The Search for the Historical Gassendi

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Search for the Historical Gassendi The Search for the Historical Gassendi Margaret J. Osler University of Calgary Writing about the history of science and the history of philosophy in- volves assumptions about the role of context and about the relationships between past and present ideas. Some historians emphasize the context, concentrating on the intellectual, personal, and social factors that affect the way earlier thinkers have approached their subject. Analytic philoso- phers take a critical approach, considering the logic and merit of the arguments of past thinkers almost as though they are engaging in contem- porary debates. Some philosophers use the ideas of historical ªgures to support their own philosophical agendas. Scholarly studies of the French natural philosopher Pierre Gassendi (1592–1655) exemplify many of these approaches. What, then, is context? At the most basic level, the context is the text itself. The most acontextual scholars examine only snippets of the text. In- terested in ideas about necessity, arguments for the existence of God, or ideas about matter and gravity, they mine the writings of historical ªgures for their views on these questions without considering the author’s aim for the book or project as a whole. This approach has frequently characterized discussions of Gassendi’s philosophy. His major work, the Syntagma Philo- sophicum, is a massive treatise in difªcult neo-Latin, daunting to all but the hardiest (or most foolish) of scholars. Consequently, of those philosophers and historians who deal with Gassendi at all, many rely on the bits that have been translated into English or French or those that deal with speciªc topics and seldom consider the entirety of his work, but the work as a whole gives the parts their meaning. Gassendi aimed to develop a com- plete philosophy to replace Aristotelianism. He accepted the ancient idea that a complete philosophy consists of three major parts: Logic, Physics, and Ethics. He organized his magnum opus accordingly (Gassendi [1658] Perspectives on Science 2011, vol. 19, no. 2 ©2011 by The Massachusetts Institute of Technology 212 Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/POSC_a_00037 by guest on 27 September 2021 Perspectives on Science 213 1964, 1:26–30). In the manner of the humanists, he sought an ancient model for his philosophizing (see Osler 2000, pp. 93–208; Gassendi [1958] 1964, 1:30). For a variety of reasons—including the fact that he found Epicureanism the ancient philosophy most compatible with his own voluntarist theology—he selected the Greek atomist and hedonist Epicurus (341 b.c.–270 b.c.) for his model (Osler 1994, p. 42). As a Cath- olic priest, Gassendi sought to transform Epicureanism into a theologi- cally acceptable philosophy. The project of baptizing Epicurus was thus the aim and goal of the Syntagma Philosophicum.1 An important reason for the relative neglect of Gassendi’s philosophy stems from the paucity of texts available in modern languages. The difªculty and length of his writing poses an obstacle to many scholars. Fortunately, a slow but steady stream of new translations is providing an improved basis for considering his philosophy. Although his exchange with Descartes—the Fifth “Objections” to the Meditations and Descartes’ “Reply”—is readily available in most modern languages, it gives a limited and somewhat distorted view of his philosophy. The exchange follows Descartes’ agenda in the Meditations and thus fails to convey the nature ei- ther of Gassendi’s Epicurean project or of his concerns and involvement with the sciences of the day. Seeing Gassendi only in relation to Descartes has distorted his image in much English-language scholarship, where ana- lytic philosophers have considered his philosophy only in terms of his re- action to Descartes (in whose ideas they tend to be far more interested) without appreciating the broader compass of his philosophy. Further study of the relative roles of Gassendi and Descartes in seventeenth-century thought as well as their inºuence on later thinkers is needed to elucidate the nature of the seventeenth-century intellectual community as well as the sources of modern philosophical prejudices (see Osler 2010). Bernard Rochot published facing-page translations of two of Gassendi’s works: the Exercitationes paradoxicae adversus Aristoteleos (1624), Gassendi’s ªrst published work which is a skeptical attack on the Aristotelians; and the Disquisitio Metaphysica (1644) (see Gassendi 1959, 1962). Despite some inevitable ºaws in Rochot’s translations, these books made impor- tant aspects of Gassendi’s writings accessible to a wider audience. Unfor- tunately, they did not deal explicitly with either Gassendi’s Epicurean project, a topic on which Rochot had also written an important mono- graph (Rochot 1944), or with his broader interests in the sciences and nat- ural philosophy. The only translation of Gassendi’s works into English is The Selected Works of Pierre Gassendi (1972). In this edition, Craig B. Brush selected 1. On Gassendi’s motives and theological orientation, see Osler (1994, Chaps. 2–4). Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/POSC_a_00037 by guest on 27 September 2021 214 The Search for the Historical Gassendi snippets from several of Gassendi’s works. In harmony with the positivist historiography of science of the early 1970s, he selected passages that con- cerned logic and physics, neglecting to include any of Gassendi’s extensive writings on theology or ethics, both of which play central roles in the Syntagma Philosophicum and other writings. Although this volume is useful for what it covers, it presents only a limited view of Gassendi’s philosophi- cal concerns. Recently, the availability of translated texts is improving. Sylvie Taus- sig has published a series of French translations of sections of the Syntagma Philosophicum. To date, she has translated Books Three and Four of the ªrst section of the “Physics”—“On the Material Principle” (2009) and “On the Efªcient Principle, or the Causes of Things” (2006)—as well as Book Three of the “Ethics”—“On Liberty, On Fortune, On Fate, and On Divi- nation” (2008). These three sections of the Syntagma Philosophicum lay out the foundations of Gassendi’s philosophy. They formulate his atomism, his notion of causality, aspects of his theology, and, in Book III of the “Eth- ics”, his rejection of the hard determinism of Calvin and Hobbes. Taussig has translated the two sections of the Syntagma Philosophicum that most clearly express Gassendi’s theology in contrast to the studies by analytic philosophers that tend to downgrade or overlook that aspect of his thought. Taussig has also translated Gassendi’s Latin letters from Volume 6 of his Opera Omnia. An enormous set of notes to the letters, published in a separate volume, is deeply ºawed by Taussig’s failure to mention the work of other scholars, as well as by factual and bibliographical errors. She has neither translated the letters, also in Volume 6, that others wrote to Gassendi, nor has she dealt with additional letters that exist in various Eu- ropean archives. Nonetheless, her translations have made far more of Gassendi’s writings accessible to a wider audience, and this development bodes well for an increasingly thorough and nuanced understanding of his ideas. In addition to her translations, Taussig has produced two books dealing with Gassendi’s life as a philosopher. In one, Pierre Gassendi (1592–1655): Introduction à la vie savante, Taussig summarizes various aspects of Gas- sendi’s life and career from 1621–1655, the years covered by the published correspondence. Basically summarizing the letters published in Volume 6 of the Opera omnia, this book has sections on Gassendi’s biography for these years, the nature of the correspondence, Gassendi’s science, his Epicurean project, his interactions with various notables, and his role in the history of his time. In fact, the book is little more than a topical analysis of the letters. Despite the inclusion of an extensive—but incomplete—bibliog- raphy of scholarship on Gassendi, the notes to Taussig’s text refer to the Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/POSC_a_00037 by guest on 27 September 2021 Perspectives on Science 215 letters but barely mentions any secondary sources. A second volume edited by Taussig and Anthony Turner, Mémoire de Gassendi: Vies et célébrations écrits avant 1700, contains the early biographies of Gassendi. Each of these works recounts the same series of events, although each emphasizes differ- ent aspects of Gassendi’s life. They all recount his birth to modest parents in the village of Champtercier a few miles outside of Digne in the region of Haute Provence. They note Gassendi’s precocious interest in the stars, his piety, and his intellectual acumen that resulted in his attending school in Digne and proceeding on to university in Aix. At a young age he de- cided on a career in the Church, studied both theology and philosophy, and was later ordained as a priest. They trace Gassendi’s interactions with various scholars and savants in France, including his friend and patron Nicolas-Claude Fabri de Peiresc and the intellectual broker, Marin Mersenne. Ultimately Gassendi was appointed to the Collège Royal as a Professor of Mathematics. Each of the Vies describes Gassendi’s ªnal days and death in the home of Henri Louis Habert de Montmor—a patron of natural philosophers, where he lived for the last two years of his life. The editors of this volume focus on the literary qualities of these documents. They note, for example, the parallels between Antoine de La Poterie’s manuscript and Gassendi’s Life of Peiresc, which, in turn, reºects the form of his Life, Opinions, and Morals of Epicurus. Gassendi emerges in this ac- count not only as a restorer of Epicurus, but also as an Epicurean him- self—leading a life of moderation and enjoying the joys of friendship, al- beit as a pious follower of that sect.
Recommended publications
  • On the Infinite in Leibniz's Philosophy
    On the Infinite in Leibniz's Philosophy Elad Lison Interdisciplinary Studies Unit Science, Technology and Society Ph.D. Thesis Submitted to the Senate of Bar-Ilan University Ramat-Gan, Israel August 2010 This work was carried out under the supervision of Dr. Ohad Nachtomy (Department of Philosophy), Bar-Ilan University. Contents א.……………………………….…………………………………………Hebrew Abstract Prologue…………………………………………………………...………………………1 Part A: Historic Survey Methodological Introduction…………………………………………………………..15 1. Aristotle: Potential Infinite………………………………………………………….16 2. Thomas Aquinas: God and the Infinite………………………………………..…….27 3. William of Ockham: Syncategorematic and Actual Infinite……………………..….32 4. Rabbi Abraham Cohen Herrera: Between Absolute Unity and Unbounded Multitude………………………………………………………………………..….42 5. Galileo Galilei: Continuum Constructed from Infinite Zero's………………………49 6. René Descartes: Infinite as Indefinite…………………………………………….…58 7. Pierre Gassendi: Rejection of the Infinite…………………………………………...69 8. Baruch Spinoza: Infinite Unity…………………………………………………...…73 9. General Background: Leibniz and the History of the Infinite……………………....81 Summary…………………………………………………………………………….…94 Part B: Mathematics Introduction…………………………………………………………………………….99 1. 'De Arte Combinatoria' as a Formal Basis for Thought: Retrospective on Leibniz's 1666 Dissertation………………………………………………………………....102 2. Leibniz and the Infinitesimal Calculus……………………………………….……111 2.1. Mathematical Background: Mathematical Works in 16th-17th Centuries…..111 2.2. Leibniz's Mathematical Development…………………………………….…127
    [Show full text]
  • Pierre Gassendi's Animals
    [Intellectual History Archive 3, 2018] Begley, Pierre Gassendi’s Animals PIERRE GASSENDI’S ANIMALS: A CASE OF EXCLUSION Justin Begley1 University of Helsinki I. Introduction: A Learned Vegetarian The French priest, professor of mathematics, historian, and philosopher, Pierre Gassendi, was perhaps the most influential and well-respected thinkers of his day. 2 While the linguistic and conceptual complexity of his Latin tomes excluded him from the philosophical canon that was formed during the late eighteenth, historians are now beginning to appreciate just how central his ideas were to the development of early modern intellectual life. But recent studies of Gassendi have consistently bypassed a major component of his thought: his defense of a vegetarian diet.3 Conversely, because it is no small task to identify and translate the relevant passages from Gassendi’s oeuvre, historical surveys of vegetarianism have mostly neglected his arguments. Indeed, in the history of vegetarianism, emphasis has been placed on religious sectarians or intellectual outsiders such as Thomas Bushnell and Roger Crab, while figures such as Gassendi who were, historically speaking, intellectual insiders have paradoxically been neglected. 4 Proponents of vegetarianism have thus been shaped teleologically as progressive or even “radical” thinkers. But Gassendi remained thoroughly embedded in the institutions of his day, and channeled the full gamut of humanist apparatuses in his endeavor to integrate the philosophy of the ancient Greek atomist, Epicurus, into the university curriculum. For this purpose, he sought to cleanse Epicurean philosophy of its popular associations with excess, atheism, and debauchery 1 [email protected] 2 Meric Casaubon, Generall Learning: A Seventeenth-Century Treatise on the Formation of the General Scholar, ed.
    [Show full text]
  • Seventeenth-Century News
    131 seventeenth-century news Michael Edwards. Time and The Science of The Soul In Early Modern Philosophy. Brill’s Studies in Intellectual History 224. Leiden: Brill, 2013. x + 224 pp. $128.00. Review by Karin Susan Fester, Independent Scholar. This is a book for philosophers who are not only interested in the concept of time, but who seek new perspectives on this intriguing and problematical philosophical concept as well as appreciate what René Descartes and Thomas Hobbes have to say about it. Michael Edwards’ book is distinctive because it focuses attention on the numerous late Aristotelian thinkers who assumed that the soul’s diverse functions played an active role in the concept of time. More precisely, it is de- voted to the aspects of time which have either not been thoroughly examined or omitted by other historians of early modern philosophy; instead, these other scholars have shown how Aristotelian natural philosophy was concentrated on “space” rather than “time.” Edwards argues that time is somehow intimately connected to the human ra- tional soul—“‘relative’ or as dependent on motion and the soul”—and this, of course, contrasts with Isaac Newton’s (1642–1727) concept of time as something ‘absolute’ (6). The author seems to achieve a persuasive argument, and he invokes elements from early modern commentaries and textbooks concerning Aristotle’s Physics and De Anima and attempts to find connections and influential elements to the natural and political philosophy of Descartes and Hobbes in the seventeenth century. The in-depth Introduction begins with delineating distinct ways of conceptualizing time: absolute and relative.
    [Show full text]
  • Nominalism and Constructivism in Seventeenth-Century Mathematical Philosophy
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector Historia Mathematica 32 (2005) 33–59 www.elsevier.com/locate/hm Nominalism and constructivism in seventeenth-century mathematical philosophy David Sepkoski Department of History, Oberlin College, Oberlin, OH 44074, USA Available online 27 November 2003 Abstract This paper argues that the philosophical tradition of nominalism, as evident in the works of Pierre Gassendi, Thomas Hobbes, Isaac Barrow, and Isaac Newton, played an important role in the history of mathematics during the 17th century. I will argue that nominalist philosophy of mathematics offers new clarification of the development of a “constructivist” tradition in mathematical philosophy. This nominalist and constructivist tradition offered a way for contemporary mathematicians to discuss mathematical objects and magnitudes that did not assume these entities were real in a Platonic sense, and helped lay the groundwork for formalist and instrumentalist approaches in modern mathematics. 2003 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. Résumé Cet article soutient que la tradition philosophique du nominalisme, évidente dans les travaux de Pierre Gassendi, Thomas Hobbes, Isaac Barrow et Isaac Newton, a joué un rôle important dans l’histoire des mathématiques pendant le dix-septième siècle. L’argument princicipal est que la philosophie nominaliste des mathématiques est à la base du développement d’une tradition « constructiviste » en philosophie mathématique. Cette tradition nominaliste et constructiviste a permis aux mathématiciens contemporains de pouvoir discuter d’objets et quantités mathématiques sans présupposer leur réalité au sens Platonique du terme, et a contribué au developpement desétudes formalistes et instrumentalistes des mathématiques modernes.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-86613-2 - Pierre Gassendi and the Birth of Early Modern Philosophy Antonia Lolordo Excerpt More information Introduction This book is bothaninterpretation of Gassendi’s central metaphysical, epistemological, and natural philosophical views and an advertisement for their philosophical and historical interest. Historians of seventeenth- century philosophy can usually tell you that Gassendi was an atomist, an empiricist,oramitigated skeptic, as well as an opponent of Aristotle and Descartes. They might add that he attempted to revive Epicureanism. However, few are likely to have any clear conception ofthe theses Gassendi articulates, the argumentsheoffers in their defense, or the systematic connections between them. This is an unfortunatesituation, and I aim to remedy it. There are at leasttwo reasons why those of us who are interested in early modern philosophy and natural philosophy need to know more about Gassendi. The first is widely recognized. Gassendi’s influence and the importance he was accorded by his peers and close contemporaries is unquestionable. Gassendi was a central figure in seventeenth-century philosophy and, as such, very importantfor the development of mod- ern philosophical thought. He knew and was known by such figures as Descartes and Hobbes and is importantfor understanding Leibniz, Locke, and Newton. Were one a seventeenth-century intellectual who found Cartesianism unacceptable, Gassendi’s philosophy was the obvi- ous alternative. Less well known, however, is the philosophical interest
    [Show full text]
  • Doing Hard Time: Is God the Prisoner of the Oldest Dimension?
    Doing Hard Time: Is God the Prisoner of the Oldest Dimension? R.T. Mullins University of Notre Dame Abstract: In this paper I shall consider an objection to divine temporality called “The Prisoner of Time” objection. I shall begin by distinguishing divine timelessness from divine temporality in order to clear up common misunderstandings and caricatures of divine temporality. From there I shall examine the prisoner of time objection and explain why the prisoner of time objection fails to be a problem for the Christian divine temporalist. During the 20th Century, various Christian philosophers and theologians have rejected divine timelessness. This is not an entirely new phenomena; one can find philosophers and theologians from the Reformation on rejecting divine timelessness. Thinkers like Pierre Gassendi, Isaac Newton, Samuel Clarke, and John Tillotson all rejected the doctrine of divine timelessness long ago for philosophical, theological, scientific, and biblical reasons.1 For these thinkers, time is a necessary concomitant of God’s eternal nature. Despite the efforts of these thinkers, the doctrine of divine timelessness continued to play a central role in Christian theology until the 20th Century. During the 20th Century, and the beginning of this century, one can find a more wide spread rejection of divine timelessness amongst Christian philosophers and systematic theologians. Some of these rejections have been quite rigorous, while others have been misguided. The more recent widespread rejection of the atemporal God has led many into the loving arms of the temporal God. However, divine temporality is not without its critics. Divine atemporality refuses to lay down and die.
    [Show full text]
  • Polish Translation of Gassendi's Polemic with Descartes
    http://dx.doi.org/10.12775/szhf.2018.035 Joanna Usakiewicz University of Białystok, Białystok, Poland e-mail: [email protected] Jerzy Kopania e-mail: [email protected] Polish Translation of Gassendi’s Polemic with Descartes. Description of the Completed Research Project The completion of the following research project involved translating into Polish the work by Pierre Gassendi Disquisitio metaphysica, which is a po- lemic with René Descartes’ Meditations on First Philosophy.1 The description consists of the aim of the project, translation methodology as well as the con- tent summary and the major theses of the introduction to the translation. The project was financed by the National Science Centre under the de- cision DEC-2013/09/B/HS1/01994. The Centre, based in Cracow, finances original research, i.e. experimental or theoretical research which is to pro- duce new knowledge without aiming at immediate commercial application. This project was completed within the years 2014-2017. 1 This work has been carried out thanks to the support of the National Science Centre (Poland), grant: DEC-2013/09/B/HS1/01994. 157 JOA NNA USAKIewICZ, JERZY KOPANIA 1. Origin and aim of translation I n the Polish humanities Pierre Gassendi (1592–1655) is associated pri- marily with his polemic against René Descartes’ Meditations on First Philoso- phy. Of all prolific lifework only a small portion was translated into Polish in 1964, namely a modest part of the treatise Syntagma philosophicum – the introduction (devoted to philosophy) and the first part (devoted to the the- ory of cognition and logic).2 The edition contains the introduction by Leszek Kołakowski3 which has so far been the only overall discussion of Gassendi’s philosophy in Polish.
    [Show full text]
  • The University of Chicago the Ontological Argument, Its Criticisms and Consequences a Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of T
    THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT, ITS CRITICISMS AND CONSEQUENCES A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE DIVINITY SCHOOL IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY BY JASON GRANT CATHER CHICAGO, ILLINOIS AUGUST 2017 Copyright c 2017 by Jason Grant Cather All Rights Reserved TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGMENTS . vi 1 NEOCLASSICAL METAPHYSICS FOR THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT . 1 1.1 Overview . .1 1.2 The Appeal of the Ontological Argument . .2 1.3 On the Nature of Argument . .5 1.4 The Appeal of Neoclassical Metaphysics . .5 1.5 How to Think About Divine Greatness . .9 1.5.1 The Ontological Principle . .9 1.5.2 Actual Entities . .9 1.5.3 Societies . 10 1.5.4 Eternal Objects . 11 1.5.5 God . 12 1.6 Neoclassical Metaphysics as a Modal Metaphysics . 13 1.7 Neoclassical Understandings of Existential Statements . 14 1.8 Conclusion . 16 2 WHAT MAKES AN ARGUMENT ONTOLOGICAL? . 18 2.1 Overview . 18 2.2 Identifying Arguments as Ontological . 19 2.3 An Absurdly Brief History of the Debate Surrounding the Argument . 22 2.4 Parameters for Successful Arguments, or What Can We Expect an Argument toDo?....................................... 33 2.5 What Does a Parody Do? . 36 2.6 Are the Parodies Ontological? . 39 2.7 From Parody to Parity . 41 2.8 Conclusion . 42 3 ON FORMULATIONS OF ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENTS . 43 3.1 Overview . 43 3.2 From Parody to Caricature . 43 3.3 Two Interpretations . 45 3.4 Is the Argument Just for Theists? . 51 3.5 Ontologically Neutral Formulations . 53 3.5.1 Is Neutrality Really Desirable? .
    [Show full text]
  • SHORTER LEIBNIZ TEXTS Also Available from Continuum
    THE SHORTER LEIBNIZ TEXTS Also available from Continuum Leibniz Reinterpreted, Lloyd Strickland Leibniz: A Guide for the Perplexed, Franklin Perkins THE SHORTER LEIBNIZ TEXTS A Collection of New Translations Lloyd Strickland continuum Continuum The Tower Building 80 Maiden Lane, Suite 704 11 York Road New York, NY 10038 London SE1 7NX © Lloyd Strickland 2006 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publishers. Lloyd Strickland has asserted his right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identified as Author of this work. British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. ISBN: 0826489508 (hardback) 0826489516 (paperback) Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data A catalog record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. Typeset by Interactive Sciences Ltd, Gloucester Printed and bound in Great Britain by Cromwell Press Ltd, Trowbridge, Wiltshire For Dawn (Bur) This page intentionally left blank This page intentionally left blank Page 2 (recto) of Leibniz's handwritten manuscript LH 37, 4ff 14r-15v This page intentionally left blank This page intentionally left blank Contents Acknowledgements xv Selected Bibliography xvii Introduction 1 A note on the translations 24 I. METAPHYSICS A. Creation 29 1. On first truths (middle-end 1680) 29 2. On the reason why these things exist rather than other things (March-August 1689) 30 3. On the ultimate origination of things (23 November 1697) 31 4.
    [Show full text]
  • Pierre Gassendi on the Three Acts of the Mind
    Logic and the Movement of Reasoning: Pierre Gassendi on the Three Acts of the Mind Sorana Corneanu University of Bucharest Downloaded from http://direct.mit.edu/posc/article-pdf/29/3/292/1923003/posc_a_00370.pdf by guest on 03 October 2021 The aim of this paper is to assess the central role the imagination acquires in Pierre Gassendi’s logic. I trace the structuring scheme of the three acts of the mind—common to a good number of late scholastic and early modern logics— to the Thomistic notion of the movement of reasoning in knowledge and argue that Gassendi revisits this notion in his logic. The three acts scheme is from the beginning a bridge between logic and the natural philosophical treatment of the soul. I show how Gassendi’s take on the three acts is similarly poised between his Logic and his Physics and I discuss the rationale, sources and consequences of his attribution of the three acts to the imagination. I argue for the following points: Gassendi’s conception of the logical role of the imag- ination answers to his empiricist epistemology, his naturalized view of the mind (which involves a defense of thinking in animals) and his notion of a natural logic; it is also operative in his pairing of the formal mechanism of logical operations with a progressive mechanism of the operations of the mind; and it serves as a counterpart to his experimental understanding of the progress of knowledge.1 1. Logic and the Three Acts of the Mind The organization of logical material in three main parts, according to the three ‘acts of the intellect’—apprehension, judgment and reasoning—with the occasional addition of a fourth part, on method, is a relatively wide- 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Physical Color Theory Before Newton Author(S): Henry Guerlac Reviewed Work(S): Source: Journal of the History of Ideas, Vol
    Can there Be Colors in the Dark? Physical Color Theory before Newton Author(s): Henry Guerlac Reviewed work(s): Source: Journal of the History of Ideas, Vol. 47, No. 1 (Jan. - Mar., 1986), pp. 3-20 Published by: University of Pennsylvania Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2709592 . Accessed: 28/11/2011 22:42 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. University of Pennsylvania Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Journal of the History of Ideas. http://www.jstor.org CAN THERE BE COLORS IN THE DARK? PHYSICAL COLOR THEORY BEFORE NEWTON BY HENRY GUERLACt Isaac Newton's first scientific paper, setting forth his epoch-making theory of light and colors, appeared in the Philosophical Transactionsof the Royal Society of London in February 1672.1 Newton was barely thirty years old, a young don at Trinity College, Cambridge, where he was destined to remain immured for the next quarter century. Yet several years before submitting his classic paper he had been investigating the problem of colors using what one scholar has called his "instrument of choice," the triangular glass prism.
    [Show full text]
  • Omnipotence and Promise: the Legacy of the Scholastic Distinction of Powers
    The Etienne Gilson Series 23 Omnipotence and Promise: The Legacy of the Scholastic Distinction of Powers by Francis Oakley 1 March 2002 Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies Note: The author may be contacted at: The Oakley Center for the Humanities and Social Sciences Williams College Williamstown MA USA 01267 ISSN 0-708-319X ISBN 0-88844-723-X © 2002 by Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies 59 Queen’s Park Crescent East Toronto, Ontario, Canada M5S 2C4 Printed in Canada ocusing, as I plan to, on the legacy of medieval scholasticism which in its time spawned so many creative and exceedingly Frefined distinctions, my concern, appropriately enough, will be with one of them. It is a distinction, admittedly, that it would be easy enough to dismiss as a typical scholastic cliché. And while such a dismissal would, I am convinced, be unwarranted, about the categorization itself I am not disposed to wrangle. Cliché it surely was, echoed in such early neo-scholastic manuals as that of Joseph Kleutgen who, in 1881, acknowledged it in passing to be something of a commonplace “among [as he put it] the Catholic doctors.”1 But that notwithstanding, it will be my purpose to claim that, if it was indeed a cliché, it was one with a future–not only in the theology of redemption, where it first appeared, but also in natural or philosophical theology, in epistemology, in natural philosophy, in ethics, in legal philosophy. And it will be my purpose also, in the brief time at my disposal, to try to persuade you that during the first half-millennium at least of its long career, it was a cliché that exerted a truly profound influence over the course of European intellectual history.
    [Show full text]