the relation on Ln, defined by ∈ ≤ [(α , . , α ) (β , . , β )] [( i = 1, . , n)(α β )], 1 n ≤ 1 n ⇔ ∀ i ≤ i and for the elements (n) = ( ,..., ), (n) = ( ,..., ) of Ln, the four-tuple L = (Ln, , (n), (n⊥)) forms⊥ a poset⊥ with> universal> bounds> (n) and (n). n ≤ ⊥ > ⊥ > n Definition 1. A mapping A : + L L is called an aggregation operator on n N L = (L, , , ) if the following conditions∈ → are fulfilled: ≤ ⊥ > ∪ (AG.1) A preserves the order on Ln for all n N+, i. e. ∈ [(α , . , α ) (β , . , β )] [A(α , . , α ) A(β , . , β )] 1 n ≤ 1 n ⇒ 1 n ≤ 1 n AGOPS on Posets and Their Categorical Foundations 263 (AG.2) A is the identity mapping id on L, i. e. A(α) = α for all α L, L ∈ (AG.3) A preserves universal bounds, i. e. (n) (n) + A( ) = and A( ) = for all n N . ⊥ ⊥ > > ∈ For n 2, a mapping B : Ln L is called an n -ary aggregation operator on L = (≥L, , , ) iff the conditions→ (AG.1) and (AG.3) are satisfied. A 1-ary aggregation operator≤ ⊥ > B : L L is the identity mapping id on L. → L An aggregation operator A on L can be identified by a family of n-ary aggregation + operators An n N . This means that for a given aggregation operator A { | ∈ } + on L, we may associate a family of n-ary aggregation operators An n N to A, which is defined by A (α , . , α ) = A(α , . , α ). Conversely,{ | if∈ A } n 1 n 1 n { n | n N+ is a family of n-ary aggregation operators on L, then we can define an ∈ } aggregation operator A on L by A(α1, . , αn) = An(α1, . , αn). It is obvious that the connection between the aggregation operators and the families of n -ary aggregation operators are bijective. Thus an aggregation operator and its associated + family of n-ary aggregation operators An n N can be conceived as the same things. { | ∈ } Aggregation operators on posetus in the sense of Definition 1 provide an abstract and a useful mathematical tool for unifying various kinds of aggregation operator under the same framework, and they also enable us to apply the notion of aggregation operator in several branch of mathematics. In order to clarify this, we design the following example: Example 2. (a) For the particular posetu I = ([0, 1], , 0, 1), an (n-ary) aggrega- tion operator on I is called an (n-ary) aggregation operator≤ in [4, 11, 15]. Thus an (n -ary) aggregation operator in the sense of Definition 1 is a straightforward extension of (n-ary) aggregation operator in the sense of [4, 11, 15] to a general posetu. (b) Let [0, 1] denote the set of all closed subintervals of [0, 1], i. e. [0, 1] = I I [a, b] a, b [0, 1], a b . If we consider the partial ordering w on [0, 1] (called the{ weak| interval-ordering∈ ≤ } [12]) defined by ¹ I [a, b] [c, d] ((a c) and (b d)) , ¹w ⇔ ≤ ≤ then [0, 0] and [1, 1] are obviously the least and greatest elements of the poset ( [0, 1], ). An interval-valued aggregation operator (or an extended aggregation I ¹w operator) in [12] is nothing else but an aggregation operator on ( [0, 1], w, [0, 0], [1, 1]). I ¹ 2 (c) Consider the set L∗ = (x , x ) [0, 1] x + x 1 . The relation on { 1 2 ∈ | 1 2 ≤ } ≤L∗ L∗, defined as (x , x ) (y , y ) ((x y ) and (y x )) , 1 2 ≤L∗ 1 2 ⇔ 1 ≤ 1 2 ≤ 2 264 M. DEMIRC˙ I˙ is a partial ordering [6, 7]. 0L∗ = (0, 1) and 1L∗ = (1, 0) are the least and greatest elements of the poset (L∗, ). An aggregation operator on (L∗, , 0 , 1 ) is ≤L∗ ≤L∗ L∗ L∗ called an aggregation operator on L∗ in [6]. (d) Let [0, 1] stand for the set of all normal convex fuzzy subsets of [0, 1] (i. e. a normal convexNC fuzzy subset µ of [0, 1] is a mapping µ : [0, 1] [0, 1] satisfying the conditions that µ(x) = 1 and µ(x ) µ(x ) µ(x ) for→ all x , x , x [0, 1] x [0,1] 1 ∧ 3 ≤ 2 1 2 3 ∈ with x x x ∈[13]). Define the relation on [0, 1] by 1 ≤ 2 ≤ ∨3 v NC µ ν µ ν = µ, v ⇔ u where : [0, 1] [0, 1] [0, 1] is the extended minimum operation min on [0u, 1]NC [8, 13],× i. e. N C → N C NC g [ (µ, ν)] (x)= min(µ, ν) (x)= µ(x ) ν(x ) x , x [0, 1], x=min x , x . u { 1 ∧ 2 | 1 2 ∈ { 1 2}} [ ] ∨ Then ( [0, 1],g) forms a poset [13] . Furthermore the fuzzy subsets 01, 11 of [0, 1] , definedNC by v 1, if x = 0 1, if x = 1 0 (x) = and 1 (x) = 1 0, otherwise 1 0, otherwise, { } { } are the least and greatest elements of ( [0, 1], ). We will show in Remark 3 that NC v aggregation operators on ( [0, 1], , 01, 11) enable us to aggregate type 2 fuzzy sets with normal convex fuzzyNC grades.v (e) A non-decreasing function F :[ , ] [0, 1], satisfying the properties that F is left-continuous on (0, ), F (0) =−∞ 0 and∞ F→( ) = 1, is called a distance distri- bution function on [ , ∞][11, 16].
Recommended publications
  • Scott Spaces and the Dcpo Category
    SCOTT SPACES AND THE DCPO CATEGORY JORDAN BROWN Abstract. Directed-complete partial orders (dcpo’s) arise often in the study of λ-calculus. Here we investigate certain properties of dcpo’s and the Scott spaces they induce. We introduce a new construction which allows for the canonical extension of a partial order to a dcpo and give a proof that the dcpo introduced by Zhao, Xi, and Chen is well-filtered. Contents 1. Introduction 1 2. General Definitions and the Finite Case 2 3. Connectedness of Scott Spaces 5 4. The Categorical Structure of DCPO 6 5. Suprema and the Waybelow Relation 7 6. Hofmann-Mislove Theorem 9 7. Ordinal-Based DCPOs 11 8. Acknowledgments 13 References 13 1. Introduction Directed-complete partially ordered sets (dcpo’s) often arise in the study of λ-calculus. Namely, they are often used to construct models for λ theories. There are several versions of the λ-calculus, all of which attempt to describe the ‘computable’ functions. The first robust descriptions of λ-calculus appeared around the same time as the definition of Turing machines, and Turing’s paper introducing computing machines includes a proof that his computable functions are precisely the λ-definable ones [5] [8]. Though we do not address the λ-calculus directly here, an exposition of certain λ theories and the construction of Scott space models for them can be found in [1]. In these models, computable functions correspond to continuous functions with respect to the Scott topology. It is thus with an eye to the application of topological tools in the study of computability that we investigate the Scott topology.
    [Show full text]
  • Generic Filters in Partially Ordered Sets Esfandiar Eslami Iowa State University
    Iowa State University Capstones, Theses and Retrospective Theses and Dissertations Dissertations 1982 Generic filters in partially ordered sets Esfandiar Eslami Iowa State University Follow this and additional works at: https://lib.dr.iastate.edu/rtd Part of the Mathematics Commons Recommended Citation Eslami, Esfandiar, "Generic filters in partially ordered sets " (1982). Retrospective Theses and Dissertations. 7038. https://lib.dr.iastate.edu/rtd/7038 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Iowa State University Capstones, Theses and Dissertations at Iowa State University Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Retrospective Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Iowa State University Digital Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. INFORMATION TO USERS This was produced from a copy of a document sent to us for microfilming. While most advanced technological means to photograph and reproduce this docum. have been used, the quality is heavily dependent upon the quality of the mate submitted. The following explanation of techniques is provided to help you underst markings or notations which may appear on this reproduction. 1.The sign or "target" for pages apparently lacking from the documen photographed is "Missing Page(s)". If it was possible to obtain the missin; page(s) or section, they are spliced into the film along with adjacent pages This may have necessitated cutting through an image and duplicatin; adjacent pages to assure you of complete continuity. 2. When an image on the film is obliterated with a round black mark it is ai indication that the film inspector noticed either blurred copy because o movement during exposure, or duplicate copy.
    [Show full text]
  • PARTIALLY ORDERED TOPOLOGICAL SPACES E(A) = L(A) R\ M(A)
    PARTIALLY ORDERED TOPOLOGICAL SPACES L. E. WARD, JR.1 1. Introduction. In this paper we shall consider topological spaces endowed with a reflexive, transitive, binary relation, which, following Birkhoff [l],2 we shall call a quasi order. It will frequently be as- sumed that this quasi order is continuous in an appropriate sense (see §2) as well as being a partial order. Various aspects of spaces possess- ing a quasi order have been investigated by L. Nachbin [6; 7; 8], Birkhoff [l, pp. 38-41, 59-64, 80-82, as well as the papers cited on those pages], and the author [13]. In addition, Wallace [10] has employed an argument using quasi ordered spaces to obtain a fixed point theorem for locally connected continua. This paper is divided into three sections, the first of which is concerned with definitions and preliminary results. A fundamental result due to Wallace, which will have later applications, is proved. §3 is concerned with compact- ness and connectedness properties of chains contained in quasi ordered spaces, and §4 deals with fixed point theorems for quasi ordered spaces. As an application, a new theorem on fixed sets for locally connected continua is proved. This proof leans on a method first employed by Wallace [10]. The author wishes to acknowledge his debt and gratitude to Pro- fessor A. D. Wallace for his patient and encouraging suggestions dur- ing the preparation of this paper. 2. Definitions and preliminary results. By a quasi order on a set X, we mean a reflexive, transitive binary relation, ^. If this relation is also anti-symmetric, it is a partial order.
    [Show full text]
  • Endomorphism Monoids of Combinatorial Structures
    Endomorphism Monoids of Combinatorial Structures Nik Ruskuc [email protected] School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews Dunedin, December 2007 Relational structures Definition I A relational structure X = (X ; Ri (i 2 I )) consists of a set X and a collection of relations defined on X . r I Each relation Ri has an arity ri , meaning Ri ⊆ X i . I The sequence (ri (i 2 I )) is called the signature of X . Combinatorial structures as relational structures Different combinatorial structures can be distinguished by their signatures and special properties required from their relations. Examples I A (simple, undirected) graph is a relational structure with signature (2), such that its only binary relation is symmetric and irreflexive. I A general structure of signature (2) is a digraph. I Posets: signature (2); properties R, AS, T. I Permutations: signature (2,2); properties: two linear orders. Morphisms Definition Let X = (X ; Ri (i 2 I )) be a relational structure. An endomorphism is a mapping θ : X ! X which respects all the relations Ri , i.e. (x1;:::; xk ) 2 Ri ) (x1θ; : : : ; xk θ) 2 Ri : An automorphisms is an invertible endomorphism. Remark For posets and graphs the above becomes: x ≤ y ) xθ ≤ yθ; x ∼ y ) xθ ∼ yθ: Warning: A bijective endomorphism need not be invertible. Take V = Z, E = f(i − 1; i): i ≤ 0g, and f : x 7! x − 1. Morphisms End(X ) = the endomorphism monoid of X Aut(X ) = the automorphism group of X General Problem For a given X , how are X , End(X ) and Aut(X ), and their properties, related? Trans(X ) and Sym(X ) Let E = E(X ) be a trivial relational structure on X .
    [Show full text]
  • Lazy Monoids and Reversible Computation
    Imaginary group: lazy monoids and reversible computation J. Gabbay and P. Kropholler REPORT No. 22, 2011/2012, spring ISSN 1103-467X ISRN IML-R- -22-11/12- -SE+spring Imaginary groups: lazy monoids and reversible computation Murdoch J. Gabbay and Peter H. Kropholler Abstract. By constructions in monoid and group theory we exhibit an adjunction between the category of partially ordered monoids and lazy monoid homomorphisms, and the category of partially ordered groups and group homomorphisms, such that the unit of the adjunction is in- jective. We also prove a similar result for sets acted on by monoids and groups. We introduce the new notion of lazy homomorphism for a function f be- tween partially-ordered monoids such that f (m m ) f (m) f (m ). ◦ ′ ≤ ◦ ′ Every monoid can be endowed with the discrete partial ordering (m m ≤ ′ if and only if m = m′) so our constructions provide a way of embed- ding monoids into groups. A simple counterexample (the two-element monoid with a non-trivial idempotent) and some calculations show that one can never hope for such an embedding to be a monoid homomor- phism, so the price paid for injecting a monoid into a group is that we must weaken the notion of homomorphism to this new notion of lazy homomorphism. The computational significance of this is that a monoid is an abstract model of computation—or at least of ‘operations’—and similarly a group models reversible computations/operations. By this reading, the adjunc- tion with its injective unit gives a systematic high-level way of faithfully translating an irreversible system to a ‘lazy’ reversible one.
    [Show full text]
  • Math 311 - Introduction to Proof and Abstract Mathematics Group Assignment # 15 Name: Due: at the End of Class on Tuesday, March 26Th
    Math 311 - Introduction to Proof and Abstract Mathematics Group Assignment # 15 Name: Due: At the end of class on Tuesday, March 26th More on Functions: Definition 5.1.7: Let A, B, C, and D be sets. Let f : A B and g : C D be functions. Then f = g if: → → A = C and B = D • For all x A, f(x)= g(x). • ∈ Intuitively speaking, this definition tells us that a function is determined by its underlying correspondence, not its specific formula or rule. Another way to think of this is that a function is determined by the set of points that occur on its graph. 1. Give a specific example of two functions that are defined by different rules (or formulas) but that are equal as functions. 2. Consider the functions f(x)= x and g(x)= √x2. Find: (a) A domain for which these functions are equal. (b) A domain for which these functions are not equal. Definition 5.1.9 Let X be a set. The identity function on X is the function IX : X X defined by, for all x X, → ∈ IX (x)= x. 3. Let f(x)= x cos(2πx). Prove that f(x) is the identity function when X = Z but not when X = R. Definition 5.1.10 Let n Z with n 0, and let a0,a1, ,an R such that an = 0. The function p : R R is a ∈ ≥ ··· ∈ 6 n n−1 → polynomial of degree n with real coefficients a0,a1, ,an if for all x R, p(x)= anx +an−1x + +a1x+a0.
    [Show full text]
  • Partial Orders for Representing Uncertainty, Causality, and Decision Making: General Properties, Operations, and Algorithms
    Partial Orders are . What We Plan to Do Uncertainty is . Properties of Ordered . Partial Orders for Towards Combining . Representing Uncertainty, Main Result Auxiliary Results Causality, and Decision Proof of the Main Result My Publications Making: General Properties, Home Page Operations, and Algorithms Title Page JJ II Francisco Zapata Department of Computer Science J I University of Texas at El Paso Page1 of 45 500 W. University El Paso, TX 79968, USA Go Back [email protected] Full Screen Close Quit Partial Orders are . What We Plan to Do 1. Partial Orders are Important Uncertainty is . • One of the main objectives of science and engineering Properties of Ordered . is to select the most beneficial decisions. For that: Towards Combining . { we must know people's preferences, Main Result Auxiliary Results { we must have the information about different events Proof of the Main Result (possible consequences of different decisions), and My Publications { since information is never absolutely accurate, we Home Page must have information about uncertainty. Title Page • All these types of information naturally lead to partial orders: JJ II { For preferences, a ≤ b means that b is preferable to J I a. This relation is used in decision theory. Page2 of 45 { For events, a ≤ b means that a can influence b. This Go Back causality relation is used in space-time physics. Full Screen { For uncertain statements, a ≤ b means that a is Close less certain than b (fuzzy logic etc.). Quit Partial Orders are . What We Plan to Do 2. What We Plan to Do Uncertainty is . • In each of the three areas, there is a lot of research Properties of Ordered .
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Monoids and Groups
    1 Monoids and groups 1.1 Definition. A monoid is a set M together with a map M × M ! M; (x; y) 7! x · y such that (i) (x · y) · z = x · (y · z) 8x; y; z 2 M (associativity); (ii) 9e 2 M such that x · e = e · x = x for all x 2 M (e = the identity element of M). 1.2 Examples. 1) Z with addition of integers (e = 0) 2) Z with multiplication of integers (e = 1) 3) Mn(R) = fthe set of all n × n matrices with coefficients in Rg with ma- trix multiplication (e = I = the identity matrix) 4) U = any set P (U) := fthe set of all subsets of Ug P (U) is a monoid with A · B := A [ B and e = ?. 5) Let U = any set F (U) := fthe set of all functions f : U ! Ug F (U) is a monoid with multiplication given by composition of functions (e = idU = the identity function). 1.3 Definition. A monoid is commutative if x · y = y · x for all x; y 2 M. 1.4 Example. Monoids 1), 2), 4) in 1.2 are commutative; 3), 5) are not. 1 1.5 Note. Associativity implies that for x1; : : : ; xk 2 M the expression x1 · x2 ····· xk has the same value regardless how we place parentheses within it; e.g.: (x1 · x2) · (x3 · x4) = ((x1 · x2) · x3) · x4 = x1 · ((x2 · x3) · x4) etc. 1.6 Note. A monoid has only one identity element: if e; e0 2 M are identity elements then e = e · e0 = e0 1.7 Definition.
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 3 Partially Ordered Sets
    Lecture 3 Partially ordered sets Now for something totally different. In life, useful sets are rarely “just” sets. They often come with additional structure. For example, R isn’t useful just because it’s some set. It’s useful because we can add its elements, multiply its elements, and even compare its elements. If A is, for example, the set of all bananas and apples on earth, it’s not as natural to do any of these things with elements of A. Today, we’ll talk about a structure called a partial order. 3.1 Preliminaries First, let me remind you of something called the Cartesian product, or direct product of sets. Definition 3.1.1. Let A and B be sets. Then the Cartesian product of A and B is defined to be the set consisting of all pairs (a, b) where a A and œ b B. We denote the Cartesian product by œ A B. ◊ Example 3.1.2. R2 is the Cartesian product R R. ◊ Example 3.1.3. Let T be the set of all t-shirts in Hiro’s closet, and S the set of all shorts in Hiro’s closet. Then S T represents the collection of all ◊ possible outfits Hiro is willing to consider in August. (I.e., Hiro is willing to consider putting on any of his shorts together with any of his t-shirts.) 23 24 LECTURE 3. PARTIALLY ORDERED SETS Note that we can “repeat” the Cartesian product operation, or apply it many times at once. Example 3.1.4.
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 19: Alternating Group
    MATH 433 Applied Algebra Lecture 19: Alternating group. Abstract groups. Sign of a permutation Theorem 1 For any n ≥ 2 there exists a unique function sgn : S(n) → {−1, 1} such that • sgn(πσ)= sgn(π) sgn(σ) for all π, σ ∈ S(n), • sgn(τ)= −1 for any transposition τ in S(n). A permutation π is called even if it is a product of an even number of transpositions, and odd if it is a product of an odd number of transpositions. It turns out that π is even if sgn(π)=1 and odd if sgn(π)= −1. Theorem 2 (i) sgn(πσ)= sgn(π) sgn(σ) for any π, σ ∈ S(n). (ii) sgn(π−1)= sgn(π) for any π ∈ S(n). (iii) sgn(id) = 1. (iv) sgn(τ)= −1 for any transposition τ. (v) sgn(σ)=(−1)r−1 for any cycle σ of length r. Alternating group Given an integer n ≥ 2, the alternating group on n symbols, denoted An or A(n), is the set of all even permutations in the symmetric group S(n). Theorem (i) For any two permutations π, σ ∈ A(n), the product πσ is also in A(n). (ii) The identity function id is in A(n). (iii) For any permutation π ∈ A(n), the inverse π−1 is in A(n). In other words, the product of even permutations is even, the identity function is an even permutation, and the inverse of an even permutation is even. Theorem The alternating group A(n) has n!/2 elements.
    [Show full text]
  • Theoretical Probability and Statistics
    Theoretical Probability and Statistics Charles J. Geyer Copyright 1998, 1999, 2000, 2001, 2008 by Charles J. Geyer September 5, 2008 Contents 1 Finite Probability Models 1 1.1 Probability Mass Functions . 1 1.2 Events and Measures . 5 1.3 Random Variables and Expectation . 6 A Greek Letters 9 B Sets and Functions 11 B.1 Sets . 11 B.2 Intervals . 12 B.3 Functions . 12 C Summary of Brand-Name Distributions 14 C.1 The Discrete Uniform Distribution . 14 C.2 The Bernoulli Distribution . 14 i Chapter 1 Finite Probability Models The fundamental idea in probability theory is a probability model, also called a probability distribution. Probability models can be specified in several differ- ent ways • probability mass function (PMF), • probability density function (PDF), • distribution function (DF), • probability measure, and • function mapping from one probability model to another. We will meet probability mass functions and probability measures in this chap- ter, and will meet others later. The terms “probability model” and “probability distribution” don’t indicate how the model is specified, just that it is specified somehow. 1.1 Probability Mass Functions A probability mass function (PMF) is a function pr Ω −−−−→ R which satisfies the following conditions: its values are nonnegative pr(ω) ≥ 0, ω ∈ Ω (1.1a) and sum to one X pr(ω) = 1. (1.1b) ω∈Ω The domain Ω of the PMF is called the sample space of the probability model. The sample space is required to be nonempty in order that (1.1b) make sense. 1 CHAPTER 1. FINITE PROBABILITY MODELS 2 In this chapter we require all sample spaces to be finite sets.
    [Show full text]
  • Ordered Sets
    Ordered Sets Motivation When we build theories in political science, we assume that political agents seek the best element in an appropriate set of feasible alternatives. Voters choose their favorite candidate from those listed on the ballot. Citizens may choose between exit and voice when unsatisfied with their government. Consequently, political science theory requires that we can rank alternatives and identify the best element in various sets of choices. Sets whose elements can be ranked are called ordered sets. They are the subject of this lecture. Relations Given two sets A and B, a binary relation is a subset R ⊂ A × B. We use the notation (a; b) 2 R or more often aRb to denote the relation R holding for an ordered pair (a; b). This is read \a is in the relation R to b." If R ⊂ A × A, we say that R is a relation on A. Example. Let A = fAustin, Des Moines, Harrisburgg and let B = fTexas, Iowa, Pennsylvaniag. Then the relation R = f(Austin, Texas), (Des Moines, Iowa), (Harrisburg, Pennsylvania)g expresses the relation \is the capital of." Example. Let A = fa; b; cg. The relation R = f(a; b); (a; c); (b; c)g expresses the relation \occurs earlier in the alphabet than." We read aRb as \a occurs earlier in the alphabet than b." 1 Properties of Binary Relations A relation R on a nonempty set X is reflexive if xRx for each x 2 X complete if xRy or yRx for all x; y 2 X symmetric if for any x; y 2 X, xRy implies yRx antisymmetric if for any x; y 2 X, xRy and yRx imply x = y transitive if xRy and yRz imply xRz for any x; y; z 2 X Any relation which is reflexive and transitive is called a preorder.
    [Show full text]