Midterm 2 Review the Exam Will Cover Chapters 4 (Functions

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Midterm 2 Review the Exam Will Cover Chapters 4 (Functions Midterm 2 Review The exam will cover Chapters 4 (Functions, injections, surjections, bijections, cardinality of sets etc.) and 13 (sequences, convergence, bounded, monotone etc.). 1 As I stated in class, the first problem on the test will be to state the definition of a sequence (an)n=1 converging to a limit L 2 R. You should also be able to state the other definitions in these chapters, and the exam will also ask for some of these definitions. Here is a list of definitions you should be able to state: • injective function • surjective function • bijective function • cardinality of a finite set • countable set • composition of two functions • convergent sequence • bounded sequence • monotone sequence • supremum and infimum of a set/sequence You should also be able to produce examples of each of these objects, and also examples which have various combinations of these properties (e.g. a function which is injective but not surjective, or a sequence which is bounded but not monotone), as well as when there exist no examples (e.g. an unbounded convergent sequence, which cannot exist because every convergent sequence is bounded). For example, if X = f1; 2; 3g and Y = f4; 5; 6; 7g, then an example of a function f : X ! Y which is injective and not surjective would be to define f as follows: f(1) = 5, f(2) = 4, f(3) = 7. n For example, a sequence which is bounded but not monotone is an = (−1) . You should be able to prove that a given sequence converges, and good practice for this would be (−1)n 1 1 1 p1 showing that sequences like n , n2 , n3 , n , n all converge. Here is an example of a proof that 1 n2 converges to 0. Proof. We wish to show that given any > 0, we can find an N 2 N such that for every index 1 q 1 n ≥ N, we have n2 − 0 < . Let > 0 be fixed but arbitrary. Consider the number which is q 1 2 1 1 positive. Choose an N 2 such that N > . Then we also have that N > , and so 2 < . N N 1 1 1 Thus, whenever n ≥ N, we have 2 ≤ 2 < . So for all n ≥ N, we see that 2 − 0 < . n N n Here is another example of the sort of thing that could reasonably be asked on the test. 1 Suppose f : A ! B and g : B ! C are both surjective. Show that the composition g ◦ f : A ! C is surjective. Proof. We need to show that for every c 2 C, there exists an a 2 A such that g ◦ f(a) = c. Fix an element c 2 C. Because g is surjective, there exists some element b 2 B such that g(b) = c. Then because f is surjective, there exists an element a 2 A such that f(a) = b. For this a, we see that g(f(a)) = c, and so there exists an element a 2 A such that g ◦ f(a) = c. Though the exam will not ask for some of the longer proofs, it could ask for shorter ones, or for ideas from the longer ones. For example, the following key fact came up in a couple of proofs, and has a short proof that could come up. Suppose (an) is a bounded sequence, and let S = sup(an). Show that for every > 0, there is an element an such that S − < an ≤ S. Proof. By definition, S is an upper bound for the sequence, so for every n, an ≤ S. Suppose that the claim is false, i.e. suppose that there is an > 0 so that there are no elements of the sequence with S − < an ≤ S. But then, for every n, we have that an ≤ S − . Thus S − is an upper bound for the sequence, and it is less than S. This contradicts the assumption that S was the least upper bound, and the claim is proven. As another example, the proofs of 13.14 (limits of sequences are unique) and 13.17 (if a sequence is bounded, it cannot converge to a limit outside of the bounds) in the book, which we worked in class, are based on a similar idea. So those proofs could come up. 2.
Recommended publications
  • I0 and Rank-Into-Rank Axioms
    I0 and rank-into-rank axioms Vincenzo Dimonte∗ July 11, 2017 Abstract Just a survey on I0. Keywords: Large cardinals; Axiom I0; rank-into-rank axioms; elemen- tary embeddings; relative constructibility; embedding lifting; singular car- dinals combinatorics. 2010 Mathematics Subject Classifications: 03E55 (03E05 03E35 03E45) 1 Informal Introduction to the Introduction Ok, that’s it. People who know me also know that it is years that I am ranting about a book about I0, how it is important to write it and publish it, etc. I realized that this particular moment is still right for me to write it, for two reasons: time is scarce, and probably there are still not enough results (or anyway not enough different lines of research). This has the potential of being a very nasty vicious circle: there are not enough results about I0 to write a book, but if nobody writes a book the diffusion of I0 is too limited, and so the number of results does not increase much. To avoid this deadlock, I decided to divulge a first draft of such a hypothetical book, hoping to start a “conversation” with that. It is literally a first draft, so it is full of errors and in a liquid state. For example, I still haven’t decided whether to call it I0 or I0, both notations are used in literature. I feel like it still lacks a vision of the future, a map on where the research could and should going about I0. Many proofs are old but never published, and therefore reconstructed by me, so maybe they are wrong.
    [Show full text]
  • Elementary Functions Part 1, Functions Lecture 1.6D, Function Inverses: One-To-One and Onto Functions
    Elementary Functions Part 1, Functions Lecture 1.6d, Function Inverses: One-to-one and onto functions Dr. Ken W. Smith Sam Houston State University 2013 Smith (SHSU) Elementary Functions 2013 26 / 33 Function Inverses When does a function f have an inverse? It turns out that there are two critical properties necessary for a function f to be invertible. The function needs to be \one-to-one" and \onto". Smith (SHSU) Elementary Functions 2013 27 / 33 Function Inverses When does a function f have an inverse? It turns out that there are two critical properties necessary for a function f to be invertible. The function needs to be \one-to-one" and \onto". Smith (SHSU) Elementary Functions 2013 27 / 33 Function Inverses When does a function f have an inverse? It turns out that there are two critical properties necessary for a function f to be invertible. The function needs to be \one-to-one" and \onto". Smith (SHSU) Elementary Functions 2013 27 / 33 Function Inverses When does a function f have an inverse? It turns out that there are two critical properties necessary for a function f to be invertible. The function needs to be \one-to-one" and \onto". Smith (SHSU) Elementary Functions 2013 27 / 33 One-to-one functions* A function like f(x) = x2 maps two different inputs, x = −5 and x = 5, to the same output, y = 25. But with a one-to-one function no pair of inputs give the same output. Here is a function we saw earlier. This function is not one-to-one since both the inputs x = 2 and x = 3 give the output y = C: Smith (SHSU) Elementary Functions 2013 28 / 33 One-to-one functions* A function like f(x) = x2 maps two different inputs, x = −5 and x = 5, to the same output, y = 25.
    [Show full text]
  • Monomorphism - Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia
    Monomorphism - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Monomorphism Monomorphism From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia In the context of abstract algebra or universal algebra, a monomorphism is an injective homomorphism. A monomorphism from X to Y is often denoted with the notation . In the more general setting of category theory, a monomorphism (also called a monic morphism or a mono) is a left-cancellative morphism, that is, an arrow f : X → Y such that, for all morphisms g1, g2 : Z → X, Monomorphisms are a categorical generalization of injective functions (also called "one-to-one functions"); in some categories the notions coincide, but monomorphisms are more general, as in the examples below. The categorical dual of a monomorphism is an epimorphism, i.e. a monomorphism in a category C is an epimorphism in the dual category Cop. Every section is a monomorphism, and every retraction is an epimorphism. Contents 1 Relation to invertibility 2 Examples 3 Properties 4 Related concepts 5 Terminology 6 See also 7 References Relation to invertibility Left invertible morphisms are necessarily monic: if l is a left inverse for f (meaning l is a morphism and ), then f is monic, as A left invertible morphism is called a split mono. However, a monomorphism need not be left-invertible. For example, in the category Group of all groups and group morphisms among them, if H is a subgroup of G then the inclusion f : H → G is always a monomorphism; but f has a left inverse in the category if and only if H has a normal complement in G.
    [Show full text]
  • Solutions to Homework Set 5
    MAT320/640, Fall 2020 Renato Ghini Bettiol Solutions to Homework Set 5 1. Decide if each of the statements below is true or false. If it is true, give a complete proof; if it is false, give an explicit counter-example. (Recall that a function f : X ! Y is called surjective, or onto, if every point of Y belongs to its image, that is, if f(X) = Y .) (a) There exists a continuous function f : R n f0g ! R. (b) There exists a continuous surjective function f : R n f0g ! R. (c) There exists a continuous function f : [0; 1] ! R. (d) There exists a continuous surjective function f : [0; 1] ! R. (e) The function f : R ! R, f(x) = x2, is uniformly continuous. (f) The function f : [0; 1] ! R, f(x) = x2, uniformly continuous. Solution: (a) TRUE: For example, any constant function f : R n f0g ! R is continuous; e.g., f(x) = 0 for all x 2 R n f0g. (b) TRUE: For example, consider the function f : R n f0g ! R given by ( x; if x < 0; f(x) = x − 1; if x > 0: Since the domain of f is R n f0g, it is continuous on its domain. Moreover, f is clearly surjective (draw its graph). (c) TRUE: For example, any constant function f : [0; 1] ! R is continuous; e.g., f(x) = 0 for all x 2 [0; 1]. (d) FALSE: Suppose, by contradiction, that such a function f : [0; 1] ! R exists. Since [0; 1] is compact and f : [0; 1] ! R is continuous, its image f([0; 1]) is compact.
    [Show full text]
  • Logic and Proof Release 3.18.4
    Logic and Proof Release 3.18.4 Jeremy Avigad, Robert Y. Lewis, and Floris van Doorn Sep 10, 2021 CONTENTS 1 Introduction 1 1.1 Mathematical Proof ............................................ 1 1.2 Symbolic Logic .............................................. 2 1.3 Interactive Theorem Proving ....................................... 4 1.4 The Semantic Point of View ....................................... 5 1.5 Goals Summarized ............................................ 6 1.6 About this Textbook ........................................... 6 2 Propositional Logic 7 2.1 A Puzzle ................................................. 7 2.2 A Solution ................................................ 7 2.3 Rules of Inference ............................................ 8 2.4 The Language of Propositional Logic ................................... 15 2.5 Exercises ................................................. 16 3 Natural Deduction for Propositional Logic 17 3.1 Derivations in Natural Deduction ..................................... 17 3.2 Examples ................................................. 19 3.3 Forward and Backward Reasoning .................................... 20 3.4 Reasoning by Cases ............................................ 22 3.5 Some Logical Identities .......................................... 23 3.6 Exercises ................................................. 24 4 Propositional Logic in Lean 25 4.1 Expressions for Propositions and Proofs ................................. 25 4.2 More commands ............................................
    [Show full text]
  • A New Characterization of Injective and Surjective Functions and Group Homomorphisms
    A new characterization of injective and surjective functions and group homomorphisms ANDREI TIBERIU PANTEA* Abstract. A model of a function f between two non-empty sets is defined to be a factorization f ¼ i, where ¼ is a surjective function and i is an injective Æ ± function. In this note we shall prove that a function f is injective (respectively surjective) if and only if it has a final (respectively initial) model. A similar result, for groups, is also proven. Keywords: factorization of morphisms, injective/surjective maps, initial/final objects MSC: Primary 03E20; Secondary 20A99 1 Introduction and preliminary remarks In this paper we consider the sets taken into account to be non-empty and groups denoted differently to be disjoint. For basic concepts on sets and functions see [1]. It is a well known fact that any function f : A B can be written as the composition of a surjective function ! followed by an injective function. Indeed, f f 0 id , where f 0 : A Im(f ) is the restriction Æ ± B ! of f to Im(f ) is one such factorization. Moreover, it is an elementary exercise to prove that this factorization is unique up to an isomorphism: i.e. if f i ¼, i : A X , ¼: X B is 1 ¡ Æ ±¢ ! 1 ! another factorization for f , then we easily see that X i ¡ Im(f ) and that ¼ i ¡ f 0. The Æ Æ ± purpose of this note is to study the dual problem. Let f : A B be a function. We shall define ! a model of the function f to be a triple (X ,i,¼) made up of a set X , an injective function i : A X and a surjective function ¼: X B such that f ¼ i, that is, the following diagram ! ! Æ ± is commutative.
    [Show full text]
  • Proofs and Mathematical Reasoning
    Proofs and Mathematical Reasoning University of Birmingham Author: Supervisors: Agata Stefanowicz Joe Kyle Michael Grove September 2014 c University of Birmingham 2014 Contents 1 Introduction 6 2 Mathematical language and symbols 6 2.1 Mathematics is a language . .6 2.2 Greek alphabet . .6 2.3 Symbols . .6 2.4 Words in mathematics . .7 3 What is a proof? 9 3.1 Writer versus reader . .9 3.2 Methods of proofs . .9 3.3 Implications and if and only if statements . 10 4 Direct proof 11 4.1 Description of method . 11 4.2 Hard parts? . 11 4.3 Examples . 11 4.4 Fallacious \proofs" . 15 4.5 Counterexamples . 16 5 Proof by cases 17 5.1 Method . 17 5.2 Hard parts? . 17 5.3 Examples of proof by cases . 17 6 Mathematical Induction 19 6.1 Method . 19 6.2 Versions of induction. 19 6.3 Hard parts? . 20 6.4 Examples of mathematical induction . 20 7 Contradiction 26 7.1 Method . 26 7.2 Hard parts? . 26 7.3 Examples of proof by contradiction . 26 8 Contrapositive 29 8.1 Method . 29 8.2 Hard parts? . 29 8.3 Examples . 29 9 Tips 31 9.1 What common mistakes do students make when trying to present the proofs? . 31 9.2 What are the reasons for mistakes? . 32 9.3 Advice to students for writing good proofs . 32 9.4 Friendly reminder . 32 c University of Birmingham 2014 10 Sets 34 10.1 Basics . 34 10.2 Subsets and power sets . 34 10.3 Cardinality and equality .
    [Show full text]
  • Foundations of Abstract Mathematics Paul L. Bailey
    Foundations of Abstract Mathematics Paul L. Bailey Department of Mathematics, Southern Arkansas University E-mail address: [email protected] Date: January 21, 2009 i Contents Preface vii 1. Purpose vii 2. Description of the Blocks vii 2.1. Commentary vii 2.2. Developmental Blocks vii 2.3. Orientation Blocks viii 3. Description of the Volumes viii 3.1. Foundations of Abstract Mathematics viii 3.2. Objects of Abstract Mathematics viii 3.3. Categories of Abstract Mathematics viii 4. Description of this Volume viii 4.1. Goals viii 4.2. Similar Treatments ix Chapter 1. Sets 1 1. Orientation 1 2. Axioms of Set Theory 2 3. Subsets 3 4. Set Operations 4 5. Cartesian Product 7 6. Relations 9 7. Numbers 10 8. Problems and Exercises 11 Chapter 2. Functions 13 1. Mappings 13 2. Functions 14 3. Images and Preimages 15 4. Injective and Surjective Functions 15 5. Restrictions and Constrictions 16 6. Composition of Functions 17 7. Identities and Inverses 17 8. Retractions and Sections 18 9. Monos and Epis 19 10. Inclusions and Projections 20 11. Problems and Exercises 21 Chapter 3. Collections 23 1. Collections 23 2. Power Sets 23 iii iv CONTENTS 3. Mapping Sets 24 4. Function Sets 24 5. Characteristic Functions 25 6. Products 26 7. Coproducts 27 8. Families 28 9. Partitions 29 10. Problems and Exercises 30 Chapter 4. Relations 31 1. Relations 31 2. Properties of Relations 31 3. Order Relations 32 4. Equivalence Relations 34 5. Equivalence Classes 35 6. Equivalence Relations and Partitions 35 7. Equivalence Relations and Functions 37 8.
    [Show full text]
  • Consider the “Function” F(X) = 1 X − 4 . in Fact, This Is Not a Function Until I Have Told You It's Domain and Codomain
    Consider the “function” 1 f(x) = . x − 4 In fact, this is not a function until I have told you it’s domain and codomain. More accurately we have to talk about the function 1 f : R \{4} → R, f(x) = . x − 4 It’s important to get in the habit of specifying the domain and codomain. In fact the definition of function f : A → B specifies it as a subset of the cartesian produce A × B. From this point of view, our function is the set {(x, 1/(x − 4) : x ∈ R \{4}} ⊂ R \{4} × R 1 Note: my definition of function is different from that of the book. Book does not require that the function be defined everywhere in A. Range The range of a function f : A → B is the subset of B consisting of values of the function. A function is surjective (or onto) if the range equals the codomain. The function f : R \{4} → R given by f(x) = 1/(x − 4) is not surjective because it misses the value 0. That is, the equation g(x) = 0 has no solution in R \{4}. 2 However, if we define a new function g : R \{4} → R \{0}, using the same formula g(x) = 1/(x−4), then g is a surjective function. Note that although the formula is the same, this is a different function from f because we have changed the codomain. To prove g is surjective, we must show that if y ∈ R \{0}, then the equation g(x) = y has a solution x ∈ R\{4}.
    [Show full text]
  • Notes for MATH 582
    Notes for MATH 582 David J. Fern´andez-Bret´on (based on the handwritten notes from January-April 2016, typed in January-April 2017, polished in January-April 2018) Table of Contents Chapter 1 Basic set theory 3 1.1 What is a Set? . 3 1.2 Axiomatizing set theory . 3 1.3 The Language of set theory . 4 1.4 Cantor's set theory . 6 1.5 Patching up Cantor's set theory . 8 1.6 Other ways of dodging Russell's Paradox . 14 1.7 The last few words about the axiomatic method . 15 Chapter 2 Relations, functions, and objects of that ilk 17 2.1 Ordered pairs, relations and functions . 17 2.2 Equivalence relations . 23 2.3 Partial orders . 26 2.4 Well-orders . 28 Chapter 3 The natural numbers, the integers, the rationals, the reals... and more 32 3.1 Peano Systems . 32 3.1.1 Arithmetic in a Peano system . 34 3.1.2 The order relation in a Peano system . 35 3.1.3 There exists one Peano system . 37 3.2 The integers . 38 3.3 The rational numbers . 38 3.4 The real numbers . 39 3.4.1 Dedekind cuts . 39 3.4.2 Cauchy sequences . 39 3.5 Other mathematical objects . 44 Chapter 4 Ordinal numbers 45 4.1 Definition and basic facts . 45 4.2 Classes . 48 4.3 A few words about NBG ............................................... 50 4.4 The Axiom of Replacement . 50 4.5 Ordinal numbers as representatives of well-ordered sets . 53 4.6 Sets and their ranks .
    [Show full text]
  • Injective, Surjective, and Bijective Functions
    Module A-5: Injective, Surjective, and Bijective Functions Math-270: Discrete Mathematics November 10, 2019 Motivation You’re surely familiar with the idea of an inverse function: a function that undoes some other function. For example, f(x)=x3 and g(x)=p3 x are inverses of each other. Whether thinking mathematically or coding this in software, things get compli- cated. The theory of injective, surjective, and bijective functions is a very compact and mostly straightforward theory. Yet it completely untangles all the potential pitfalls of inverting a function. Terminology If a function f maps a set to a set , we are accustomed to calling the domain (which is fine) but we are also accustomed to callingX the range,Y and that is sloppy. The rangeX of f is the set of values actually hit by f. In other words, y isY in the range of f(x) if and only if there is some x in the domain such that f(x)=y. Without this restriction, we refer to as the co-domain of f(x). You have probably heard the phrase “y is theY image of x”whenf(x)=y. Likewise, we can say “x is a pre-image of y.” Notice that we say “a pre-image” and not “the pre-image.” That’s because y might have multiple pre-images. For example, if f(x)=x2 as a function of the real line, then y = 4 has two pre-images: x = 2 and x = 2. Meanwhile, y = 0 has only one pre-image, x = 0. In contrast, y = 1 has no pre-images.
    [Show full text]
  • Differential Topology
    Differential Topology Bjørn Ian Dundas 26th June 2002 2 Contents 1 Preface 7 2 Introduction 9 2.1 A robot's arm: . 9 2.1.1 Question . 11 2.1.2 Dependence on the telescope's length . 12 2.1.3 Moral . 13 2.2 Further examples . 14 2.2.1 Charts . 14 2.2.3 Compact surfaces . 15 2.2.8 Higher dimensions . 19 3 Smooth manifolds 21 3.1 Topological manifolds . 21 3.2 Smooth structures . 24 3.3 Maximal atlases . 28 3.4 Smooth maps . 30 3.5 Submanifolds . 35 3.6 Products and sums . 39 4 The tangent space 43 4.0.1 Predefinition of the tangent space . 43 4.1 Germs . 44 4.2 The tangent space . 47 4.3 Derivations . 52 5 Vector bundles 57 5.1 Topological vector bundles . 58 5.2 Transition functions . 62 5.3 Smooth vector bundles . 63 5.4 Pre-vector bundles . 66 5.5 The tangent bundle . 68 3 4 CONTENTS 6 Submanifolds 75 6.1 The rank . 75 6.2 The inverse function theorem . 77 6.3 The rank theorem . 78 6.4 Regular values . 81 6.5 Immersions and imbeddings . 88 6.6 Sard's theorem . 91 7 Partition of unity 93 7.1 Definitions . 93 7.2 Smooth bump functions . 94 7.3 Refinements of coverings . 96 7.4 Existence of smooth partitions of unity on smooth manifolds. 98 7.5 Imbeddings in Euclidean space . 99 8 Constructions on vector bundles 101 8.1 Subbundles and restrictions . 101 8.2 The induced bundles . 105 8.3 Whitney sum of bundles .
    [Show full text]