Dutch Books, Additivity, and Utility Theory1
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
An Improved Dutch Book Theorem for Conditionalization
An Improved Dutch Book Theorem for Conditionalization Michael Rescorla Abstract: Lewis proved a Dutch book theorem for Conditionalization. The theorem shows that an agent who follows any credal update rule other than Conditionalization is vulnerable to bets that inflict a sure loss. Lewis’s theorem is tailored to factive formulations of Conditionalization, i.e. formulations on which the conditioning proposition is true. Yet many scientific and philosophical applications of Bayesian decision theory require a non-factive formulation, i.e. a formulation on which the conditioning proposition may be false. I prove a Dutch book theorem tailored to non-factive Conditionalization. I also discuss the theorem’s significance. §1. Diachronic Dutch books The diachronic norm Conditionalization is a central plank of Bayesian decision theory. Conditionalization requires that, in certain situations, you conditionalize on a proposition E by replacing your old credences P with new credences Pnew given by: Pnew(H) = P(H | E). Here P(H | E) is the old conditional probability of H given E, defined by the ratio formula: PHE(&) PHE( | ) PE() for cases where P(E) > 0. A conditioning proposition is a proposition on which you have conditionalized. The probability calculus axioms entail that P(E | E) = 1, so conditionalizing on E requires you to become certain of E, i.e. to set Pnew(E) = 1. 2 Philosophers pursue various strategies for defending Conditionalization. One prominent strategy builds upon the classic Dutch book arguments advanced by Ramsey (1931) and de Finetti (1937/1980). A Dutch book is a set of acceptable bets that guarantees a net loss. You are Dutch bookable when it is possible to rig a Dutch book against you. -
FRANK RAMSEY OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 7/1/2020, Spi OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 7/1/2020, Spi
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 7/1/2020, SPi FRANK RAMSEY OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 7/1/2020, SPi OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 7/1/2020, SPi CHERYL MISAK FRANK RAMSEY a sheer excess of powers 1 OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 7/1/2020, SPi 3 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, OXDP, United Kingdom Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries © Cheryl Misak The moral rights of the author have been asserted First Edition published in Impression: All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this work in any other form and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press Madison Avenue, New York, NY , United States of America British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Control Number: ISBN –––– Printed and bound in Great Britain by Clays Ltd, Elcograf S.p.A. Links to third party websites are provided by Oxford in good faith and for information only. -
On De Finetti's Instrumentalist Philosophy of Probability
Forthcoming in the European Journal for Philosophy of Science On de Finetti’s instrumentalist philosophy of probability Joseph Berkovitz1 Abstract. De Finetti is one of the founding fathers of the subjective school of probability. He held that probabilities are subjective, coherent degrees of expectation, and he argued that none of the objective interpretations of probability make sense. While his theory has been influential in science and philosophy, it has encountered various objections. I argue that these objections overlook central aspects of de Finetti’s philosophy of probability and are largely unfounded. I propose a new interpretation of de Finetti’s theory that highlights these aspects and explains how they are an integral part of de Finetti’s instrumentalist philosophy of probability. I conclude by drawing an analogy between misconceptions about de Finetti’s philosophy of probability and common misconceptions about instrumentalism. 1. Introduction De Finetti is one of the founding fathers of the modern subjective school of probability. In this school of thought, probabilities are commonly conceived as coherent degrees of belief, and expectations are defined in terms of such probabilities. By contrast, de Finetti took expectation as the fundamental concept of his theory of probability and subjective probability as derivable from expectation. In his theory, probabilities are coherent degrees of expectation.2 De Finetti represents the radical wing of the subjective school of probability, denying the existence of objective probabilities. He held that probabilities and probabilistic reasoning are subjective and that none of the objective interpretations of probability make sense. Accordingly, he rejected the idea that subjective probabilities are guesses, predictions, or hypotheses about objective probabilities. -
Variant on Lewis's Diachronic Dutch Book
A Dutch Book Theorem and Converse Dutch Book Theorem for Kolmogorov Conditionalization Michael Rescorla Abstract: This paper discusses how to update one’s credences based on evidence that has initial probability 0. I advance a diachronic norm, Kolmogorov Conditionalization, that governs credal reallocation in many such learning scenarios. The norm is based upon Kolmogorov’s theory of conditional probability. I prove a Dutch book theorem and converse Dutch book theorem for Kolmogorov Conditionalization. The two theorems establish Kolmogorov Conditionalization as the unique credal reallocation rule that avoids a sure loss in the relevant learning scenarios. §1. Dutch book arguments for conditionalization How should you update your credences in light of new evidence? The most widely discussed norm is Conditionalization, which requires that: If you assign credence P(H) to a proposition H, and you gain new evidence that is exhausted by knowledge of E, then you respond to your new evidence by assigning credence P(H | E) to H. Here P(H | E) is the conditional probability of H given E. Conditionalization traces back to Bayes’s seminal discussion (Bayes and Price, 1763). It is a linchpin of Bayesian decision theory. Philosophers have pursued various strategies for justifying Conditionalization. One prominent strategy builds upon the classic Dutch book arguments advanced by Ramsey (1931) 2 and de Finetti (1937/1980). A Dutch book is a collection of acceptable bets that inflict a sure loss. An agent is Dutch bookable when it is possible to rig a Dutch book against her. Dutch bookability is a very undesirable property, because a sufficiently devious bookie can pump a Dutch bookable agent for money by offering her bets that she gladly accepts.