Angelaki Deleuze and Guattari's Last Enigmatic Message

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Angelaki Deleuze and Guattari's Last Enigmatic Message This article was downloaded by: [Ingenta Content Distribution Psy Press Titles] On: 4 March 2011 Access details: Access Details: [subscription number 911796916] Publisher Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37- 41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK Angelaki Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/title~content=t713405211 Deleuze and Guattari's Last Enigmatic Message Isabelle Stengers To cite this Article Stengers, Isabelle(2005) 'Deleuze and Guattari's Last Enigmatic Message', Angelaki, 10: 2, 151 — 167 To link to this Article: DOI: 10.1080/09697250500417399 URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09697250500417399 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.informaworld.com/terms-and-conditions-of-access.pdf This article may be used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, re-distribution, re-selling, loan or sub-licensing, systematic supply or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae and drug doses should be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims, proceedings, demand or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material. ANGELAKI journal of the theoretical humanities volume 10 number 2 august 2005 experimenting with what is philosophy? or many, Gilles Deleuze’s last message, What Fis Philosophy?, written together with Felix Guattari, came as a surprise, even as something of a disappointment. Indeed, in What is Philosophy? we face a strong differentiation between the creations which are proper to philo- sophy, to science, and to art. I will leave art aside and concentrate on the differentiation between philosophy as a creation of concepts, and science as dealing with functions. More precisely, I will try to approach the striking affirmation that concepts isabelle stengers and functions may well intersect, but only after each has achieved its own specific self-fulfilment. ‘‘It is in their full maturity, and not in the process DELEUZE AND of their constitution, that concepts and functions necessarily intersect, each being created by their GUATTARI’S LAST 1 own specific means.’’ ENIGMATIC MESSAGE This affirmation, proposed without any expla- nation, has caused many to wonder or even to feel betrayed. Deleuze and Guattari were associated with the affirmation of productive connexions, the creation of deterritorializing processes escaping This question will be my starting point. But I fixed identities, transgressing boundaries and static will not stay within Deleuze and Guattari’s text classifications, destroying the power of exclusive but rather follow Deleuze’s own advice: we disjunction, that is the either/or alternatives, such should be interested in tools for thinking, not as, for instance, doing either science or philosophy. in an exegesis of ideas. An idea is always engaged Many would have anticipated a joyful celebration in what he called a matter, always a specific one. Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution Psy Press Titles] At: 22:32 4 March 2011 of a free experimental interplay between scientific An idea needs to be so engaged in order for the references and philosophical ones. Some would how and the why this idea indeed matters, have taken for granted that the open character of the kind of difference it makes, to come into the process of the constitution of scientific enun- processual existence, what Deleuze calls ‘‘actua- ciations would have been emphasized, as well as its lization’’ or ‘‘effectuation.’’ This is all the more undetermined boundaries with politics, econom- so when we deal with the enigma of a choice: the ics, cultural imperialism, and so on. Why did they ‘‘why’’ of this choice should not lead back to choose to produce a seemingly ‘‘classical picture,’’ the authors’ intentions; it is a question that puts with a mature science facing a mature philosophy, the reader of What is Philosophy? at risk, a as illustrated by ‘‘great philosophers’’? question the answer to which must be created ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/05/020151^17 ß 2005 Taylor & Francis and the Editors of Angelaki DOI: 10.1080/09697250500417399 151 last enigmatic message and effectuated following a line that belongs specific ‘‘bad will,’’ what forces it to think and neither to the initiators nor to the reader but create, as opposed to goodwill, being allowed to happens ‘‘between them.’’ think by consensual evidence. Even the joyful Not commenting but effectuating means experi- affirmation of productive connexions may turn menting with a line that is not that of the book, but into ‘‘goodwill,’’ leading ‘‘to an absolute disaster which, if the effectuation is not a failure, should for thought whatever its benefits might be, connect different aspects of this book that other- of course, from the viewpoint of universal wise would appear as independent. The effectua- capitalism.’’5 tion line I will experiment with stems from my The experimentation on What is Philosophy? I conviction that, in spite of the seemingly ‘‘classi- will propose stems from this guess. I will try and cal’’ outlook of What is Philosophy?, which address disappointed Deleuzian ‘‘friends,’’ who disappointed many readers, this book may well wonder about Deleuze’s suddenly ‘‘acritical’’ turn, be the most ‘‘political’’ of Deleuze’s books.2 It is who deplore the fact that he seems to have his one book that addresses its reader as if he were suddenly forgotten he has been thinking all his perhaps a friend, but at that twilight hour ‘‘when life ‘‘against’’ the image of thought associated with one distrusts even the friend,’’ even the one who dominant philosophy, and has chosen to celebrate had most enthusiastically followed the great open- all ‘‘great philosophers.’’ I will experiment with ing of possibilities that Deleuzian themes have the feeling that, at this twilight hour, What is inspired. Here, the crucial problem may well be Philosophy? asks us to consider what Deleuze’s that ‘‘we lack resistance to the present,’’3 and to favourite ‘‘conceptual persona,’’ the idiot, keeps resist here does not mean to criticize or to saying while others hurry towards consensual denounce but to construct. goals: that ‘‘there may be something more For instance, when we read that ‘‘philosophers important.’’ ‘‘Something more important’’ does have not been sufficiently concerned with the not mean something which would transcend our 4 nature of the concept as philosophical reality,’’ disagreements and reconcile us around a sacred the point would not be, or would not only be, to cause. The idiot is unable to mobilize or convince; deal with a question of special interest for perhaps he can slow down the mobilization and philosophers, a closure on a professional domain, have some mobilized certainties stutter. it would be part of the problem of this lack of The idiot will never acknowledge that some- resistance, a problem that science and probably art body has correctly understood what was more also share, entailing the very strong likelihood of important. It is the task for everyone to learn and their destruction. But the point is also not ‘‘how to feel where and how his or her slowing down and avoid destruction’’ as if it were the central stuttering actually happened. My experimental question, as if our world would lose its very soul reading stems from the feeling that Deleuze and if philosophy, or science, or art were to become Guattari were both addressing their epoch, that is part of a destroyed past. If, as I read it, What is their friends, and distrusting it and them, asking Philosophy? is indeed a political book, the point is Downloaded By: [Ingenta Content Distribution Psy Press Titles] At: 22:32 4 March 2011 us to think with the epochal fact that bad will as that learning how to resist is a task which tolerates such can no longer be taken for granted. This is no economy. No great masterword (mot d’ordre) why my reading will take the reader to a still more designating a common enemy may spare those who belong to a threatened practice from asking acritical position. It may well be that what we what kind of specific vulnerability this enemy is vitally need now is to honour what forces us to exploiting since he (or it) does not need to use escape goodwill and consensual thought, what violent, repressive means. Thus the seemingly indeed causes us to diverge and to think, each modest task of a ‘‘pedagogy of the concept’’ may with diverging means. And it may well be that well be the only way for philosophy to situate itself what we have to honour will designate us as among other threatened practices, each from the survivors, having to disentangle ourselves from point of view of its own specific capacity to resist. all the words which designated our survival as For each of them, the point would be its own something we did deserve. 152 stengers matters of fact and states of affairs dramatize this challenge I will designate them all using the opposite term that I suspect the Let us first address the question of scientific translators wished to avoid: ‘‘matters of fact.’’ functions, and begin with a small problem It seems that Deleuze and Guattari accept that of translation. When the translators of What is functions may be defined by a reference which Philosophy? dealt with the claim that scientific would be characterized as a ‘‘matter of fact,’’ that functions refer to ‘‘des e´tats de choses,’’ they chose is as ‘‘holding together’’ by themselves, and not as to translate ‘‘e´tats de choses’’ as ‘‘states of affairs.’’ obtaining their definition from the states of affairs This has rather strange consequences when those and the power dimensions that those states of ‘‘states of affairs’’ are contrasted with ‘‘things’’ affairs include.
Recommended publications
  • Surrationalism After Bachelard: Michel Serres and Le Nouveau Nouvel Esprit Scientifique Massimiliano Simons
    parrhesia 31 · 2019 · 60-84 surrationalism after bachelard: michel serres and le nouveau nouvel esprit scientifique massimiliano simons 1. INTRODUCTION The work of Michel Serres, if considered at all, is often presented as a radical break with or criticism of the work of Gaston Bachelard. This is sometimes also endorsed by Serres himself, who in an interview stated: Yes, I wrote my thesis under Bachelard, but l thought privately that the “new scientific spirit” coming into fashion at that time lagged way behind the sciences. ... The model it offered of the sciences could not, for me, pass as contemporary. This new spirit seemed to me quite old. And so, this milieu was not mine.1 Bruno Latour, in a similar vein, has described Serres as the anti-Bachelard.2 Within this context the project of Bachelard is described as a naive belief in the rational- ity of science or as a misguided project to purify science from all non-scientific el- ements. For instance, in his own work, Latour, inspired by Serres, uses Bachelard as the perfect illustration of the paradox of modernity he is attacking: Gaston Bachelard’s dual enterprise—which […] exaggerates the objectiv- ity of the sciences by dint of breaking with common sense, and symmetri- cally exaggerates the objectless power of the imaginary by dint of episte- mological breaks—offers the perfect symbol for this impossible crisis, this drawing and quartering.3 This image, however, is too simplistic and in fact makes us unable to really appre- ciate what we can learn from the work of Bachelard today.
    [Show full text]
  • Capitalist Sorcery: Breaking the Spell
    Capitalist Sorcery Breaking the Spell Philippe Pignarre Paris, France and Isabelle Stengers Université Libre de Bruxelles, Belgium Translated and edited by Andrew Goffey -W “%“"" /~q‘.` fr." $]“"**\ 'JL _f .’?"":\ " IQ ;-’°°*w.' 3 E, 3 Li f"°~*-7; ‘cs 55 gwusff' ., ,~-. if - .2 5 \._*w4{ 4 '» . 65; a'q,_,,»r' !~ *_/‘ \./ ¢w».;m ‘­ 9 man? I _r l' I AN ?fu\’/WN,zmv; f iz ,._\,'\,,,-al; { E © Editions LA DECOUVERTE, Paris, France, 2005, 2007 Translation and Introduction © Andrew Goffey 2011 All rights reserved. No reproduction, copy or transmission of this publication may be made without written permission. No portion of this publication may be reproduced, copied or transmitted save with written permission or in accordance with the provisions of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, or under the terms of any licence permitting limited copying issued by the Copyright Licensing Agency, Saffron House, 6-10 Kirby Street, London EC1N BTS. Any person who does any unauthorized act in relation to this publication may be liable to criminal prosecution and civil claims for damages. The authors have asserted their rights to be identified as the authors of this work in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. English translation first published 2011 by PALGRAVE MACMILLAN Palgrave Macmillan in the UK is an imprint of Macmillan Publishers Limited, registered in England, company number 785998, of Houndmills, Basingstoke Hampshire RG21 6XS. Palgrave Macmillan in the US is a division of St Martin's Press LLC, 175 Fifth Avenue, New York, NY 10010. Palgrave Macmillan is the global academic imprint of the above companies and has companies and representatives throughout the world.
    [Show full text]
  • P-70 Stengers Foreword
    Stengers’shibbolet Bruno Latour 1997 (foreword) Isabelle Stengers, Power and Invention, University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis -Would you say that Isabelle Stengers is the greatest French philosopher of science? -Yes, except she is from Belgium a country that exists only in part and where, contrary to France, the link between science and the state is nil. -Would you say that she is the philosophical right-hand of the Nobel Prize winner of chemistry Ilya Prigogine? -Yes, since she wrote several books with him, and yet she has spent the rest of her life trying to escape from the mass of lunatics attracted to this “New Alliance” between science and culture they both wrote together. -Is she an historian of science? -Hard to say. Although she wrote extensively on Galileo, on XIXth century thermodynamics, on chemistry1, she remains a philosopher interested in what her physicists and chemists colleagues should understand of their science. Her main object of attention is modern science, and this is what historians and philosophers should study together, no? -You are not going to say that she is an internalist philosopher of science, are you? -Worse than that, Isabelle Stengers is an “hyperinternalist” forcing you always to go further towards a small number of theoretical decisions made by her scientific colleagues. In her eyes, most scientists are often not internalist enough. -But at least don’t tell us that she is a whiggish historian of science looking, like Gaston Bachelard or Georges Canguilhem, for the ways by which hard science finally escapes from history? -She is, I am afraid, much worse.
    [Show full text]
  • Didier Debaise and Benedikte Zitouni in Conversation with Isabelle Doucet
    Architectural Theory Review ISSN: 1326-4826 (Print) 1755-0475 (Online) Journal homepage: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/ratr20 Narrate, Speculate, Fabulate: Didier Debaise and Benedikte Zitouni in Conversation with Isabelle Doucet Isabelle Doucet, Didier Debaise & Benedikte Zitouni To cite this article: Isabelle Doucet, Didier Debaise & Benedikte Zitouni (2018) Narrate, Speculate, Fabulate: Didier Debaise and Benedikte Zitouni in Conversation with Isabelle Doucet, Architectural Theory Review, 22:1, 9-23, DOI: 10.1080/13264826.2018.1418130 To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/13264826.2018.1418130 Published online: 08 Mar 2018. Submit your article to this journal Article views: 110 View related articles View Crossmark data Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=ratr20 Interview NARRATE, SPECULATE, FABULATE: DIDIER DEBAISE AND BENEDIKTE ZITOUNI IN CONVERSATION WITH ISABELLE DOUCET Isabelle Doucet School of Environment, Education and Development, The University of Manchester, Manchester, UK Email: [email protected] Didier Debaise FNRS - Université Libre de Bruxelles (ULB), Brussels, Belgium Benedikte Zitouni Centre for Sociological Studies, Saint-Louis University of Brussels, Brussels, Belgium Article History: Received 11 December 2017; accepted 11 December 2017 On Monday, 25 September 2017, I convened a conversation with philosopher Didier Debaise and social scientist Benedikte Zitouni in Brussels, and meandered between French and English discussing the ways in which we study and research the world. This “world” is, for Benedikte, a world of activist urban practices, nineteenth- century urban planning in Brussels, urban agriculture, and eco-feminism, whilst Didier studies, as a philosopher, the concepts, ideas, and regimes of thought through which philosophers have guided us to study reality, nature, and science.
    [Show full text]
  • A Review of Isabelle Stengers
    What Is Given in Experience? Bruno Latour Every synthesis begins “anew” and has to be taken up from the start as if for the first time. —Isabelle Stengers, Penser avec Whitehead: Une libre et sauvage creation de concepts It could be one of those little games journalists play on television talk shows about books: “Who was the greatest philosopher of the twentieth century whose name begins with W?” Most learned people in America would answer “Wittgenstein.” Sorry. The right answer is “Whitehead”—another philosopher whose name begins with W, to be sure, but one who is vastly more daring, and also, unfortunately, much less studied. Among his many misfortunes, Whitehead had the very bad one of provoking too much interest among theologians and too little among epistemologists. His reputation in America is thus skewed toward his theological innovations to the detriment of his epistemological theories. He also suffers from the terrible stigma of having indulged in metaphysics, something one is no longer supposed to do after the edicts of the first “W,” even though those who think that metaphysics is passé know usually much less science than Whitehead and swallow—without an ounce of criticism—hook, line, and sinker the entirety of metaphysical beliefs about nature that one can easily derive by lumping together the least-common-denominator views of geneticists and so-called cognitive scientists. As Isabelle Stengers says in her recently published masterpiece about Whitehead, “critical consciousness admits so many things without criticizing them” (74). What makes Stengers’s book, Penser avec Whitehead—in English, “to think with Whitehead”—such an important work for Anglo-American philosophy is that in it the greatest philosopher of the twentieth century is finally studied in great detail by someone who is one of the most innovative philosophers of science of the present time.
    [Show full text]
  • Composing with Gaia: Isabelle Stengers and the Feminist Politics of the Earth MIRIAM TOLA
    PhænEx 11, no. 1 (spring/summer 2016): 1-21 © 2016 Miriam Tola Composing with Gaia: Isabelle Stengers and the Feminist Politics of the Earth MIRIAM TOLA In her recent writings philosopher of science Isabelle Stengers reworks the figure of Gaia, the living planet, as a way to disrupt the fantasy of human exceptionalism and consider what political practices might open up livable worlds beyond the grip of capitalism. Building on, and simultaneously departing from, the work of scientists James Lovelock and Lynn Margulis, Stengers describes Gaia as an assemblage of forces largely indifferent to human reasons and projects, and draws attention to the multiple regimes of existence that characterize life on earth. If the prevalent narrative of the Anthropocene presents an undifferentiated human species as the dominant geological force on earth,1 Gaia is a figure for the post-Anthropocene that puts pressure on the idea of Man [sic] as the primary force making the world. The first part of this essay situates Stengers’s political use of Gaia theory in current debates on the Anthropocene. The second part considers how the figure of Gaia intersects with feminist attempts to challenge the Western divide between humans endowed with agency and malleable natural resources deprived of political relevance. I argue that Stengers’s reworking of Gaia helps in reconsidering the relations between two bodies of feminist literature. The first body of work comprises a range of Deleuzian feminists who bring to the fore the earthly forces that enable and vastly exceed the scope of human existence. The second includes ecofeminist perspectives, including Marxist ecofeminism, that focus on the ways in which the current political economy feeds on the enclosure of social reproduction and nature’s productivity.
    [Show full text]
  • Isabelle Stengers
    The Invention of Modern Science Isabelle Stengers Translated by Daniel IV. Smith Theory out of Bounds Volume 19 M IN NE SO TA University of Minnesota Press Minneapolis • London This translation would not have been possible without the support of a Vice-Chancellor’s Postdoctoral Fellowship in the School of Philosophy at the University of New South Wales, whose generosity is gratefully acknowledged. Copyright 2000 by the Regents of the University of Minnesota Originally published as Llnvemion des sciences modemes (Paris: La Decouverte, 1993). Copyright 1993 Gius. Laterz.a & Figli Spa, Roma-Bari. This book is a result of the cooperation between Laterza Publishing House and Sigma Tau Foundation in the “Lezioni Italiane” series. The English-language edition has been arranged through the mediation of Eulama Literary Agency. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior written permission of the publisher. Published by the University of Minnesota Press 111 Third Avenue South, Suite 290 Minneapolis, MK 55401-2520 http://www.upress.umn.edu Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper LIBRARY OF CONGRESS C AT A LOG 1NTG-I N - PI B L1 C ATIO N DATA Stengers, Isabelle. [Invention des sciences modemes. English] The invention of modern science / Isabelle Stengers ; translated by Daniel W . Smith, p. cm. — (Theory out of bounds ; v. 19) Includes bibliographical references (p. ) and index. ISBN 0-8166-3055-0 (he : acid-free paper) — ISBN 0-8166-3056-9 (pb : acid-free paper) 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Table of Content
    2. Philosophy – Sections & Papers 2.1 Process Philosophy Section Head: Leemon McHenry Wednesday, July 5, afternoon Room: HS 102 Session 1 1 Pierfrancesco Basile Dr. Swiss National Foundation Zürich Postal Code: 8049 Switzerland Phone:0041-044-341 65 84 fax: 0041-044.341 65 84 e-mail: [email protected] Experience All the Way Down: the Reinterpretation of Leibniz in James Ward and Alfred North Whitehead Abstract: In the preface to Process and Reality (1929) Whitehead indicates the following among the “contemporary school of though” and authors to which he believes that his own attempt to develop a metaphysical theory of reality is indebted: English and American realism (Nunn), process philosophy and pragmatism (Bergson, James, Dewey), British absolute idealism (Bradley). No mention is made of the Cambridge philosopher James Ward (1843-1925), author among others of two significant series of Gifford Lectures entitled Naturalism and Agnosticism (1899) and The Realm of Ends: Pluralism and Theism (1911). Focussing mainly on this latter work, the paper examines some rather striking similarities in the philosophies of the two thinkers, arguing that some of Whitehead’s conceptual breakthroughs are already anticipated by Ward’s attempt to develop a revised version of Leibniz’s monadism as a pluralistic yet spiritualistic alternative to Bradley’s absolute idealism. From a philosophical point of view, the aim of the paper is to evaluate the motivations leading both philosophers towards a panpsychic conception of the ultimate nature of reality. 2 John Lango Professor Department of Philosophy Hunter College 695 Park Avenue New York, NY 10021 USA Phone: 212-769-4022 e-mail: [email protected] Whitehead's Philosophy of Time Abstract: Presumably, process philosophy takes time seriously.
    [Show full text]
  • A Review of Isabelle Stengers ’Penser Avec Whitehead’ Bruno Latour
    What is Given in Experience ? A Review of Isabelle Stengers ’Penser avec Whitehead’ Bruno Latour To cite this version: Bruno Latour. What is Given in Experience ? A Review of Isabelle Stengers ’Penser avec Whitehead’. Boundary 2, 2005, 32 (1), pp.222-237. hal-01020582 HAL Id: hal-01020582 https://hal-sciencespo.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01020582 Submitted on 8 Jul 2014 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. What Is Given in Experience? Bruno Latour Every synthesis begins “anew” and has to be taken up from the start as if for the first time. —Isabelle Stengers, Penser avec Whitehead: Une libre et sauvage creation de concepts It could be one of those little games journalists play on television talk shows about books: “Who was the greatest philosopher of the twentieth century whose name begins with W?” Most learned people in America would answer “Wittgenstein.” Sorry. The right answer is “Whitehead”—another philosopher whose name begins with W, to be sure, but one who is vastly more daring, and also, unfortunately, much less studied. Among his many misfortunes, Whitehead had the very bad one of provoking too much interest among theologians and too little among epistemologists.
    [Show full text]
  • Isabelle Stengers' an Ecology of Practices
    Copyright ofFull Text rests with the original copyright owner and, except as permitted under the Copyright Act 1968, copying this copyright material is prohibited without the permission ofthe owner or 111111111111111 its exclusive licensee or agent or by way ofa licence 200504057 from Copyright Agency Limited. For information about such licences contact Copyright Agency Limited on (02) 93947600 (ph) or (02) 93947601 (fax) introductory notes on an ecology of practices ISABELLE STENGERS Prepared for an ANU Humanities Research Centre Symposium in early August 2003, these notes may be considered as a comment on Brian Massumi's proposition that 'a political ecology would be a social technology of belonging, assuming coexistence and co-becoming as the habitat of practices'. I . PHYSICS AND ITS HABITAT Let us start with a not-so-simple example, since it follows the path along which I encoun­ tered this idea of ecology-that of scientific practices and, more particularly, physics. Physics as a practice is in dire need of a new habitat, since from its birth as the first so­ called 'modem science' its claims were entangled with its historical 'habitat'. Since then, how­ ever, the claims have survived, but not the habitat. Asa result, the way physics presents itself now, the way it defines 'physical reality', is by way of persistent but now freely floating theologtco-pohucal claims referring to the opposition between the world as understood from that an intelligible point of view (which may be associated with divine creation) and the worldas wemeetit and interact withit. As a result ofdefining 'physical reality' as the objective and beyond our merely human fictions, physics claims for itselfa exclusive position ofjudge­ ment over and against all other 'realities', including those of all other sciences.
    [Show full text]
  • Cosmoecological Sheep and the Arts of Living on a Damaged Planet
    Cosmoecological Sheep and the Arts of Living on a Damaged Planet VINCIANE DESPRET Department of Philosophy, University of Liège, Belgium MICHEL MEURET French National Institute for Agricultural Research, Joint Research Unit Selmet, Montpellier, France Abstract In recent decades, in the South of France some young people from urban back- grounds have chosen to become shepherds and to learn to reconnect with the herding prac- tices that many livestock breeders had abandoned under the pressure of agricultural mod- ernization policies. In some cases they have found themselves entrusted with sheep that are as naive about herding as they themselves were. Before their introduction to transhumance— seasonal movement between pastures—these animals were primarily confined and fed in- doors or in small fenced areas. The shepherds had to learn how to lead, how to understand other modes of living, how to teach their sheep what is edible and what is not, and how to form a flock; the sheep had to learn how to “compose with” dogs and humans, to acquire new feeding habits, a new ethos, and moreover, new ways of living in an enlarged world. These practices cannot be reduced to a livestock economy: shepherds consider herding a work of transformation and ecological recuperation—of the land, of the sheep, of ways of being to- gether. Learning the “arts of living on a damaged planet,” as Anna Tsing has termed it, hu- mans and animals are making their own contributions to a new cosmoecology, creating cos- moecological connections and contributing to what Ghassan Hage has called alter-politics. Keywords cosmoecology, cosmopolitics, sheep, shepherds, multispecies, ethology, ethics I have especially been swayed by Donna Haraway’s conviction that there is something about our everyday engagements with other kinds of creatures that opens new kinds of possibilities for relating and understanding.
    [Show full text]
  • Reflections on Etienne Souriau's Les Différents Modes D'existence1
    Reflections on Etienne Souriau’s 1 Les différents modes d'existence Bruno Latour translated by Stephen Muecke « Reflections on Etienne Souriau’s Les Modes d’existence », in (edited by Graham Harman, Levi Bryant and Nick Srnicek The Speculative Turn Continental Materialism and Realism re.press Australi, pp. 304-333, Melbourne, Australie] http://www.re-press.org/book- files/OA_Version_Speculative_Turn_9780980668346.pdf ‘There is no ideal existence, the ideal is not a type of existence.’2 —Étienne Souriau If we have never been modern, then what history are we supposed to inherit? For twenty years or so, I have been interested in the following question: if we have never been modern, then what has happened to us? This question is relevant to history and anthropology, as well as to the philosophy of the period that Whitehead describes with the phrase ‘the bifurcation of nature’.3 This bifurcation begins somewhere between Galileo and Locke and comes to an end, in Whitehead's opinion, with William James. This brief period, which I call ‘the modernist parenthesis’—during 1 I would like to thank Isabelle Stengers for having led me to Étienne Souriau (and to Whitehead, and to so many authors I would never have approached without her constant tutoring). The book under discussion is Souriau's Les différents modes d'existence, originally published by Presses Universitaires de France in 1943. The book was republished in 2009, also by PUF, with an introduction by Isabelle Stengers and Bruno Latour. 2 Étienne Souriau, Les différents modes d'existence, Paris, Presses Universitaires de France, 1943, p. 157.
    [Show full text]