Must God Be Incorporeal?
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
From Hades to the Stars: Empedocles on the Cosmic Habitats of Soul', Classical Antiquity, Vol
Edinburgh Research Explorer From Hades to the stars Citation for published version: Trepanier, S 2017, 'From Hades to the stars: Empedocles on the cosmic habitats of soul', Classical Antiquity, vol. 36, no. 1, pp. 130-182. https://doi.org/10.1525/ca.2017.36.1.130 Digital Object Identifier (DOI): 10.1525/ca.2017.36.1.130 Link: Link to publication record in Edinburgh Research Explorer Document Version: Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Published In: Classical Antiquity Publisher Rights Statement: Published as Trépanier, S. 2017. From Hades to the Stars: Empedocles on the Cosmic Habitats of Soul, Classical Antiquity, Vol. 36 No. 1, April 2017; (pp. 130-182) DOI: 10.1525/ca.2017.36.1.130. © 2017 by the Regents of the University of California. Authorization to copy this content beyond fair use (as specified in Sections 107 and 108 of the U. S. Copyright Law) for internal or personal use, or the internal or personal use of specific clients, is granted by the Regents of the University of California for libraries and other users, provided that they are registered with and pay the specified fee via Rightslink® or directly with the Copyright Clearance Center. General rights Copyright for the publications made accessible via the Edinburgh Research Explorer is retained by the author(s) and / or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing these publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Take down policy The University of Edinburgh has made every reasonable effort to ensure that Edinburgh Research Explorer content complies with UK legislation. -
Jantzen, GOD's WORLD, GOD's BODY
View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Asbury Theological Seminary Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 4 Issue 1 Article 8 1-1-1987 Jantzen, GOD'S WORLD, GOD'S BODY Charles Taliaferro Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Taliaferro, Charles (1987) "Jantzen, GOD'S WORLD, GOD'S BODY," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 4 : Iss. 1 , Article 8. Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol4/iss1/8 This Book Review is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. BOOK REVIEWS God's World, God's Body,by Grace Jantzen. Foreword by John Macquarie (Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1984). Pap. $10.95. Reviewed by CHARLES TALIAFERRO, St. Olaf College. In recent years philosophers have sought to retain a Christian metaphysics while either dispensing with or radically revising important tenets of the classical Christian conception of God. Immutability, metaphysical simplicity, eternity, necessary existence, essential goodness, omniscience, and omnipotence have been among the most popular Divine attributes targetted for critical review. In God's World, God's Body Grace Jantzen argues for the bold thesis that a Christian metaphysics need not claim that God is incorporeal. Criticism of the thesis that God is incorporeal is not new to philosophical theology, but Jantzen's work is a significant, new attempt to establish the compatibility of theism with the view that there are no incorporeal, nonphysical persons. -
The Presocratic Philosophers 374
XXII De Anima (a) Material beginnings The psuchê or animator is that part or feature of an animate being which endows it with life; and since the primary signs of life are cognition and mobility, the psuchê is the source of knowledge and the source of locomotion. That gives a formal or functional account of psuchê; but it leaves us to ask what the psychic nature consists in: what sort of thing is it that provides us with life? is it the same sort of thing in men, in animals and in plants? where (if anywhere) is it located in the body? is it separable from the body? To those questions the early Presocratics had, by and large, no interesting answers. The doxography regularly deals with the question: What is psuchê made of? Anaximenes and Anaximander and Anaxagoras and Archelaus said that the nature of psuchê is airy (398: Aëtius, 12 A 29; cf. 13 B 2; Philoponus, 13 A 23).1 Parmenides and Hippasus and Heraclitus [say that the psuchê] is fiery (399: Aëtius, 18 A 9). And a fragment of Epicharmus indicates that the fiery soul was familiar enough outside professional scientific circles (23 B 48). Water and earth, the other two canonical elements, had fewer backers; but Hippo went for water (Hippolytus, 38 A 3), and late stories give souls of earth and water to Xenophanes (Macrobius, 21 A 50).2 In the physics ascribed by Diogenes to Zeno, ‘soul is a mixture of [the hot, the cold, the dry and the wet], with none of them having dominance’ (IX. -
The Metaphysics of Light in the Hexaemeral Literature
The Metaphysics of Light in the Hexaemeral Literature From Philo of Alexandria to Ambrose of Milan I S I D O R O S C H A R A L A M P O S K A T S O S Pembroke College December 2018 This dissertation is submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy D e c l a r a t i o n This dissertation is the result of my own work and includes nothing which is the outcome of work done in collaboration except as declared in the Acknowledgements and specified in the text. It is not substantially the same as any that I have submitted, or, is being concurrently submitted for a degree or diploma or other qualification at the University of Cambridge or any other University or similar institution except as declared in the Acknowledgements and specified in the text. I further state that no substantial part of my dissertation has already been submitted, or, is being concurrently submitted for any such degree, diploma or other qualification at the University of Cambridge or any other University or similar institution except as declared in the Acknowledgements and specified in the text. It does not exceed the prescribed word limit. Isidoros Charalampos Katsos Pembroke College CB2 1RF [email protected] The Metaphysics of Light in the Hexaemeral Literature From Philo of Alexandria to Ambrose of Milan Summary This study investigates the concept of light in the early Jewish-Christian exegesis of the biblical creation narrative (Gen. 1, so-called ‘hexaemeron’). The study argues that the early hexaemeral exegetes theorised light from a dual perspective, both physical and metaphysical. -
The Coherence of Stoic Ontology
UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Electronic Theses and Dissertations Title The Coherence of Stoic Ontology Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/3wg7m1w0 Author de Harven, Vanessa Publication Date 2012 Peer reviewed|Thesis/dissertation eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California The Coherence of Stoic Ontology by Vanessa de Harven A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Prof. Dorothea Frede, Co-chair Prof. Klaus Corcilius, Co-chair Prof. A.A. Long Spring 2012 Abstract The Coherence of Stoic Ontology by Vanessa de Harven Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy University of California, Berkeley Professors Dorothea Frede and Klaus Corcilius, Co-chairs Any thoroughgoing physicalist is challenged to give an account of immaterial entities such as thoughts and mathematical objects. The Stoics, who eagerly affirmed that only bodies exist, crafted an elegant solution to this challenge: not everything that is Something (ti) exists. Rather, some things have a derivative mode of reality they call subsistence: these entities are non-existent in that they are not themselves solid bodies, but they are nonetheless Something physical because they depend on bodies for their subsistence. My dissertation uncovers the unifying principles of Stoic subsistence, and shows how they can account for thoughts and other immaterial entities without running afoul of their physicalist commitments. While all commentators agree that the Stoics posited Something as the highest category of being, they have failed to find a coherent physicalist account of Stoic ontology. -
HIMA 20.2 149-194 Ilyenkov.Indd
Historical Materialism 20.2 (2012) 149–193 brill.nl/hima Dialectics of the Ideal (2009) Evald Ilyenkov Abstract E.V. Ilyenkov is widely considered to be the most important Soviet philosopher in the post- Stalin period. He is known largely for his original conception of the ideal, which he deployed against both idealist and crude materialist forms of reductionism, including offfijicial Soviet Diamat. This conception was articulated in its most developed form in ‘Dialectics of the Ideal’ (2009), which was written in the mid-1970s but prevented from publication in its complete form until thirty years after the author’s death. The translation before you provides for the fijirst time the complete, unabridged and unedited text of ‘Dialectics of the Ideal’ in English translation, including the author’s own subsequent comments on the text. Keywords Soviet philosophy, neopositivism, anti-reductionism, consciousness, language The thought of the ideal passing into the real is profound: very important for history. But also in the personal life of man it is clear that this contains much truth. Against vulgar materialism.1 The ‘ideal’ – or the ‘ideality’ of phenomena – is too important a category to be handled thoughtlessly and carelessly, as it is associated not only with a Marxist understanding of the essence of idealism, but even with its naming. Among idealistic doctrines we include all those concepts in philosophy which take as their starting-point of an explanation of history and knowledge a conception of the ideal that is, as it were, partial, unelaborated – as consciousness or will, as thought or as the mind in general, as ‘soul’ or ‘spirit’, as ‘feeling’ or as ‘creativity’, or as ‘socially-organised experience’. -
'Self-Motion': Descartes and the Aristotelians on the Soul As the Life
LIFE AS "SELF-MOTION": DESCARTES AND "THE ARISTOTELIANS" ON THE SOUL AS THE LIFE OF THE BODY SARAH BYERS DESCARTES'S ARGUMENTS THAT THE BODY can be considered a self- propelled machine rely on a misuse of the Aristotelian concept of "self-motion." They depend upon the premise that life is self-motion, the Aristotelian definition which Descartes learned from Latin hand- books at La F16che. By retaining this premise, Descartes believed he was defeating the Aristotelians on their own turf when he argued that soul is unnecessary for explaining life functions (self-motion). How- ever, his arguments fail to establish what he intended them to, be- cause whereas Aristotle meant the capacity for self-induced alteration (qualitative motion), Descartes interpreted "self-motion" as a refer- ence to the local motions of the constitutive parts of a body. That this was a misunderstanding, and not simply a disagreement with Aristo- tle's meaning, can be demonstrated from the Meditations, the Dis- course, the Treatise on Man, the Passions of the Soul, The World, and the letters. Owing to this misinterpretation, Descartes never actually addressed the Aristotelian theory, and so his physics leaves unre- solved a problem that Aristotle is able to solve by positing the soul as the life of the body, namely: Why do some things metabolize, but oth- ers do not? Surprisingly, these points have not yet been made. Though Des Chene has recently drawn attention to the question of "life" in Descartes, he has not noticed this.1 Michael Frede has noted that from Correspondence to: Department of Philosophy, Ave Maria University, 1025 Commons Circle, Naples, FL 34119. -
The Standing of the Soul: the Search for a Middle Being Between God and Matter in the De Statu Animae of Claudianus Mamertus
The Standing of the Soul: The Search for a Middle Being between God and Matter in the De Statu Animae of Claudianus Mamertus Author: Steven Robert Cain Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/bc-ir:105066 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Boston College Electronic Thesis or Dissertation, 2016 Copyright is held by the author, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise noted. Boston College The Graduate School of Arts and Sciences Department of Philosophy THE STANDING OF THE SOUL: THE SEARCH FOR A MIDDLE BEING BETWEEN GOD AND MATTER IN THE DE STATU ANIMAE OF CLAUDIANUS MAMERTUS a dissertation by STEVEN ROBERT CAIN submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy May, 2016 © copyright by STEVEN ROBERT CAIN 2016 ABSTRACT THE STANDING OF THE SOUL: THE SEARCH FOR A MIDDLE BEING BETWEEN GOD AND MATTER IN THE DE STATU ANIMAE OF CLAUDIANUS MAMERTUS Steven Robert Cain Advisor: Dr. Stephen Brown This thesis is intended as a complement to Fr. Ernest Fortin’s Christianisme et culture philosophique. In that work, he examined the De statu animae of Claudianus Mamertus and its affinity to the thought of the Neoplatonic philosophers (especially Porphyry) in order to make its doctrine more clear. But he also looked at it to see the greatness of philosophical spirit that its author possessed, a remarkable spirit considering the time in which he wrote. Though Fr. Fortin’s work is quite thorough, there are some aspects of the De statu animae that are treated only slightly or not at all. -
On the Greek Origins of the Concepts Incorporeality and Immateriality Renehan, R Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies; Summer 1980; 21, 2; Periodicals Archive Online Pg
On the Greek Origins of the Concepts Incorporeality and Immateriality Renehan, R Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies; Summer 1980; 21, 2; Periodicals Archive Online pg. 105 On the Greek Origins of the Concepts Incorporeality and Immateriality R. Renehan EW CONCEPTS have been more influential, for better or F worse, in the history of Western philosophy and theology than those of incorporeal beings and immaterial essences. Their importance for the particular directions which European thought long took in pondering such problems as the nature of deity, soul, intellect, in short, of ultimate reality, is not easily exag gerated. Despite this, there still exists much confusion about the historical origins of the concepts 'incorporeality' and 'immateri ality', and even an occasional failure to grasp the strict implications of these terms. To give some examples: Etienne Drioton, writing about the be liefs of the ancient Egyptians on the afterlife, has made the follow ing observations: "Besides body, [the Egyptians] attributed two elements to man, more or less ghostly and independent of matter: the 'ba' which can apparently be rendered exactly by 'soul' and which they used to represent as a bird with human head; and the 'ka' in which some Egyptologists have seen an immaterial reflec tion of man's body, a 'double' ... Whatever the truth may be, death was definitely regarded by the Egyptians as being the separa tion of the spiritual and corporeal elements of man.... The first element in their belief, and presumably the most ancient, was that the immaterial principle of man, his spirit, continued to live in close connection with the corpse and even depending on it."l The anachronisms here are glaring. -
Andrei Lebedev Pythagoras, Parmenides, Heraclitus
DOI:10.30842/ielcp230690152352 Andrei Lebedev (RAS Institute of Philosophy/HSE University) IDEALISM (MENTALISM) IN EARLY GREEK METAPHYSICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL THEOLOGY: Pythagoras, Parmenides, Heraclitus, Xenophanes and others (with some remarks on the «Gigantomachia over being» in Plato’s Sophist) Abstract and table of contents: (1) Preliminary criticism of the presuppositions of the denial of existence of idealism in early Greek thought: pseudohistorical evolu- tionism, Platonocentrism that ignores the archaic features of Plato’s metaphysics and psychology, and the modern stereotype of «Presocratics» as physicalists, a product of the late 19th century (excessive) positivist reaction against Hegelianism and German idealism in the English-speaking historiography of Greek philosophy. (2) Demiourgos and creationism in Pre-Platonic philosophy. Creation by divine mind is a form of objective idealism (mentalism). (3) The thesis of Myles Burnyeat and Bernard Williams (no idealism in Greek philosophy) is criticized. We point to scholastic and ancient (Platonic) roots of Descartes’ substance dualism of body and mind, as well as to the even more ancient Pythagorean roots of Plato’s doctrine of immortal soul. (4) A provisional taxonomy of different types of idealism (mentalism) in ancient Greek philosophy is proposed. 11 types are distinguished. (5) The evidence of the Orphic-Pythagorean graffiti from Olbia on the early Pythagorean substance dualism of body and soul proves its Preplatonic origin. (6) Criticism of modern naturalistic interpretations of Pythagorean first principles peras and apeiron (Burkert, Huffman and others). Peras and apeiron (a geometrical analogue of later terms form and matter) are self- subsistent incorporeal mathematical essences, out of which physical bodies are «constructed» (ἁρμόζειν, another geometrical term for «construction») by the divine mind-demiourgos. -
Hobbes: Metaphysics and Method
HOBBES: METAPHYSICS AND METHOD BY STEWART DUNCAN A dissertation submitted to the Graduate School—New Brunswick Rutgers, The State University of New Jersey in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Graduate Program in Philosophy Written under the direction of Martha Bolton and approved by New Brunswick, New Jersey October, 2003 c 2003 Stewart Duncan ALL RIGHTS RESERVED ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION Hobbes: Metaphysics and Method by Stewart Duncan Dissertation Director: Martha Bolton This dissertation discusses the work of Thomas Hobbes, and has two main themes. The first is Hobbes’s materialism, and the second is Hobbes’s relation- ships to other philosophers, in particular his place in the mechanist movement that is said to have replaced Aristotelianism as the dominant philosophy in the seventeenth century. I argue that Hobbes does not, for most of his career, believe the general materialist view that bodies are the only substances. He believes, rather, that ideas, which are our main mechanism for thinking about the world, allow us to understand many bodies, but not to understand every thing we recognize to exist. The incomprehensible things include God – and, early in Hobbes’s career, the human mind. Discussing materialism and our knowledge of God leads me to engage with the debate over Hobbes’s alleged atheism. I argue that the evidence for Hobbes’s atheism is weak at best. Hobbes is a sincere theist, though his view is sometimes unusual. My discussion of Hobbes’s relationships to other philosophers has three parts. In chapter five I argue that Hobbes’s views about method are in important ways ii similar to Zabarella’s. -
Divine Embodiment in Jewish Antiquity: Rediscovering the Jewishness of John’S Incarnate Christ
Divine Embodiment in Jewish Antiquity: Rediscovering The Jewishness of John’s Incarnate Christ by Deborah L. Forger A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (Near Eastern Studies) in the University of Michigan 2017 Doctoral Committee: Professor Gabriele Boccaccini, Chair Associate Professor Ellen Muehlberger Associate Professor Rachel Neis Professor Ray Van Dam Deborah L. Forger [email protected] ORCID iD: 0000-0003-1285-7880 © Deborah L. Forger 2017 All Rights Reserved For Danny, Daniel, and Olivia ii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS This thesis has been a labor of love and it would never have been birthed into existence without the guidance, support, and aid of many people. To my chair, Gabriele Boccaccini, I owe enormous thanks. My transition back into academia after working in parish ministry was more challenging than I had anticipated and he took a real chance on me. His enthusiasm for the Second Temple Period instilled within me an equal fervor for this beautiful area of research and enabled me to fuse my previous training in scriptural exegesis with an equally rigorous attention to the history and culture of this period in Jewish history. His instrumental role in the establishment of the Enoch Seminar and his ongoing vision for its future potential also afforded a young scholar like myself an unparalleled opportunity to engage with leading specialists in our field, often in some of the most pristine locations in Italy. The collaborative atmosphere that these meetings fosters testifies to the ongoing potential of scholarship to bridge the gap between different disciplines and to dismantle divisions that have previously stymied progress in the study of the origins of two major world religions.