<<

Review and History 2017; 5(1): 38-46

Neurosciences and philosophy: what is new in the 21st century? M. L. Vargas1,2 1Department of . Complejo Asistencial de Zamora, Spain. 2Segovia Clinical Research Group (GINCS). Segovia, Spain.

ABSTRACT

is article aims to clarify certain questions currently being debated around the intersection between neuroscience and philosophy. Four areas of the subject are addressed: a) neuromania: the problem of reducing philosophy to computational neuroscience and its abuses in the form of the naturalistic fallacy; b) : conditions of possibility of humanisation and hope as a horizon for a subjective morality; c) posthumanism: the default mode network as a substrate of the self, and the postmodernist dissolution of the of self; and d) : the problem of , its physical substrate in psychons, and the proposal of the “brains- problem”. e contributions of several recent philosophers, including Habermas, Ricoeur, Cortina, Varela, and Bunge, are reviewed. It is proposed that 21st-century neuroscience may contribute to a better of the neurological processes underlying the creation of a common logos through better understanding of the conditions of possibility of the emergence of mental properties in “minding matter”. Consciousness is an important indicator, but not the only indicator, of this kind of ontological emergence. is will contribute to the prevention, by philosophical anthropology, of two ap orias of subjectivity: alienation and suicide, both of individuals and of humans as a species.

KEYWORDS

Philosophy, neuroscience, neuroethics, brain, mind, consciousness

Introduction whether these disciplines really do share a  eld of interest or whether, on the contrary, they address entirely e neurosciences and philosophy have a shared interest separate issues, concealed behind the polysemy of terms in certain problems, such as the problem of consciousness like “mind” or “consciousness”, derived from popular or the issue of purposive behaviour. is intersection has psychology. been addressed by the philosophy of psychiatry, among other disciplines. e Oxford University Press has Any scienti c discipline, because it deals in facts, must published a range of material on the subject, exempli ed be considered as a uni ed entity, as true facts do not by its Textbook of philosophy and psychiatry.1 We may be allow for mutual contradiction. Furthermore, science justi ed, therefore, in reviewing the intersections of these itself appeals to an ideology of the “unity of science”, disciplines within a narrower timeframe. ere are two whereby science would be the set of proven facts, or in grounds for criticising this approach, however:  rstly, we other words, the set of truths. We will therefore use the must examine the de nitions of these disciplines (why word “neuroscience”, in the singular, from here on. e “neurosciences and philosophy” and not “neuroscience pre x “neuro-” refers to the study of the section of reality and philosophies”?); and secondly, we must consider comprising the set of nervous systems.

Corresponding author: Dr Martín Lorenzo Vargas Aragón Received: 09 May 2017 / Accepted: 05 July 2017 E-mail: [email protected] © 2017 Sociedad Española de Neurología

38 Neurosciences and philosophy

Philosophy, on the other hand, is better expressed as a Development plurality. If we take philosophy to mean the path towards the truth, then it is fundamentally a method. Plato Neuromania? embraces dialectics to the extent that in e Republic (VII, 533d),2 Socrates asserts that “only the dialectical García-Albea6 has critiqued the current proliferation way of inquiry proceeds in this direction, destroying the of the pre x “neuro-”, compiling a list of 30 “neuro- hypotheses, to the beginning itself in order to make it Xes”, from neuroculture to and secure”. Philosophical methods have always been diverse, . In his 2011 book Apin g mankind. before and since Plato. At the risk of oversimplifying Neuromania, Darwinitis and the misrepresentation the question, contemporary Western philosophical of humanity7, Raymond Tallis proposes the term traditions can be grouped into four families: Anglo- “neuromaniac” to describe proponents of t he Saxon analytical philosophy; continental philosophy, that human behaviour can be explained exhaustively in¨ uenced by phenomenology, hermeneutics, and by neuroscience. Tallis believes that neuromaniacs, postmodernist poststructuralism; the critical theory of together with su¬ erers of “Darwinitis” (who explain 3,4 the Frankfurt School; and materialist philosophy. human behaviour as an evolutionary adaptation), may is narrative review aims to clarify certain questions be promoting excessive theoretical simpli cation, with currently being debated around the intersection between morally and politically dangerous consequences. Are we neuroscience and these four philosophical traditions. e no more than our brains? review is limited loosely to the 21st century, taking into An important issue here is the reduction of epistemology account the proposal of the “short 20th century”, ending to neuroscience. e current reductionist debate 5 with the collapse of the Soviet Union in late 1991 and began in 1986, with the analytical philosopher Patricia coinciding with the Decade of the Brain. Selecting which Churchland’s book : toward a uni ed questions to investigate is of greater diª culty: is the mind science of the mind-brain.8 Churchland proposes a real, or is it a cultural construct? Is mind the same thing reduction of to neuroscience, for a as it is for a philosopher? Should the modelled a° er the work of Pellionisz and Llinás, which philosophical mind be reduced to the neuroscienti c enabled the geometrisation of the structure and function mind? Is it the place of philosophy to set the agenda of the cerebellum as a tensor network. According to this for neuroscienti c investigation? Furthermore, how do model, mental representations would be di¬ erent states a scientist’s mind and the dominant discourse of her of the system’s phase space, and cerebral computation community in¨ uence her e¬ orts to carry out “objective” would be no more than the series of coordinate neuroscienti c research? Is it even possible to speak transformations between said phase spaces.8(p426) From objectively about subjectivity? this position of reductionist , Churchland We will brie¨ y address these questions and others defends a distributed connectionist model of the brain, from four di¬ erent perspectives: 1) neuromania, 2) ruling out the existence of hypothetical “grandmother neuroethics, 3) posthumanism, and 4) qualia. Other cells” with the capacity to react to speci c stimuli 9 approaches could have been chosen; it is hoped that this (see Quiroga’s article for a review of the problem of one may illustrate, even roughly, the 21st-century synergy gnostic cells or “grandmother cells”). Neurophilosophy between philosophical constructs and neuroscienti c understands science and philosophy as paired, mutually fact. e aim of this is to contribute to the use in enriching disciplines. e concept of “metascience” neuroscience, and particularly in , of (by de nition always in the singular) would be the models with a grounding in ontology, semantics, ethics, asymptotic extreme where the two disciplines become 10 and epistemology, in order to meaningfully interpret the one in the mind of the researcher. overwhelming deluge of information being produced is reductionist approach has focused on developing by neuroscience. Finally, scienti c communication does computational models. ere is broad consensus that not escape the hermeneutic circle, which is nonetheless these should not be formalised in lineal mathematical in¨ uenced by an echo of probabilism in the scienti c terms; rather, they should model nonlinear complex speech acts re¨ ecting a silent reality. systems (Gabbiani and Cox’s Mathematics for

39 M. L. Vargas neuroscientists11 is a good guide). Computational It would appear to be impossible to approach the neuroscience and systems neuroscience12 are the important issue of morality from a solely computational dominant paradigms in today.13 standpoint. Computational neuroscience takes cerebral Between the biological (or implementational) and processes as a point of reference, but morality is social the phenomenological (or symbolic mental) levels of in nature. e regulation of interpersonal conduct is analysis, we are witnessing the development of the beyond the reach of the computer metaphor, giving us subsymbolic mental (or computational) level of analysis grounds to wonder whether a naturalist reduction of (see Bermúdez14 and Dayan et al.15 for an introduction to ethics may also be possible. computational models). Neuroethics: the conditions of possibility of e clinical usefulness of clarifying the philosophical humanisation issue of neuronal reductionism is perhaps most evident in the context of atte ntion-de cit/hyperactivity disorder In 2002, the  rst conference on neuroethics was organised (ADHD), which has become a highly controversial by the Dana Foundation, Stanford University’s Center issue. Supported by the prestige of Nature Neuroscience, 21 16 for Biomedical Ethics, and the University of California. defenders of neuroscience could employ Sigman’s e event was followed by several publications, including arguments for evidence-based education. e use of Neuroética. Cuando la materia se despierta (Neuroethics. psychostimulants to treat children with ADHD would When matter awakens), by the philosopher Kathinka then simply be derived from the ethical duty to mitigate Evers,22 and e neuroscience of freedom and creativity: the disadvantage associated with a medical condition. our predictive brain, by the neuroscientist Joaquín M. Critical theorists opposing neuromania might refer Fuster.23 to Jürgen Habermas’s 1968 critique of technocratic Adela Cortina24 draws a distinction between the ethics discourse as an instrument of capitalism, in his book of neuroscience and the neuroscience of ethics. In the Technology and science as ideology.17 Concerning clinical  rst, neuroethics would simply be a branch of bioethics. neuroscience, followers of the Frankfurt School would e second viewpoint would be of greater philosophical argue that the monolithic discourse of scientism, the interest; according to Cortina: DSM classi cations in use, opinion leaders in the pay of “Big Pharma”, and the invention of new diseases are Evidently, if the neuroscience of ethics has an impact no more than techniques employed by capitalist power. on our understanding of human agency, then it is Neither has schizophrenia escaped postmodernist not merely another branch of applied ethics; rather, critique.18 Philosophical analysis of the problem of it must be its central axis, as it sheds light on issues as complex as liberty, choice, rationality, and agency neuromania raises several epistemological questions to itself. e neuroscience of ethics is therefore central which computational neuroscience can now provide an to our political, moral, and social aspirations.24 answer. Other questions invite us to re¨ ect on arguments that resolve the “naturalistic fallacy”, made in the 18th Alluding to the naturalistic fallacy, Cortina asks: “can century by David Hume and in the 20th by Karl-Otto Apel we truly make the step from the cerebral ‘is’ to the and George Moore. Dussel19 analyses these arguments moral ‘ought’?” Her article discusses certain common in detail. Readers interested in the naturalistic fallacy inexactitudes of neuroethical experimentation, are also recommended to read Javier Muguerza’s “ ‘Es’ y concluding that neuroscience, together with other ‘debe’ (En torno a la lógica de la falacia naturalista)” (“ ‘Is’ scienti c disciplines, reveals the human propensity for and ‘ought’ [On the logic of th e naturalistic fallacy]”), cooperation, but does not constitute the foundation for the second chapter of his book La razón sin esperanza a universal ethics. 20 (Reason without hope), where he explains that: By demonstrating that the tendency towards cooperation is a human universal, neuroethics supports Aranguren’s the naturalist fallacy consists in attempting to proposal that morality brings structure to humankind.25 derive conclusions expressed in evaluative language However, hominisation is not the same thing as (the language of value judgements or norms) from premises expressed in descriptive language (the humanisation. María Zambrano maintains that an language of judgements of fact).20(p80) animal is “born in a moment” and then adapts, while

40 Neurosciences and philosophy humans “are never fully born”; rather, hope leads them to explanation could be how the pathological suppression seek the completion of the project they aspire to become: of structures related to moral control is accompanied “hope is the substance of our lives; it is what lies behind by the disinhibition of “subhuman” conduct (impulsive all else.”26(p112) aggression, for example). However, as this is not a It would appear, then, that neuroethics’ promise to create suª cient condition, explanations for good, justice, a universal ethics only goes as far as hominisation, but and duty should be sought elsewhere, in the subjective cannot reach the level of humanisation. In other words, understanding of the motives of human behaviour, the neuroethics can reveal the conditions of possibility conscious self as a moral subject. for moral conduct, but not the speci c course to be followed: cerebral integrity would be a necessary but not Posthumanism? a suª cient condition for free, intelligible moral conduct. Henry Ey sensed this in his description of mental illness e conscious self as a moral subject is a concept deeply as a “pathology of freedom”, noting that freedom has rooted in the philosophy of Descartes and Kant, and been considered a necessary condition for morality is essential for us to understand the Enlightenment since Kant. In the light of the approaches summarised humanism that gave way to the modern era. Some above, it is clear that science, including neuroethics, believe this ideal to have disintegrated a° er May 1968, appears to remain axiologically neutral: it can say little while others consider it still to be valid. Philosophical on moral values. Moral philosophy, then, continues anthropology matured over the course of the 20th to be independent of science. Man essentially remains century, with pretensions of becoming a  rst philosophy open, hoping for emancipation, whether as a member with the subject as the source of its argumentation. e of a dialoguing community27 or as a dissident subject, latter third of the 20th century saw the convergence of the attracted to, like Javier Muguerza, the irrationality of analytical tradition of the “self”, rooted in language, and hope.28 Ernst Bloch best explains the function of hope: the concept of the transcendental, phenomenological subject, rooted in . is led to the idea of the Yet Heraclitus says, ‘Whoever does not hope for the subject as the author of speech acts and the zero-point of unexpected will not  nd it.’ is should be enough the self anchored both to a body and to the world. to invok e t he call to action, according to which human existence —in the transcendental sense e default mode network (DMN) has become the upon which this existence is founded— means that main candidate considered for the material correlate of which transgresses or goes beyond.29(p210) the concept of self. A complete review of the subject33 postulates that the main function of the DMN is to allow Without analysing in detail this opening-up of human ¨ exible, self-relevant mental explorations (simulations), nature, we should note at least the potential of aesthetics a way of predicting and evaluating the results of a as a treatment framework. Let us consider, for example, situation before it takes place. Its role in tasks involving art therapy or music therapy from the perspective of autobiographical memory, prospection, mentalisation, Ortega y Gasset’s conception of man as a “fantastic and moral decision-making supports the suggestion 30 31 animal” , or María Zambrano’s application of poetic that DMN is the biological substrate of the self. e reason to psychotherapy. Both examples could serve as a psychological and philosophical construct of subjectivity 32 reference point for future neuroaesthetics research. is characterised by temporality, self-awareness, and Neuroethics does not recognise the ultimate questions morality. Drawing on arguments from computational of ethics: what is good? What is just? How must we neuroscience and an exhaustive review of Freud’s oeuvre, behave? Understanding of the cerebral processes studied it has also been proposed that the DMN may also be by neuroethics, as a necessary condition for ethics, the substrate of the psychoanalytical concept of “ego”.34 could help explain amoral behaviour (if we accept that In his theoretical framework for , morality is the structure underpinning the human Northo¬ 35 performs a detailed analysis of this possibility, condition, amorality could be classi ed as subhuman and studying object relations from the perspective of immorality as inhuman): since the case of Phineas Gage, neuroscience. Since Kandel36, numerous works have numerous examples have been published. A possible sought meeting-points between neuroscience and

41 M. L. Vargas ; see, for example, Ansermet and Once mind and subjectivity are deconstructed, all that Magistretti’s37 book approaching from a remains is consciousness, in the Cartesian sense. Perhaps Lacanian perspective. We will not discuss in detail the neuroscience and philosophy can converge here, to tackle vast body of literature on mentalisation and its relation the hard problem of consciousness? Could we shed light to the DMN, Buddhist meditation, and the practice of on the ontology of qualia? “mindfulness”. Santachita and Vargas38 can be consulted for a critical review of these issues from a philosophical Qualia: the brain-mind problem perspective. However, while the  rst decade of the 21st century saw e Oxford Companion to Philosophy de nes “qualia” as neuroscience begin to address the neuronal substrate of “the subjective qualities of conscious experience (plural t he self, the 1990s saw philosophy beginning to abandon of the Latin singular quale).42 Qualia are indescribable the subject. In 1990, Paul Ricoeur published Soi-même which refer to the secondary qualities of comme un autre,39 in wh ich he developed his thesis of the things, such as colour. ey are prior to language and “broken cogito”. e theory, revisiting Nietzsche, posits behave as shared semantic  elds that are understood the self as merely an illusion of the Cartesian cogito: the a priori, prior to any speech act. For example, the death of God is joined by the death of the self and of experience of the colour red cannot be de ned; rather, the modern concept of subject. is was anticipated by familiarity is assumed before an object is described as Barthes, with his death of the author, and later by French being red. e problem of qualia is the main challenge poststructuralism, led by Foucault and Derrida. for the various ontological models of mind tasked with explaining the nature of conscious experience. In the postmodern era, the modern concept of self no longer represents the image of what is human. e If neuroscience is comfortable with studying mind, the “Sloterdijk-Habermas controversy” in Germany in same cannot be said of consciousness. A° er the cognitive 43 1999 led to the consolidation of posthumanism40 as the revolution instigated by Howard Gardner in 1985, contemporary image of humanity. is debate, which arti cial models gave rise to the computer has not escaped political interpretation, began with a metaphor in the study of cognitive processes. Later, the connectionist paradigm also accommodated for new eugenics debate centred around biotechnology and 44 cybernetics. Posthumanism posits that classic humanistic the mind (Blanco’s general is recommended). However, conscious experience was not education as the ideal for progress has been surpassed accepted as an object of neuroscienti c study until nearly by scienti c advancement, and that humankind could 20 years later, with the rediscovery of the phenomenology be improved by overtly technological means. And if of Husserl and Merleau-Ponty. e words of Joaquín the human body can be improved through technology, Fuster serve by way of example: “…phenomenology — then the same appears to be true of the self. In our times, the analysis of conciousness— is increasingly recognised dominated by the use of social media, personal as a useful method in cognitive science and, accordingly, has acquired a hitherto unknown polymorphism: it is no in cognitive neuroscience”.45(p249) e renewed interest in longer a case simply of identifying a sameness linking consciousness requires a robust handling of the brain- the di¬ erent selves anchored to a single body, but of mind problem. Recommended literature on the subject joining this corporeal identity with the various virtual includes the recent reviews by Goñi-Sáez46 and Tirapu47; selves that make up the complex postmodern subject, Gallagher and Zahavi’s book e phenomenological which is increasingly expressed through virtual speech mind48; and Damásio’s books Descartes’ error49 and acts, less tied to the body. At the same time, however, Looking for Spinoza,50 which focus more on materialism the new “post-truth” appears to be travelling in the and science outreach. other direction, departing from cold reason in favour of unstable, emotional argument. is context, together e embodied mind: cognitive science and human with possibility of understanding identity experience,51 the 1991 book by Francisco J. Varela, through , has sparked a complex debate Evan ompson, and Eleanor Rosch, brings around the reinterpretation of human rights, no longer together the dynamic, non-linear study of conscious serviceable in the new posthuman world.41 processes and the phenomenological and Buddhist

42 Neurosciences and philosophy traditions under the umbrella of “enaction”. Varela Varela. Systemics is also coherent with the formation proposes neurophenomenology as a methodological of brain-world systems such as that anticipated in the solution to the hard problem of consciousness.52-55 19th century by , who considered the Neurophenomenology also allows for compatibility mind to possess , an idea revisited by his between the phenomenological tradition and disciple Husserl, and later by the phenomenological connectionist computational models.56 According to the tradition. Similarly, in the mid-20th century, Viktor neurophenomenological theory of enaction, object and von Weizsäcker’s philosophical anthropology described subject are part of a single dynamic process; therefore, the “circle of form” (der Gestaltkreis), postulating the objectivity and subjectivity would be a single entity, as unity of perception and movement. More recently, would epistemology and ontology. eise57 defends Joaquín Fuster has made a similar appeal to this system, a similar, markedly holistic, approach based on self- proposing the term “perception-action cycle”.65 organising complex systems and quantum mechanics. He proposes the existence of a substratum of fundamental Conclusions awareness, a theory focusing on information over matter and action over agency. According to the fundamental We have brie¨ y reviewed some of the philosophical awareness theory, qualia are not the “hard problem of traditions and issues that are of interest to neuroscience. consciousness”; in fact, they are the foundational elements is article has discussed these subjects only of all existence. Similar holistic approaches to the issue super cially; a wealth of additional information and 58 of qualia are Chalmers’ panpsychofunctionalism and discussion can be found in the literature. is article has 59 Velmans’ re¨ exive . attempted to demonstrate the way in which philosophy In this author’s opinion, the emergentist materialism appears, in some sense, to lead the way for new lines defended by Mario Bunge60,61 is the best theoretical of enquiry in neuroscience. At times, neuroscience framework from which to ap proach the brain-mind contributes theoretical or mathematical models, and problem from the perspective of neuroscience: Bunge’s even demonstrated fact, but at others its only result is the system is materialist, systematic, emergentist, realist, increasing noise of uninformative data. and scienti c; all these properties are compatible with erefore, the epistemological problem of mind seems to neuroscience. Bunge de nes “emergence” as follows: be delegated to computational neuroscience models, and “To say that P is an emergent property of systems of may be reduced to these models. e metascience born kind K is short for P is a global (or collective or non- of the hybridisation of epistemology and computational distributive) property of a system of kind K, none of neuroscience revives the Greek logos, with its triple sense whose components or precursors possesses P”.62(p32) In of word, reason, and link. However, with posthumanism, other words, deals with the properties the path of subjectivity appears to dissolve due to the loss belonging to systems but not to the elements making up of a semantic reference for the concept of “self”. Similarly, said systems. According to Bunge, qualia are an emergent it seems possible that the path of neuroethics is simply a property of minding matter. Minding matter would be projection towards hope. organised into psychons, which Bunge de nes as plastic e human being is an open universe. e 21st century neuronal systems. Note that the concept “psychon” was has seen the emergence of philosophical anthropology originally proposed by Eccles,63,64 although from a dualist as a promising  rst philosophy oriented towards hope perspective whereby the psychon is a mental element (for an introduction to philosophical anthropology from interacting with a neural counterpart, the “dendron”. a phenomenological perspective, see San Martín66,67). Furthermore, the systemic nature of Bunge’s model is In order to become a  rst philosophy, philosophical particularly well-suited to the study of mental events anthropology must be based in a scienti c understanding emerging in cognitive systems made up of the brain of reality. Philosophers must therefore be familiar with and the world. Systemics facilitates heuristic continuity computational advances in neuroscience. However, with the classic dynamic biological models proposed philosophical anthropology must also have the capacity by Ludwig von Bertalan¬ y’s general systems theory, to describe the changing  gure of the human being in and later by Humberto Maturana and Francisco the 21st century and precisely de ne the philosophical

43 M. L. Vargas issues that may inspire the future work of . model, ’s55,75 “neural assemblies”, Joaquín is close, bilateral collaboration is the only way to Fuster’s45,65 “cognits”, Peter van der Helm’s76 “gnosons”, or prevent one discipline from losing sight of the other in a Meehan and Bressler’s77,78 “neurocognitive networks”. continually growing Tower of Babel. Such an enquiry into the conditions of possibility e ontological issue of qualia is potentially the most of the emergence of mental properties and its most important issue today for collaboration between characteristic indicator (consciousness) is of clinical neuroscience and philosophies. If we accept Bunge’s usefulness for at least two reasons. Firstly, it de nes emergentist monism as the option that is most compatible the discipline of clinical neuroscience in a way that is with neuroscience, as well as his proposal that mental coherent with materialist ontology.79 Secondly, it helps properties are an attribute of psychons, and consider the in formulating clinical problems as inverse problems mind to be a radically intersubjective emergent property, (scienti c problems are forward; technological problems then it would remain for future philosophical enquiry, are inverse). For example, Otto Dörr characterised linguistics, and to clarify whether schizophrenia as a logopathy, or pathology of the logos.80 it would not be more appropriate to formulate the brain- In this case, the inverse problem is the diagnostic mind problem as the “brains-mind problem”. If systems usefulness of the abnormal experiences called “basic neuroscience takes the brains-mind problem as an object symptoms”,81 which are probably indirect indicators of of study and focuses on the understanding of combined the underlying connectopathy of the disorder.82 Another human action68 and the role of “self” in this action,69 then example of an inverse problem in clinical practice, in it may shed light on the conditions of possibility of the this case from clinical , is elucidating whether logos and the transcendental subject. e exacti cation or not consciousness exists in a vegetative state and of the brains-mind problem will require study into understanding the relation of this with akinetic mutism.83 the way in which shared semantic  elds are created in Problems of this type represent the path along which intersubject speech acts and the role in social clinical neurophenomenology must develop. of mediators of neuroplasticity. is involves a revision of Subjectivity is the hermeneutic system of a body open to Scheler’s theory of love70 in the language of neuroscience. inter-individual communication.84 When this openness Finally, the new challenge of the 21st century will be the is lost, or in other words when communication ceases, modelling, exacti cation, description, and empirical the self is thrown into aporia. is leaves two options: objecti cation of the mechanisms that give rise to mental alienation or suicide. e 20th century was a sad neural systems through interaction between plastic neural experiment and warning of both aporias of the self. systems located in one or several brains. e mechanisms When human relationships are merely instrumental, of intracerebral connectivity have been better modelled the uncommunicative subject is alienated as a thing than mechanisms of intercerebral connectivity. Regarding or “thingi ed”, as described by San Martín.85(p278) e the latter, speech acts seem to be the main mechanism, aporia of the collective subjectivity born of romantic with neurohormonal communication through smell led  rst to the alienation of fascism, and then also playing an important role. Other alternatives, such to modernity’s suicide, the Second World War. is was as the application of quantum mechanics to the brain, the conclusion of a story that began with the re¨ exive defended by neuroquantology71 and other holistic subject of the Greeks. e appropriation of logos as approaches appear to be of limited compatibility with dreamed by Plato a° er his Pythagorean voyage to Sicily, the currently validated models, which are closer to a that early hubris of dreaming an individual, immortal systematic ontology like the one proposed by Bunge. To soul, extinguished itself in Hiroshima and was awakened summarise the systematic materialist proposals based on to this fact in Paris in May 1968. Since then, it has only neuronal organisation, we can cite various connectionist been possible to understand subjectivity as a shared models, which have assisted in our understanding of the subjectivity in the hope for peace. is is what is new in systemic organisation of the brain: Donald Hebb’s72 “cell the 21st century, the hope that neuroscience may clarify assemblies”, Dalbir Bindra’s73 “presently excited gnostic the way in which the plastic circuits of the brain interact organisation” (pexgo), Alexander Luria’s74 “working through language, forming a shared logos. is would constellations of neurons”, Mario Bunge’s60,61 “psychon” make it possible to  nd the path by which a morality

44 Neurosciences and philosophy founded on a perpetual, open dialogue may harmonise 21. Marcus SJ, ed. Neuroethics: mapping the  eld: conference human life, doing away with both alienation and suicide. proceedings, May 13-14, 2002, San Francisco, California. Nueva York: Dana Press; 2002. Con‘ icts of interest 22. Evers K. Neuroética: cuando la materia se despierta. Buenos Aires: Katz Editores; 2010. e author has no con¨ ict of interest to declare. 23. Fuster JM. Cerebro y libertad: los cimientos cerebrales de References nuestra capacidad para elegir. Barcelona: Ariel; 2014. 24. Cortina A. Neuroética: ¿Las bases cerebrales de una ética 1. Fulford KWM, ornton T, Graham G. Oxford textbook universal con relevancia política? Isegoría. 2010;42:129-48. of philosophy and psychiatry. Oxford: Oxford University 25. Aranguren JLL. Ética. Madrid: Biblioteca Nueva; 1997. Press; 2006. 26. Zambrano M. Hacia un saber sobre el alma. Madrid: 2. Platón. República. Madrid: Editorial Gredos; 2011. [Bloom Alianza Editorial; 2008. A, trans. e Republic of Plato. New York: Hachette; 2016] 27. Apel KO. La globalización y una ética de la responsabilidad: 3. D’Agostini F. Analíticos y continentales: guía de la  losofía re¨ exiones  losó cas acerca de la globalización. Buenos de los últimos treinta años. 2nd ed. Madrid: Cátedra; 2009. Aires: Prometeo Libros; 2007. 4. Charbonnat P. Historia de las  losofías materialistas. 28. Aramayo RR. Las (sin)razones de la esperanza en Javier Barcelona: Biblioteca Buridán; 2010. Muguerza e Inmanuel Kant. Isegoría. 2004;30:91-106. 5. Hobsbawm E. La era de los extremos. El corto siglo XX: 29. Bloch E. ¿Puede frustrarse la esperanza? In: Gómez Sánchez 1914-1991. Madrid: Editorial Crítica; 1995. C, ed. Doce textos fundamentales de la ética del siglo XX. 6. García-Albea JE. Usos y abusos de lo ‘neuro’. Rev Neurol. 2ª ed. Madrid: Alianza Editorial; 2014. p.201-210. [Richter 2011;52:577-80. G. A° erness:  gures of following in modern thought and 7. Tallis R. Aping mankind: neuromania, Darwinitis and the aesthetics. New York: Columbia University Press; 2011. misrepresentation of humanity. Durham (UK): Acumen p.167] Publishing; 2011. 30. Conill-Sancho J. La superación del naturalismo en Ortega y 8. Churchland PS. Neurophilosophy: toward a uni ed science Gasset. Isegoría. 2012;46:167-92. of the mind-brain. Cambridge (MA): MIT Press; 1986. 31. Del Moral Sagarmínaga M. La luz de la oscuridad: una 9. Quiroga RQ. Gnostic cells in the 21st century. Acta aproximación al pensamiento de María Zambrano desde la Neurobiol Exp (Wars). 2013;73:463-71. psicología profunda. Madrid: Plaza y Valdés; 2017. 10. Faust D. Paul Meehl as methodologist-philosopher of 32. Zaidel DW. is not just about art. Front Hum science: the formulation of metascience. J Abnorm Psychol. Neurosci. 2015;9:80. 2006;115:205-9. 33. Buckner RL, Andrews-Hanna JR, Schacter DL. e brain’s 11. Gabbiani F, Cox SJ. Mathematics for neuroscientists. 2nd ed. default network: anatomy, function, and relevance to London: Academic Press; 2017. disease. Ann N Y Acad Sci. 2008;1124:1-38. 12. Kansaku K, Cohen L, Birbaumer N, eds. Clinical systems 34. Carhart-Harris RL, Friston KJ. e default-mode, ego- neuroscience. Tokyo: Springer; 2015. functions and free-energy: a neurobiological account of 13. Kotchoubey B, Tretter F, Braun HA, Buchheim T, Draguhn Freudian . Brain. 2010;133:1265-83. A, Fuchs T, et al. Methodological problems on the way to 35. Northo¬ G. Neuropsychoanalysis in practice: brain, self, integrative human neuroscience. Front Integr Neurosci. and objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2011. 2016;10:41. 36. Kandel ER. In search of memory: the emergence of a new 14. Bermúdez JL. Cognitive science: an introduction to science of mind. New York: W.W. Norton & Company; the science of the mind. Cambridge (UK): Cambridge 2007. University Press; 2014. 37. Ansermet F, Magistretti P. A cada cual su cerebro: 15. Dayan P, Abbott LF. eoretical neuroscience: plasticidad neuronal e inconsciente. Buenos Aires: Katz computational and mathematical modeling of neural Editores; 2006. systems. Cambridge (MA): MIT Press; 2001. 38. Santachita A, Vargas ML. Mindfulness en perspectiva. 16. Sigman M, Peña M, Goldin AP, Ribeiro S. Neuroscience and Revista de la Asociación Española de Neuropsiquiatría. education: prime time to build the bridge. Nat Neurosci. 2015;35:541-53. 2014;17:497-502. 39. Ricoeur P. Sí mismo como otro. Madrid: Siglo XXI Editores; 17. Habermas J. Ciencia y técnica como “ideología”. 7th ed. 1996. Madrid: Editorial Tecnos; 2010. 40. Vásquez Rocca A. Sloterdijk, Habermas y Heidegger; 18. Pérez Álvarez M. Esquizofrenia y cultura moderna: razones humanismo, posthumanismo y debate en torno al parque de la locura. Psicothema. 2012;24:1-9. humano. Eikasia.2009;26:1-22. 19. Dussel E. Algunas re¨ exiones sobre la “falacia naturalista” 41. Lenca M, Andorno R. Towards new human rights in the (¿Pueden tener contenidos normativos implícitos cierto age of neuroscience and neurotechnology. Life Sciences, tipo de juicios empíricos?). Diánoia. 2016;46:65-80. Society and Policy. 2017;13:5. 20. Muguerza J. La razón sin esperanza (siete trabajos y un 42. Honderich T. Enciclopedia Oxford de  losofía. Madrid: problema de ética). Madrid: CSIC; 2009. Editorial Tecnos; 2008.

45 M. L. Vargas

43. Gardner H. La nueva ciencia de la mente: historia de la 65. Fuster JM. e cognit: a network model of cortical revolución cognitiva. Barcelona: Ediciones Paidós; 1987. representation. Int J Psychophysiol. 2006;60:125-32. 44. Blanco Pérez CA. Historia de la neurociencia: el 66. San Martín J. La fenomenología de Husserl como utopía de conocimiento del cerebro y la mente desde una perspectiva la razón. Barcelona: Anthropos Editorial; 1987. interdisciplinar. Madrid: Biblioteca Nueva; 2014. 67. San Martín J. Para una superación del relativismo cultural: 45. Fuster JM. Cortex and mind: unifying cognition. Oxford: antropología cultural y antropología  losó ca. Madrid: Oxford University Press; 2003. Editorial Tecnos; 2009. 46. Goñi-Sáez F, Tirapu-Ustárroz J. El problema mente-cerebro 68. Vesper C, Abramova E, Bütepage J, Ciardo F, Crossey B, (I): fundamentos ontoepistemológicos. Rev Neurol. E¬ enberg A, et al. Joint Action: Mental Representations, 2016;63:130-9. Shared Information and General Mechanisms for 47. Tirapu-Ustárroz J, Goñi-Sáez F. El problema cerebro-mente Coordinating with Others. Front Psychol. 2017; doi: (II): sobre la conciencia. Rev Neurol. 2016;63:176-85. 48. Gallagher S, Zahavi D. La mente fenomenológica. Madrid: 10.3389/fpsyg.2016.02039 . Alianza Editorial; 2013. 69. Kircher T, David A. e self in neuroscience and psychiatry. 49. Damasio AR. El error de descartes: la emoción, la razón y el Cambridge (UK): Cambridge University Press; 2003. cerebro humano. 1st ed. Barcelona: Crítica; 1996. 70. Scheler M. Amor y conocimiento y otros escritos. Madrid: 50. Damasio A. En busca de Spinoza: neurobiología de la Ediciones Palabra; 2010. emoción y los sentimientos. Barcelona: Ediciones Destino; 71. McFadden J. Conscious electromagnetic  eld theory. 2011. NeuroQuantology. 2007;5:262-70. 51. Varela FJ, ompson E, Rosch E. e embodied mind: 72. Hebb DO. e organization of behavior. New York: Wiley; cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge 1949. (MA): MIT Press; 1991. 73. Bindra D. A theory of intelligent behavior. New York: John 52. Varela F. Neurophenomenology: a methodological remedy Wiley & Sons; 1976. for the hard problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies. 74. Luria AR. and psychological processes. New 1996;3:330-49. York: Harper & Row; 1966. 53. Varela FJ, Shear J. e view from within:  rst-person 75. Rudrauf D, Lutz A, Cosmelli D, Lachaux JP, Le Van Quyen approaches to the study of consciousness. orverton: M. From to neurophenomenology: Francisco Imprint Academic; 1999. Varela’s exploration of the biophysics of being. Biol Res. 54. ompson E, Varela FJ. Radical embodiment: neural 2003;36:27-65. dynamics and consciousness. Trends Cogn Sci. 2001;5:418- 25. 76. Van der Helm PA. Cognitive architecture of perceptual 55. Varela F, Lachaux JP, Rodriguez E, Martinerie J. e organization: from neurons to gnosons. Cogn Process. brainweb: phase synchronization and large-scale 2012;13:13-40. integration. Nat Rev Neurosci. 2001;2:229-39. 77. Bressler SL, Menon V. Large-scale brain networks in 56. Yoshimi J. Phenomenology and connectionism. Front cognition: emerging methods and principles. Trends Cogn Psychol. 2011;2:288. Sci. 2010;14:277-90. 57. eise ND, Kafatos MC. Fundamental awareness: a 78. Meehan TP, Bressler SL. Neurocognitive networks:  ndings, framework for integrating science, philosophy and models, and theory. Neurosci Biobehav Rev. 2012;36:2232- . Commun Integr Biol. 2016;9:e1155010. 47. 58. Chalmers DJ. e conscious mind: in search of a 79. Vargas Aragón ML. Ni neurología desalmada, ni psiquiatría fundamental theory. New York: Oxford University Press; descerebrada: neurociencia clínica. Kranion. 2012;9:11-5. 1996. 80. DörrZegers O. Esquizofrenia, lenguaje y evolución (o las 59. Velmans M. Understanding consciousness. London: esquizofrenias como logopatías). Actas Esp Psiquiatr. Routledge; 2000. 2010;38:1-7. 60. Bunge M. Materia y mente. Una investigación  losó ca. 81. Huber G. [ e concept of substrate-close basic symptoms Pamplona: Laetoli; 2015. and its signi cance for the theory and therapy of 61. Bunge M. El problema mente-cerebro: un enfoque schizophrenic diseases]. Nervenarzt. 1983;54:23-32. psicobiológico. 3rd ed. Madrid: Editorial Tecnos; 2011. 82. Schmitt A, Hasan A, Gruber O, Falkai P. Schizophrenia 62. Bunge M. Emergencia y convergencia: novedad cualitativa y unidad del conocimiento. Barcelona: Gedisa; 2004. as a disorder of disconnectivity. Eur Arch Psychiatry Clin [Emergence and convergence. Qualitative novelty and the Neurosci. 2011;261:S150-4. unity of knowledge. Toronto: Toronto University Press, 83. Klein C. Consciousness, intention, and command-following 2003.] in the vegetative state. Brit J Phil Sci. 2017;68:27-54. 63. Eccles JC. How the self controls its brain. Berlín: Springer- 84. Castilla del Pino C. El sujeto como sistema: el sujeto Verlag; 1994. hermeneuta. Anuario de Psicología. 1993;59:5-18. 64. Blanco Pérez CA. Sir Charles Sherrington y la naturaleza de 85. San Martín J. Antropología  losó ca II. Vida humana, lo mental. Contrastes. 2014;19:207-27. persona y cultura. Madrid: UNED; 2015.

46