Leibniz's Two Legacies. Their Implications for Knowledge

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Leibniz's Two Legacies. Their Implications for Knowledge Witold Marciszewski holds the chair of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Witold Marciszewski Science at Warsaw University, Poland. Warsaw University, Poland Mcmber ofLcibniz Gescllschaft.Presi­ dentofFoundationforInfOlmatics,Logie and Mathematics, Poland. Editor of the electronic joumal Mathesis Universalis Leibniz'sTw o Legacies. for "Logic andIntelligence, Mechanized Dcduction, Lcibnizian Perspective", as­ Their Implications fo r sociated with LogBank - a database for logic, informatics, etc. Authorofscveral Knowledge Engineering books relevant to the Marciszcwski, W.: Leibniz' two legacies and their implica­ knowledge, and (2) his implicit questioning of the same tions regarding lm owledge engineering. possibility because ofthe role attributed by him to percep­ Know!.Org. 23(1996)No.2, 1'.77-83, 37 refs. tion as characteristic of organic life. Knowledge engineering anticipated by Leibniz in such projects The former makes him closer to Alan Turing as a as ideal language for science reasoning automata, library pioneer of hard AI, the latter - to John von Neumann as organization, etc. owes to him philosophical presuppositions as to the scope of possible automation. The paper deals with an one who acknowledged peculiarities of organisms, seeing ambiguity in his position. His attitude as an engineer implies their enormous advantages over electronic devices. hard AI (as represented by A. Turing) while his metaphysical These views, though opposing each other, have a point insights involve an insuperable physical difference between in common, to wit either makes a stand against Dcscartes' organisms and artificial machines, which is highly relevant to conceptions of mind and knowledge; thus Descartes efficiency ofinformation processing (this physicalism claiming provides us with a remarkable contrastive background to the importofhardware, accords with J. vonNeumann's insights). better perceive Leibniz's two approaches3• The paper's sections: 1. Leibniz VS. Descartes in views on knowledge. 2. On physicalism and anti physicalism in logic. 3. To express Descartes' position in a most concise way, Turing's claim as to the insignificance of hardware. 4. Von let us put it as fo llows: 'the mind does not belong to the Neumann's claim as to the significance of hardware. 5. Why same world to which matter does ' (cp Ryle [1949]). Thus Leibniz would not have accepted logical physicalism. 6. Why Descartes has created the paradigm of a physics-inde­ Leibniz would have accepted logical physicalism. (Author) pendent theory of mind; the article "the" is to hint at the enormous impact of that theory, to the extent of its becoming a commonsense approach (extremities of be� 1. Leibniz vs Descartes in Views on Knowledge haviouris111 may be partly explained as a revolutionary Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646-1716), who antici­ reaction to that paradigm). Leibniz's point results from pated so enormous areas of modern knowledge, is also a denying that denial, so that it reads 'the mind 'does' forerunner of what we nowadays call 'knowledge engi­ belong' (etc). Thus Leibniz paves the way to what nowa­ neering' - by his creations of library systems and his days starts to be called 'physics of mind' (cp Penrose proj ects of collective research, the latter fruitfully mate­ [1988]). rialized with the etablishing of learned societies and Now, there arehvo theoreti cally possible concretisations ministries of science according to some of his projectsl. of this general point: either (1) one reduces thought to We need this term to cover the issues of both correct matter (as, eg, in hard AI), or (2) one acknowledges their 'producing' and efficient 'organizing and managing ' distinctness and interaction (as, eg, Popper and Eccles human knowledge. The former is traditionally handled by [1997]; as to hard and weak AI, cp Gams [1995]). Leibniz epistemology and logic, including methodology of sci­ in his philosophy never endorsed (1) but in his practical ences, the latter - by a cluster of new specialized knowledge-engineering projects he came close to it, while disciplines. However, these two fields are not unrelated to in the main stream of his philosophy it was point (2) each other. To use an example to suggest the argument, which he firmly held. In this sense we can speak of let it be recalled that the procedures offonnalizing proofs, Leibniz's two legacies. His approaching point (1) was though belonging to the sphere of mathematical produc­ connected with the idea of his 'ars combinatoria' as a tion (and so handled by mathematical logic ) turned out to universal method ofproblem solving which was combina­ be an indispensable tool for databases, in particular tory and finitist, hence feasible for mechanical devices. mathematical ones, which belong to the domain ofknow 1- In the sequel, the fairly 'materialistic' point (as that of edge organization and managementz. strong AI) is designated by the term 'anti-physicalism' Let us start from a comparison of Leibniz views to and the opposite one by 'physicalism'; this terminology those of Rene Descartes (1596-1650). Why should we may seem rather odd, but is justifiedas fo llows. The view start in this way? The answer is as fo llows. There are two that physical devices (mechanical, electronic, etc) in views of Leibniz to be discussed in this essay, which principle (technical complications notwithstanding) can oppose each other, namely (1) his explicit belief in the do the same job as organisms and minds do, involves the possibility of automation of the processes of producing irrelevance of a physical kind of hardware: it is not matter Know!. Org. 23(1996)No.2 77 Witold Marciszewski: Leibniz's Two Legacies https://doi.org/10.5771/0943-7444-1996-2-77 Generiert durch IP '170.106.35.234', am 27.09.2021, 09:57:11. Das Erstellen und Weitergeben von Kopien dieses PDFs ist nicht zulässig. · but software what matters. Thus the stress put on the 2. On Physicalism and Alltiphysicalism ill Logic import of what constitutes a physical component deserves Physicalism holds human thoughts and acts to be to be denoted as 'physicalism', while its opposite is called determined by physical laws (Webster [1971]). Logical 'antiphysicalism' . Physicalism, LP for short, holds reasoning processes to be Before we enter into the discusion of both approaches, determined by laws deriving from physical properties of it is in order to hint at their implications for knowledge the brain, hence from some hardware properties. engineering. Knowledge is produced by intelligence, In the heroic times of logical empiricism people used hence a step is needed towards a theory of intelligence as to employ the term 'physicalism' in a different sense; that data-processing faculty. Let us assume that in producing stmy, though, seems to be half-forgotten, so one can give knowledge three kinds of data processing are involved this word a new meaning, as suggested in Marciszewski and three skills respectively, to wit 'reasoning' (includ­ and Murawski [1995]. An alternativesuggestion is due to ing computing), 'abstraction ', and 'ordering'. Reason­ Schnelle [1988) who uses the phrase 'naturalization of ing with computing is the unique member of this triad logic'. However, it seems desirable to have a term related which so far, to some extent, has been successfully to the phrase 'physics of thought' (see below). Moreover, mechanized, lhat is, made feasible for machines, esp. the use of the adjective 'natural' in contexts like 'natural electronic ones; hence it plays a special role in the present logic' has been already established for what Gentzen discussion (cp Marciszewski and Murawski [1995]). called 'das natiirliche Schliessen '. As to reasoning, therefore, we can already sec its role It was the famous physicist Roger Penrose [1988) who in knowledge organization and engineering, for instance was bold enough to claim inquiries into ' the mathematics that of inferential mechanism in expert systems and olldphysics of thought'. His ideas can be combined in a databases. As for the other skills, the question is not fertile way with those ofJohn von Neumann [1958) which settled yet in an empirical way, hence a support should be prove crucial fo r the story in question. expected from philosophy. Abstraction is a subject-mat­ However, when associating physics with logic and a ter of AI research but at a most primitive stage, namely theory of mind, one has to regard the strong hold over that of pattern recognition (from that to, eg, abstracting philosophers got by the Cartesian paradigm concerning transfinite cardinals is a rather long way). Should we, for the mind-matter relations. With respect to that paradigm, the future, envisage its fu ll mastering by electronic de­ any phrase like "the physics of thought" is even worse vices, as antiphysicalism does claim? If so, then it is worth than a philosophical heresy; it is felt as a category­ while to devote time and money to such a promising mistake, like saying that numbers happen to be warm, or research. Ifnot, then it is wiser to spare resources for more that some thoughts are yellow. The term 'categ01Y­ feasible and payable AI projects. mistake ' is due to Ryle [1949]. In the same book the The same dilemma appears with regard to the skill of Cartesian doctrine is rendered as fo llows. "Human bodies ordering which includes creation of structures, as math­ [ ...) are subject to the mechanical laws which govern all ematical, syntactic, musical, technical, political ones, etc other bodies in space. [ ... J Minds are not in space, nor are (if we endorse such interpretation of Georg Cantor's well­ their operations subject to mechanical laws." (p. l1). ordering theorem)4. When the mechanical laws (like those stated by Newton) The ordering issue turns to be even more involved than are identified with the totality of physical laws, the mind­ the abstraction issue, since any non-trivial ordering pre­ body problem is doomed to be "solved" either in the supposes acts of assessing certain values.
Recommended publications
  • From Physics to Physicalism
    FROM PHYSICS TO PHYSICALISM a version of this paper is published in Physicalism and its Discontents ed, Gillett and Loewer Cambridge University Press 2001 Introduction Hilary Putnam explains that: The appeal of materialism lies precisely in this, in its claim to be natural metaphysics within the bounds of science. That a doctrine which promises to gratify our ambition (to know the noumenal) and our caution (not to be unscientific) should have great appeal is hardly something to be wondered at. (Putnam (1983), p.210) Materialism says that all facts, in particular all mental facts, obtain in virtue of the spatio- temporal distribution, and properties, of matter. It was, as Putnam says, “metaphysics within the bounds of science”, but only so long as science was thought to say that the world is made out of matter.1 In this century physicists have learned that there is more in the world than matter and, in any case, matter isn’t quite what it seemed to be. For this reason many philosophers who think that metaphysics should be informed by science advocate physicalism in place of materialism. Physicalism claims that all facts obtain in virtue of the distribution of the fundamental entities and properties –whatever they turn out to be- of completed fundamental physics. Later I will discuss a more precise formulation. But not all contemporary philosophers embrace physicalism. Some- and though a minority not a small or un-influential one- think that physicalism is rather the metaphysics for an unjustified scientism; i.e. it is scientistic metaphysics. Those among them that think that physicalism can be clearly formulated think that it characterizes a cold, colorless, unfeeling and uninteresting world and not, they think, the world we live in.
    [Show full text]
  • Divine Idealism As Physicalism? Reflections on the Structural Definition of Physicalism
    DIVINE IDEALISM AS PHYSICALISM? REFLECTIONS ON THE STRUCTURAL DEFINITION OF PHYSICALISM Jon W. Thompson Hempel’s Dilemma remains at the center of the problem of defining phys- icalism. In brief, the dilemma asks whether physicalism should be defined by appeal to current or future physics. If defined by current physics, phys- icalism is almost certainly false. If defined by an ideal future physics, then physicalism has little determinable content. Montero and Papineau have innovatively suggested that the dilemma may be avoided by defining phys- icalism structurally. While their definition is one among many definitions, it is significant in that—if successful—it would break the impasse for defining physicalism. I argue, however, that the structural definition fails because it counts metaphysical frameworks (crucially, versions of divine idealism) as “physicalist”—an unwelcome result for physicalists. This paper thus furthers the debate on the definition of physicalism and sheds light on the relationship between physicalism and idealism. 1. Hempel’s Dilemma Physicalism is often defined as the view that all that exists is what physics studies; but many voices have raised concerns over such a definition. In- deed, the problem of defining physicalism has been with us for some time now.1 “Hempel’s Dilemma” puts the problem in exacting focus: when the physicalist claims that all that exists is physical, is she claiming that [A] All that exists is what is studied by current physics or that [B] All that exists is what is studied by some ideal, perhaps future, physics?2 If the physi- calist intends [A], then physicalism is clearly false.
    [Show full text]
  • An Immaterial Thing: the Case for Dualism Today We Turn to Our Second Big Question: What Are You?
    What am I? An immaterial thing: the case for dualism Today we turn to our second big question: What are you? We can focus this question a little bit by introducing the idea of a physical or material thing. To a first approximation, a material thing is a thing entirely composed of the sorts of things described in physics: electrons, quarks, etc. Materialism, or physicalism, in general is the claim that every thing — every thing that exists — is a material thing. There are two views opposed to materialism. One is dualism. According to dualism (as the name suggests) there are two sorts of things: material things, and immaterial things. The second opposed view is idealism. According to idealism, there are no material things, and everything that exists is immaterial. According to materialism about human beings, you are material thing. You are something which, like tables, clouds, trees, and amoebae, is entirely composed of the basic particles studied in physics. According to materialism about human beings, you are material thing. You are something which, like tables, clouds, trees, and amoebae, is entirely composed of the basic particles studied in physics. Many of the ways we ordinarily think and talk about ourselves seem to suggest that we endorse materialism about ourselves. Consider, for example, the question of whether you are currently sitting in a chair. Could an immaterial thing occupy space, and sit in a chair? But other ways that we think and talk about ourselves suggest that we think of ourselves as immaterial things. For example, many people think that it is possible for human beings to enjoy life after death, and hence to exist even after one’s body has ceased to exist; and to many it has seemed easiest to understand how this could be possible if think of ourselves, not as immaterial bodies, but as immaterial souls or minds.
    [Show full text]
  • Physicalism and the Possibility of Life After Death
    Resurrection of the Body?: Physicalism and the Possibility of Life After Death The 2012 Winifred E. Weter Faculty Award Lecture Seattle Pacific University April 17, 2012 Rebekah L.H. Rice, Ph.D. Associate Professor of Philosophy College of Arts and Sciences Resurrection of the Body?: Physicalism and the Possibility of Life After Death 2012 Winifred E. Weter Lecture April 17, 2012 Seattle Pacific University Rebekah L. H. Rice, Ph.D. Department of Philosophy 1 To Jeremy, Lydia, and Silas Rice (For unparalleled love, support, and bear hugs) To Ken Harrower (Who taught me that when faced with a perplexing question, one might do well to crack open a book.) To Steve Layman, Patrick McDonald, and Leland Saunders (Colleagues than which none better can be conceived!) 2 I. Introduction Christians maintain that, as a result of divine grace, human persons can survive their deaths. This occurs as a result of a remarkable divine act—something we call “resurrection.” And it constitutes an important piece of the “good news” that Christians profess. Conceptually, this is a baffling claim. How can it be that I (God willing) will exist after my bodily death? One answer is to suggest—as Rene Descartes famously did—that I am not my body, and that I am instead an immaterial mind, or “soul.” This yields the following account of post-mortem survival: Upon my bodily death, my soul persists. Since I am my soul, and not my body, I persist. Where (or in what conditions) I will persist is a matter left to divine judgment, but the fact of my persistence is owing to the fact that though my bodily processes cease and my body decays – or worse, that it is obliterated and cast into a billion pieces – my soul persists to become the occupant of a new (glorified) body, or in any case to enjoy continued existence.
    [Show full text]
  • The Relationship Between Consciousness and Intentionality
    University of Central Florida STARS HIM 1990-2015 2013 The relationship between consciousness and intentionality Jordan Bell University of Central Florida Part of the Philosophy Commons Find similar works at: https://stars.library.ucf.edu/honorstheses1990-2015 University of Central Florida Libraries http://library.ucf.edu This Open Access is brought to you for free and open access by STARS. It has been accepted for inclusion in HIM 1990-2015 by an authorized administrator of STARS. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Recommended Citation Bell, Jordan, "The relationship between consciousness and intentionality" (2013). HIM 1990-2015. 1384. https://stars.library.ucf.edu/honorstheses1990-2015/1384 THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN CONSCIOUSNESS AND INTENTIONALITY by JORDAN BELL A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Honors in the Major Program in Philosophy in the College of Arts & Humanities and in The Burnett Honors College at the University of Central Florida Orlando, Florida Spring Term 2013 Thesis Chair: Dr. Mason Cash ABSTRACT Within the Philosophy of Mind two features of our mental life have been acknowledged as the most perplexing—consciousness, the phenomenal “what it is likeness” of our mental states, and intentionality, the aboutness or directedness of our mental states. As such, it has become commonplace to develop theories about these phenomena which seek to explain them naturalistically, that is, without resort to magic or miracles. Traditionally this has been done by analyzing consciousness and intentionality apart from one another. However, in more recent years the tide has turned. In contemporary theories these phenomena are typically analyzed in terms of the other.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 a REFUTATION of QUALIA-PHYSICALISM Michael
    1 To appear in M. O’Rourke and C. Washington (eds.), Situating Semantics: Essays on the Philosophy of John Perry (MIT Press) A REFUTATION OF QUALIA-PHYSICALISM Michael McKinsey Wayne State University Recent defenders of reductive physicalism such as Brian Loar (1990, 1997) and John Perry (2001) have adopted an intriguing new strategy:i (1) accept as so much common sense (nearly) everything that property-dualists want to say about sensory qualia, including the central claims that sensory qualia determine ‘what it’s like’ to have a given sense experience, and that persons are directly aware of these qualia in the having of such experiences; (2) contend that while these common sense facts about qualia may show that our ways of thinking and speaking about qualia are conceptually different from our ways of thinking and speaking about physical properties of the brain, these facts do not show that sensory qualia themselves (as opposed to our ways of thinking and speaking about them) are distinct from physical properties of the brain; (3) use this contention to turn aside the few existing arguments against reductive physicalism by such property dualists as Kripke (1972), Nagel (1974), Jackson (1982), and Chalmers (1996); and finally (4) insist that sensory qualia are in fact just identical with physical properties of the brain, so that consequently, the facts about the sensory qualities of conscious experience are nothing over and above physical facts about the brain. I will call the view that incorporates this strategy ‘qualia-physicalism’, or ‘Q-physicalism’ for short. In this paper I will argue that Q-physicalism is false.
    [Show full text]
  • Eidos Fecha De Recepción: Marzo 3 De 2011 ISSN 1692-8857 Fecha De Aceptación: Julio 28 De 2011 Issne 2011-7477
    eidos Fecha de recepción: marzo 3 de 2011 ISSN 1692-8857 Fecha de aceptación: julio 28 de 2011 ISSNe 2011-7477 IS THE PANPSYCHIST BETTER OFF AS AN IDEALIST? SOME LEIBNIZIAN REMARKS ON CONSCIOUSNESS AND COMPOSITION Michael Blamauer University of Vienna, Department of Philosophy [email protected] RESUMEN Algunos filósofos de la mente han defendido la idea de considerar la mente como otra característica fundamental de la realidad, además de las propiedades físicas. De ahí que la mayoría de ellos sean propiamente dualistas. Sin embargo, algunos de ellos son pansiquistas. En este artículo sostendré que ser propiamente un dualista implica, en esencia, ser pansiqui- sta. Incluso, si el pansiquismo aborda ciertas dificultades relacionadas con el problema de la conciencia de manera muy elegante, éstas permanecen inmodificables. Siendo partidario del carácter fundamental de la mente, de- fenderé la idea de que sólo mediante una revisión radical de la metafísica el pansiquista podrá evitar tales problemas y, en consecuencia, que debe adoptar el idealismo leibniciano. PALABRAS CLAVE Panpsiquismo, Leibniz, filosofía de la mente, dualismo, composición. ABSTRACT Some philosophers of mind have argued for considering consciousness as a further fundamental feature of reality in addition to its physical prop- erties. Hence most of them are property dualists. But some of them are panpsychists. In the present paper it will be argued that being a real prop- erty dualist essentially entails being a panpsychist. Even if panpsychism deals rather elegantly with certain problems of the puzzle of consciousness, there’s no way around the composition problem. Adhering to the funda- mentality claim of the mind, it will be shown that only a radical revision of metaphysics will allow the panpsychist to avoid these troubles, and hence that a panpsychist must adopt Leibnizian idealism.
    [Show full text]
  • Russellian Physicalism Barbara Gail Montero
    This is a draft of a paper that is to appear in an Oxford University Press anthology on Russellian Monism, edited by Torin Alter and Yujin Nagasawa. Russellian Physicalism Barbara Gail Montero According to David Chalmers (1996, 2002, 2010) the conceivability argument against physicalism is, by and large, successful. In outline, this argument asks us to first conceive of a world that, although just like ours at the level of fundamental physics, lacks consciousness. It goes on to claim that a world matching this conception is logically possible and concludes that consciousness is not physical. Most accept that if it is possible for there to be a world that duplicates the fundamental properties of physics without duplicating consciousness, then consciousness is not physical. And many accept that we can in some sense conceive of such a world. The controversial part of the argument is the move from conceivability to possibility. Yet, according to Chalmers, when we are very careful about what is to count as conceivability, this move also is valid. Physicalism about consciousness, then, says Chalmers, must be rejected. Or rather, it must almost be rejected. This qualification arises because “Russellian monism,” characterized roughly by Chalmers (2002, p. 265) as the view that “consciousness is constituted by the intrinsic properties of fundamental physical entities” falls through a loophole in the antiphysicalist conceivability argument. For it may be, he thinks, that when we conceive of the fundamental physical world we fail to conceive of its intrinsic properties. Yet if Russellian monism is true, consciousness depends on these intrinsic properties, and because of this, a world that duplicates our fundamental physics 1 without duplicating these properties may be a world without consciousness.
    [Show full text]
  • A a a How to Achieve the Physicalist Dream Theory of Consciousness
    Draft May 2020 For G. Rabin Grounding and Consciousness (Oxford) How to Achieve the Physicalist Dream: Identity or Grounding?* Adam Pautz Brown Imagine [a picture] with a million tiny pixels. The picture and the properties reduce to the arrangement of light and dark pixels. The supervenience of mind and all else upon the arrangement of atoms in the void — or whatever replaces atoms in the void in true physics — is another case of reduction. David Lewis (1995) The reader is welcome to label ground physicalism a form of “dualism” or “emer- gentism” (or perhaps a new position entirely), so long as she recognizes that ground physicalism is built around the thesis that the mental is not fundamental but rather grounded in the physical. Jonathan Schaffer (2020) Most of nature is pretty is boring: just different arrangements of atoms in the void. But consciousness seems special. When brains reached a certain complexity, a miracle hap- pened. There appeared properties of a wholly novel type: conscious experiences. To explain this, we may have no choice but to posit special “psychophysical laws”. There are possi- ble worlds where these laws don’t obtain, the miracle doesn’t happen, and we are all zombies. This is property dualism. In “Sensations and Brain Processes”, J. C. Smart articulated just how unappealing property dualism is. It provides a complex and nonuniform picture of reality. And he put forward an alternative physicalist dream picture of reality. In sentient as well as in- sentient nature, “there is nothing in the world but increasingly complex arrangements of physical constituents” (1959: 142).
    [Show full text]
  • 1 the Many-Worlds Theory of Consciousness Christian List* Abstract: This Paper Sketches a New and Somewhat Heterodox Metaphysica
    1 The many-worlds theory of consciousness Christian List* Discussion paper, this version posted 2 March 2021 Abstract: This paper sketches a new and somewhat heterodox metaphysical theory of consciousness: the “many-worlds theory”. It drops the assumption that all conscious subjects’ experiences are features of one and the same world and instead associates different subjects with different “first-personally centred worlds”. We can think of these as distinct “first- personal realizers” of a shared “third-personal world”, where the latter is supervenient, in a sense to be explained. This is combined with a form of modal realism, according to which different subjects’ first-personally centred worlds are all real, though only one of them is present for each subject. The theory offers a novel way of capturing the irreducibly subjective nature of conscious experience without lapsing into solipsism. The paper also looks at some scientific theories of consciousness, such as integrated information theory, through the proposed lens and reconsiders the hard problem of consciousness. 1. Introduction The aim of this paper is to sketch a somewhat heterodox metaphysical theory of consciousness: the “many-worlds theory”. The theory seeks to give an account of how consciousness, in the sense of subjective experience, fits into the world and how it relates to other, non-subjective features. To capture the irreducibly subjective nature of conscious experience, the theory drops the common assumption that all conscious experiences – yours, mine, and those of everyone else – are features of one and the same world and postulates instead that different conscious subjects are associated with different “first-personally centred worlds”.
    [Show full text]
  • Consciousness-Physicalism
    Physicalism Welcome to Physics and Religion, a series of podcasts exploring the interaction between modern science and traditional religion, mostly Christianity. I am your host, Dr. A. S. We have been dealing with the legacy of Rene Descartes. Descartes held that there were two kinds of “substance,” mind and body. For obvious reasons this point of view is called dualism. The mind can exist outside the body and has no physical properties such as mass and location; it can think the body cannot. The mind can control the body, but the body can also control the mind as for example when one does something out of passion. This seemed plausible at first but we were at a loss to explain how something completely non-physical could interact with something purely physical. We are forced back, at least for the time being, to monism, the idea that there is only one kind of substance. So what will it be, mind or body? I would like to start with the less promising of the two; mind -- nothing physical exists. Reality is purely mind, in fact, my mind! My mind is all that exists; the physical world is pure illusion. You are only an illusion and all the evidence I have of your existence is illusory. This is a philosophy called solipsism. (Bertrand Russel told of a woman who wrote to him announcing that she was a solipsist and wondered why there were not more people like her.) Can you refute solipsism? I think not. Any evidence you might bring to bear on the subject is pure illusion.
    [Show full text]
  • Donald Davidson ERNEST LEPORE and KIRK LUDWIG
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy, XXVIII (2004) Donald Davidson ERNEST LEPORE AND KIRK LUDWIG avidson, Donald (Herbert) (b. 1917, d. 2003; American), Willis S. and Marion DSlusser Professor, University of California at Berkeley (1986–2003). Previ- ously Instructor then Professor in Philosophy at: Queens College New York (1947–1950), Stanford University, California (1950–1967), Princeton University (1967–1969), Rockefeller University, New York City (1970–1976), University of Chicago (1976–1981), University of California at Berkeley (1981–2003). John Locke Lecturer, University of Oxford (1970). One of the most important philosophers of the latter half of the twentieth century, Donald Davidson explored a wide range of fundamental topics in meta- physics, epistemology, ethics, and the philosophies of action, mind, and language. His impact on contemporary philosophy is second only to that of his teacher W. V. O. Quine, who, along with Alfred Tarski, exerted the greatest influence on him. Given the range of his contributions, his work emerges as surprisingly systematic, an expression and working out of a number of central guiding ideas. Among his most important contributions are 1. his defense of the common sense view that reasons, those beliefs and desires we cite in explaining our actions, are also causes of them [11], 2. his groundbreaking work in the theory of meaning, and his proposal, based on Tarski’s work on recursive truth definitions for formal languages, for how to formulate a compositional semantic theory for a natural language [29, 46, 47, 50, 51], 3. his development of the project of radical interpretation as a vehicle for investigating questions about meaning and the psychological attitudes involved in understanding action [7, 15, 42, 44, 48], 309 310 Ernest Lepore and Kirk Ludwig 4.
    [Show full text]