Barnes, Bryant, Ma August 2019

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Barnes, Bryant, Ma August 2019 BARNES, BRYANT, M.A. AUGUST 2019 PHILOSOPHY PROPERTY INDIVIDUATION (66 pp.) Thesis Advisor: Deborah C. Smith This thesis will address the question of what individuates a property. In the current literature, the question is predominately answered in three ways. Quidditism takes properties to be categorical and individuated by their quiddities, that is, by the intrinsic nature of the property. Structuralism takes properties to be individuated by the structural roles (e.g., causal or nomological) that they play. Causal structuralism, for example, maintains that a property is individuated by the causal relationships it enters. I will survey the strengths and weaknesses of these positions and conclude by arguing for John Heil’s mixed view, which takes properties to be both dispositional and categorical. However, because Heil’s mixed view is about the nature of properties and not individuation, I will have to construct individuation conditions appropriate for his theory regarding the nature of properties. My concluding chapter will consist of articulating and defending my individuation conditions for Heil’s mixed view. PROPERTY INDIVIDUATION A thesis submitted To Kent State University in partial Fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts by Bryant Barnes August 2019 © Copyright All rights reserved Except for previously published materials Thesis written by Bryant Barnes B.A., King University, 2016 M.A. Kent State University, 2019 Approved by _______________________________, Advisor Deborah C. Smith _______________________________, Chair, Department of Philosophy Michael Byron _______________________________, Dean, College of Arts and Sciences James L. Blank TABLE OF CONTENTS………………………………………………………………………...iv ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS……………………………………………………………………..vi INTRODUCTION………………………………………………………………………………...1 CHAPTERS 1. Introduction...……………………………...………………………………………………………………………..…..……1 1.1 The Scope of the Thesis and Terminology………………………………………………………….………1 1.2 A Brief Look at Quidditism………………………………………………………………………………….……..3 1.3 A Brief Look at Structuralism………………………………………………………………………………….….4 1.4 A Foray into the Nature of Properties………………………………………………………………….…….5 1.5 A Happy Middle…………………………………………………………………………………………….…………..6 2.Quidditism………………………………………………………………………………………………...……………..........8 2.1 Structuralism and Quidditism……………………………………………………………………………..……..8 2.2 Why be a Quidditist?………………………………………………………………………………………….……10 2.3 What is a Quiddity?…………………………………………………………………………………………….……11 2.4 The Argument from Parsimony and Austere Quidditism…………………………………….……14 2.5 Extremely and Moderately Austere Quidditism……………………………………………………….16 2.6 Non-recombinatorial Quidditism……………………………………………………………………….…….17 2.7 Epistemological Arguments Against Quidditism…………………………………………….………...19 2.8 Non-recombinatorial Quidditism and Skepticism……………………………………………………..22 3. Role-Based Theories………………………………………………………………....................................……24 3.1 Structuralism…………………………………………………………………………………………………………...24 3.2 Ramsification and the Clarification of Roles………………………………………………………….….26 3.3 Nomological and Causal Structuralism………………………………………………………………….….28 3.4 Minimal and Relational Structuralism……………………………………………………………….……..30 3.5 The Symmetry Problem………………………………………………………………………………….………..35 4. Mixed Views……………………………………………………………………………………………………………….….42 4.1 Martin’s Dual Aspect Interpretation of Powerful Qualities……………………………………...42 4.2 Heil’s Identity Theory…………………………………………………………………………………………..…..45 iv 4.3 Identity Theory or DAI?................................................................................................47 5. Conclusion……………………………………………………………………………….........................................53 5.1 An Initial Articulation of the Individuation Conditions………………………………………….….53 5.2 A Problem with the Directionality of Dispositional Natures……………………………………..54 5.3 The Identity of Natures…………………………………………………………………………………………...58 5.4 A Kind of Quidditism……………………………………………………………………………………….……….60 REFERENCES………………………………………………………………………………………………………………………….…64 v ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS When I think back on writing this thesis, the words “That’s good for your project but not for your thesis” immediately come to mind. Of course, this came from my thesis advisor and mentor, Dr. Deborah C. Smith, who always kept me on track when I could not reign in all the tangents that would have otherwise been clumsily thrown into this thesis. I cannot thank her enough for keeping me on track throughout this process, providing immensely helpful comments on my initial chapter drafts (comments which, if combined, would probably exceed the length of this thesis), and always being available to bounce ideas off of. I would also like to thank my readers, Dr. David Pereplyotchik, Dr. Frank Ryan, and Dr. Donald White, who have been patiently waiting for this thesis to (finally) be completed. I value their time and greatly appreciate them devoting some of it to reading this thesis. I would also like to thank those professors whose classes I have spent the most time in and impacted my growth as a student. Dr. Pereplyotchik whose Socratic style of questioning and energy in and out of the classroom is something that I try to emulate. Dr. Aldea, with whom I read roughly 10,000 pages of Husserl, ramping up my reading comprehension. Dr. Byron, whose careful attention to precision while answering questions in class has benefited me immensely as I have gone on to write and speak in philosophical settings. I must also thank William Fenton, Cara Griffiths, and all my fellow graduate students for making my years at Kent State a wonderful experience and listening to me occasionally rant about the problems I ran into while writing this. vi Lastly, I would like to thank Dr. Craig Streetman from King University, who initially sparked my interest in philosophy and always indulged my various project ideas as an undergraduate. vii Chapter 1: Introduction 1.1 The Scope of the Thesis and Terminology Arguably, the world is made up of objects and properties. Such objects include hearts, lungs, and individuals with both hearts and lungs. Properties include tallness, redness, negative charge, being happy to have one’s thesis finished, etc. A lot has been said about what individuates objects, especially individuals. There is a large literature on the putative haecceities (or individual essences) of particular objects, but the question of what individuates properties is relatively new on the scene. It is this latter question that will be the focus of my thesis. I will call it the individuation question: Individuation Question: What individuates a property across possible worlds, that is, what are the cross-world identity conditions for a property. As Dustin Locke has articulated, the debate over what individuates a property is a “domestic dispute among property realists” (Locke 2012, 347). I take the existence of properties as an assumption that all those who discuss individuation share. So, I will not be engaging those who do not believe that properties exist. Furthermore, like most philosophers who engage the individuation question, I will assume that properties are universals rather than collections of tropes.1 However, it is beyond the scope of this thesis to defend this assumption. 1 A universal is a property that can be instantiated in different objects at the same time. If the property of redness were a universal, then everything that instantiates redness would be instantiating the same property. On the other hand, trope theory maintains that everything is particular. Every instance of redness would be unique. When a group of tropes are sufficiently similar, the trope theorist groups them under one concept (e.g., the concept of redness). 1 A closely related question to property individuation regards the nature of laws (e.g., Coulombs’ laws or Newton’s laws of motion). How one answers the question of property individuation will entail answers for questions such as ‘what is a law of nature’ or ‘are the laws of nature necessary or contingent’. It is beyond the scope of this thesis to directly address these questions, but I will make it explicit when a theory of property individuation entails a particular answer to whether laws are necessary or contingent.2 Before I continue, I should get clear on the range of properties that I am considering here. I am not talking about all properties. Rather, I am writing about a specific class of properties: fundamental physical properties. Physical properties should be distinguished from abstract properties, such as the property of being a prime number. The former kind of property is instantiated in concrete physical objects, whereas the latter is not. Fundamental properties can be explained in different ways. Following David Lewis, we can say that fundamental properties are those that act as a supervenience base for all other properties, they are intrinsic to objects, and they can “completely and without redundancy” characterize objects (1986, 60). Additionally, they “are not at all disjunctive, or determinable, or negative” (Lewis 2009, 204). Another explanation is that fundamental properties are those that would be featured in a completed science that describes the world at the most basic level (Schaffer 2004; Bird 2009).3 So, properties such as spin, force, and charge are plausible candidates for fundamental properties. In the rest of this thesis, unless otherwise specified, I will use ‘properties’ and ‘property’ to talk about these fundamental properties. 2 Throughout
Recommended publications
  • Medieval Western Philosophy: the European Emergence
    Cultural Heritage and Contemporary Change Series I, Culture and Values, Volume 9 History of Western Philosophy by George F. McLean and Patrick J. Aspell Medieval Western Philosophy: The European Emergence By Patrick J. Aspell The Council for Research in Values and Philosophy 1 Copyright © 1999 by The Council for Research in Values and Philosophy Gibbons Hall B-20 620 Michigan Avenue, NE Washington, D.C. 20064 All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Aspell, Patrick, J. Medieval western philosophy: the European emergence / Patrick J. Aspell. p.cm. — (Cultural heritage and contemporary change. Series I. Culture and values ; vol. 9) Includes bibliographical references and index. 1. Philosophy, Medieval. I. Title. III. Series. B721.A87 1997 97-20069 320.9171’7’090495—dc21 CIP ISBN 1-56518-094-1 (pbk.) 2 Table of Contents Chronology of Events and Persons Significant in and beyond the History of Medieval Europe Preface xiii Part One: The Origins of Medieval Philosophy 1 Chapter I. Augustine: The Lover of Truth 5 Chapter II. Universals According to Boethius, Peter Abelard, and Other Dialecticians 57 Chapter III. Christian Neoplatoists: John Scotus Erigena and Anselm of Canterbury 73 Part Two: The Maturity of Medieval Philosophy Chronology 97 Chapter IV. Bonaventure: Philosopher of the Exemplar 101 Chapter V. Thomas Aquinas: Philosopher of the Existential Act 155 Part Three: Critical Reflection And Reconstruction 237 Chapter VI. John Duns Scotus: Metaphysician of Essence 243 Chapter
    [Show full text]
  • Thomas Aquinas: Soul-Body Connection and the Afterlife Hyde Dawn Krista University of Missouri-St
    University of Missouri, St. Louis IRL @ UMSL Theses Graduate Works 4-16-2012 Thomas Aquinas: Soul-Body Connection and the Afterlife Hyde Dawn Krista University of Missouri-St. Louis, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://irl.umsl.edu/thesis Recommended Citation Krista, Hyde Dawn, "Thomas Aquinas: Soul-Body Connection and the Afterlife" (2012). Theses. 261. http://irl.umsl.edu/thesis/261 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate Works at IRL @ UMSL. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses by an authorized administrator of IRL @ UMSL. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Thomas Aquinas: Soul-Body Connection and the Afterlife Krista Hyde M.L.A., Washington University in St. Louis, 2010 B.A., Philosophy, Southeast Missouri State University – Cape Girardeau, 2003 A Thesis Submitted to The Graduate School at the University of Missouri – St. Louis in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Master of Arts in Philosophy April 2012 Advisory Committee Gualtiero Piccinini, Ph.D. Chair Jon McGinnis, Ph.D. John Brunero, Ph.D. Copyright, Krista Hyde, 2012 Abstract Thomas Aquinas nearly succeeds in addressing the persistent problem of the mind-body relationship by redefining the human being as a body-soul (matter-form) composite. This redefinition makes the interaction problem of substance dualism inapplicable, because there is no soul “in” a body. However, he works around the mind- body problem only by sacrificing an immaterial afterlife, as well as the identity and separability of the soul after death. Additionally, Thomistic psychology has difficulty accounting for the transmission of universals, nor does it seem able to overcome the arguments for causal closure.
    [Show full text]
  • Haecceities, Quiddities, and Structure∗
    compiled on 18 December 2015 at 14:00 Haecceities, quiddities, and structure∗ Wolfgang Schwarz Draft, 18 December 2015 Abstract. Suppose all truths are made true by the distribution of funda- mental properties and relations over fundamental particulars. The world is then completely characterized by stating which fundamental properties and relations are instantiated by which fundamental particulars. But do we have to mention the fundamental particulars by name? Arguably not. Arguably, all truths – or at least all truths we can ever know – are made true by the pattern in which fundamental properties and relations are instantiated by fundamental particulars, irrespective of the identity (“haecceity”) of those particulars. Parallel arguments suggest that the identity (“quiddity”) of fundamental properties and relations can be omitted. It would follow that all truths (or all knowable truths) are made true by the abstract structure of the world, the pattern in which fundamental properties and relations are instantiated by fundamental particulars, irrespective of the identity of the properties, relations, and particulars. I argue that this is almost correct: while not all truths are made true by the abstract structure of the world, the remaining truths are (in a certain sense) not made true by the world at all. 1 Introduction Most truths can be explained by other, more fundamental truths. That salt dissolves in water, for example, can be explained by the chemical composition of salt and water together with the general laws of physics. Explanations of this kind plausibly come to an end. At some point we reach a bottom level of fundamental facts that are not explainable in terms of anything more basic.
    [Show full text]
  • The Univocity of Substance and the Formal Distinction of Attributes: the Role of Duns Scotus in Deleuze's Reading of Spinoza Nathan Widder
    parrhesia 33 · 2020 · 150-176 the univocity of substance and the formal distinction of attributes: the role of duns scotus in deleuze's reading of spinoza nathan widder This paper examines the role played by medieval theologian John Duns Scotus in Gilles Deleuze’s reading of Spinoza’s philosophy of expressive substance; more generally, it elaborates a crucial moment in the development of Deleuze’s philosophy of sense and difference. Deleuze contends that Spinoza adapts and extends Duns Scotus’s two most influential theses, the univocity of being and formal distinction, despite neither appearing explicitly in Spinoza’s writings. “It takes nothing away from Spinoza’s originality,” Deleuze declares, “to place him in a perspective that may already be found in Duns Scotus” (Deleuze, 1992, 49).1 Nevertheless, the historiographic evidence is clearly lacking, leaving Deleuze to admit that “it is hardly likely that” Spinoza had even read Duns Scotus (359n28). Indeed, the only support he musters for his speculation is Spinoza’s obvious in- terests in scholastic metaphysical and logical treatises, the “probable influence” of the Scotist-informed Franciscan priest Juan de Prado on his thought, and the fact that the problems Duns Scotus addresses need not be confined to Christian thought (359–360n28). The paucity of evidence supporting this “use and abuse” of history, however, does not necessarily defeat the thesis. Like other lineages Deleuze proposes, the one he traces from Duns Scotus to Spinoza, and subsequently to Nietzsche, turns not on establishing intentional references by one thinker to his predecessor, but instead on showing how the borrowings and adaptations asserted to create the connec- tion make sense of the way the second philosopher surmounts blockages he faces while responding to issues left unaddressed by the first.
    [Show full text]
  • Aquinas' Principle of Individuation
    Aquinas' Principle of Individuation Patrick W. Hughes Denison University Saint Thomas Aquinas, the Thirteenth Century Catholic theologian and philosopher was one of the first Medieval philosophers to attempt to reconcile the newly re-introduced Aristotelian system with the Catholic religious thought ofthe day. Aquinas' numerous commentaries on Aristotle and his adoption of the Aristotelian thought form the basis for the whole of Aquinian metaphysics (as well as the basic Aristotileanism which pervades Aquinas' whole systematic philosophy), In this paper I will deal with a specific yet fundamental principle ofAquinianmetaphysics-the principle of individuation. On first reading of the Aquinian texts, the principle of individuation appears to be stated succinctly, yet further investigation into the concept of individuation reveals problems and ambiguities. As it is necessary for an understanding of the problem of individuation in the Aquinian system, I will start off with the basic ontology ofAquinas and then will proceed with one interpretation of the ambiguities which exist in the texts regarding the principle of individuation. I will then give a counter interpretation that Aquinas might level against my interpretation and the problems ofmy interpretation; finally, I will analyze any problems that arise from the Aquinian response. 1. Primary Substance in Aristotle and Aquinas The difficulty in dealing with systematic philosophy is that it is difficult to know where to begin, since each concept is built upon previous concepts and all of the concepts are fundamentally interrelated. Neverthe­ less, I shall start by explicating Aquinas' fundamental ontology. Aquinas, following Aristotle, points out that the world is made up of individual things-or what Aquinas calls "primary substances", Socrates, Rover, and the pine tree in my yard are all existing individual primary substances in the world.
    [Show full text]
  • Christology and the 'Scotist Rupture'
    Theological Research ■ volume 1 (2013) ■ p. 31–63 Aaron Riches Instituto de Filosofía Edith Stein Instituto de Teología Lumen Gentium, Granada, Spain Christology and the ‘Scotist Rupture’ Abstract This essay engages the debate concerning the so-called ‘Scotist rupture’ from the point of view of Christology. The essay investigates John Duns Scotus’s de- velopment of Christological doctrine against the strong Cyrilline tendencies of Thomas Aquinas. In particular the essay explores how Scotus’s innovative doctrine of the ‘haecceity’ of Christ’s human nature entailed a self-sufficing conception of the ‘person’, having to do less with the mystery of rationality and ‘communion’, and more to do with a quasi-voluntaristic ‘power’ over oneself. In this light, Scotus’s Christological development is read as suggestively con- tributing to make possible a proto-liberal condition in which ‘agency’ (agere) and ‘right’ (ius) are construed as determinative of what it means to be and act as a person. Keywords John Duns Scotus, ‘Scotist rupture’, Thomas Aquinas, homo assumptus Christology 32 Aaron Riches Introduction In A Secular Age, Charles Taylor links the movement towards the self- sufficing ‘exclusive humanism’ characteristic of modern secularism with a reallocation of popular piety in the thirteenth century.1 Dur- ing that period a shift occurred in which devotional practices became less focused on the cosmological glory of Christ Pantocrator and more focused on the particular humanity of the lowly Jesus. Taylor suggests that this new devotional attention to the particular human Christ was facilitated by the recently founded mendicant orders, especially the Franciscans and Dominicans, both of whom saw the meekness of God Incarnate reflected in the individual poor among whom the friars lived and ministered.
    [Show full text]
  • Peirce on the Medievals: Realism, Power and Form Peirce Acerca Dos Medievais: Realismo, Poder E Forma
    Peirce on the Medievals: Realism, Power and Form Peirce acerca dos Medievais: Realismo, Poder e Forma John Boler University of Washington [email protected] Abstract: In the first section, I discuss Peirce’s ambivalence attitude towards medieval thinkers – some high praise, some harsh criticism. In the second, I consider three criticisms Max Fisch mde of my book Charles Peirce and Scholastic Realism. My book had presented Peirce’s realism as if it were a single position from first to last. And I want to adjust that in the light of Fisch’s points. I now want to distinguish his scholastic realism from his on- going development of realism. To this end, I offer a more restricted and precise meaning to “scholastic realism” – roughly an anti-platonism in which the common nature is found as an element in things. That meaning does, I think, remain constant for Peirce; though I agree with Fisch that this is only a part of his developing realism. In the third section, I bring out the connection between the scholastic notion of potentiality and Peirce’s “would- be’s.” Interestingly enough (to me), this is not an influence that Peirce himself acknowledges. I also point out there that Peirce is rather dismissive of the scholastic notion of form, which he thinks is a perversion of Aristotle’s more useful (if vague) position. Keywords: Realism. Potentiality. Form. Matter. Resumo: Na primeira seção, discuto a atitude ambivalente de Peirce para com os pensadores medievais – algumas avaliações elogiosas, algumas críticas duras. Na segunda parte, considero três críticas feitas por Max Fisch ao meu livro Charles Peirce and Scholastic Realism.
    [Show full text]
  • “But What, Then, Am I
    --Religious Studies 43/3 (2007): 333-348. Published by Cambridge University Press Persons and the metaphysics of resurrection Lynne Rudder Baker Department of Philosophy Bartlett Hall 352 University of Massachusetts Amherst Amherst, MA 01003 USA Theories of the human person differ greatly in their ability to underwrite a metaphysics of resurrection. This paper compares and contrasts a number of such views in light of the Christian doctrine of resurrection. In a Christian framework, resurrection requires that the same person who exists on earth also exists in an afterlife, that a postmortem person be embodied, and that the existence of a postmortem person is brought about by a miracle. According to my view of persons (the Constitution View), a human person is constituted by—but not identical to—a human organism. A person has a first-person perspective essentially, and an organism has interrelated biological functions essentially. I shall argue for the superiority the Constitution View as a metaphysical basis for resurrection. ‘But what, then, am I?’ Descartes famously asked. Although many of us today reject Descartes’s equally famous answer--I am an immaterial mind--Descartes was right, I believe, to identify himself with a thinking thing, a thing who ‘doubts, understands, affirms, 2 denies, wills, refuses, and which also imagines and senses’.1 But neither an immaterial mind nor a material brain is the thing that thinks. The thing that thinks is the person. Just as your legs and feet are the limbs by means of which you walk, you the person—not your legs and feet—are the walker; so too the brain is the organ by means of which you think, but you the person—not your brain—are the thinker.
    [Show full text]
  • American Catholic Philosophical Association
    American Catholic Philosophical Association Executive Council Eighty-Third Annual Meeting Mary Beth Ingham Therese-Anne Druart Edward Houser Steven Jensen Reason in Context Patrick Brennan Mark Gossiaux Judith Green Patrick Murray Loyola University of New Orleans Brian Treanor Catherine A.J. Deavel Hotel Monteleone Colleen McCluskey New Orleans, LA Douglas B. Rasmussen James B. South November 13 - November 15, 2009 Richard C. Taylor Sarah Byers Matthew Cuddeback Christopher Cullen Tobias Hoffmann Michael Tkacz William Desmond Officers of the Association President……..………Mary Beth Ingham Vice-President……Therese-Anne Druart Secretary……….….…….Edward Houser Program Committee Treasurer………...………….Steve Jensen Bonnie Kent Christopher Kaczor John Hittinger ST. AUGUSTINE’S PRESS 25% discount on all our titles Dear Friends: I must miss this year’s ACPA for family reasons, but though I’ll be gone, I don’t like the idea of being forgot- ten. So whatever good I could have done being at the meeting I’ll do being absent by offering all ACPA mem- bers a 25% discount on everything St. Augustine’s has pub- lished or is in the process of publishing (I suppose this means that though I’ll be gone, I won’t be missed). Simply go to our website, www.staugustine.net, and purchase anything you’d like, including forthcoming titles. At checkout be sure to put in “ACPA” (without the quote marks) in the promo code box. Then you will automatical- ly receive a 25% discount. This offer is good from November 12, 2009, through December 15, 2009, only. Best regards, Bruce Fingerhut Some New & Forthcoming Titles from St.
    [Show full text]
  • From Primitive Mentality to Haecceity: the Unique Case in Astrology and Divination
    From Primitive Mentality to haecceity: the Unique Case in astrology and divination Geoffrey Cornelius Part I The question before us is the nature of divinatory intelligence,1 which is the mode of thought whereby meaningful interpretations are sustained in divination. This paper supports the view of some anthropologists that divination involves a distinctive mode of consciousness, mental pattern or cognitive faculty. To this end, I bring forward what may seem at first to be an unlikely combination of descriptions from anthropology and scholastic philosophy. Part I reviews Lucien Lévy-Bruhl's description of 'primitive mentality', in order to establish a characteristic of divinatory interpretation that I have termed the unique case. In Part II I suggest that the unique case parallels the concept of haecceitas (anglicised as haecceity or 'this-ness') posited by the medieval theologian John Duns Scotus. This concept is dependent on his distinction between intuitive and abstractive cognition; this pairing indicates a foundational analysis that may be fruitfully applied beyond its original context to the question of omens, astrology and divination. At the same time, this approach complements the anthropological perspective by suggesting a loftier intellectual register for divination than is usually granted to it by contemporary scholarship. Astrology is considered here in the practical and applied form in which it is most commonly encountered, which is as a method of judgment and interpretation, and this is treated as a practice of divination. Beyond its explicitly divinatory manifestation astrology raises complex questions in that it has from its origins encompassed cosmology, sacred science and pre-modern psychology.
    [Show full text]
  • Antonius Andreae Scotism's Best Supporting Auctor
    ANTONIUS ANDREAL SCOTISM'S BEST SUPPORTING AUCTOR Marek GF.NSLLR I. THE MAKING OF A DOCTOR DULCIFLUUS ANTONIUS ANDREAE AND HIS POSITION IN FORMATION OF SCOTISM The turning of the 13th and 14th century saw the emergence of a bright new star on the firmament of philosophy - the man who reinvented scho- lasticism after the Condemnation of 1277: John Duns Scotus. The light of his thought soon lit up inspiration in many adepts of the Liberal Arts and the gravity of his doctrine had caught, for some time at least, a number of young thinkers, who later became most influential philosophers of 14th century, like Francis de Mayronis, William of Ockham and Peter Auriol, to name a few. For most of them, however, the contact with the doctrine of the Subtle Doctor was only an inspiring episode early in their careers and it would be difficult to call them advocates of scotism, much less ,,true,, scotists. And still, despite the fact that so many of Scotus' best pu- pils later turned their backs on his teaching, despite Scotus' early death that had left his work unfinished, the doctrine of John Duns not only sur- vived but started flourishing and gradually became one of the most vital and powerful philosophical schools of later middle ages, whose influence was still felt at the universities even in the 18th century. How was it possi- ble that the ideas so subtle and so sketchy won minds and hearts of so many lovers of wisdom? Propagation of Scotus' views required devout followers, skilful inter- preters and commentators and, last but not least, good thinkers who, ac- cepting the opinions of John Duns for their own, would develop them in- to a comprehensive doctrine covering the whole spectrum of philosophical inquiry of the time, in a word: transform them into scotism.
    [Show full text]
  • Relativity of Explicit Conceptual Models
    NISTIR 7148 Relativity of explicit conceptual models David Flater NISTIR 7148 Relativity of explicit conceptual models David Flater Manufacturing Systems Integration Division Manufacturing Engineering Laboratory July 2004 U.S. DEPARTMENT OF COMMERCE Donald L. Evans, Secretary TECHNOLOGY ADMINISTRATION Phillip J. Bond, Under Secretary of Commerce for Technology NATIONAL INSTITUTE OF STANDARDS AND TECHNOLOGY Arden L. Bement, Jr., Director Relativity of explicit conceptual models David Flater NISTIR 7148 2004-07-29 Abstract Explicit conceptual models are supposed to capture knowledge of lasting value in a reusable form. Reuse of explicit conceptual models is hampered by arbitrary and application-specific constraints; any constraints that conflict with a new application must be altered or removed before the models can be reused. This paper explores seven facets of relativity in explicit conceptual models using Formal Concept Analysis, demonstrating first that the capture of application-specific constraints is inextricable from the modelling process, and second that the semantic differences between models built for different applications can themselves be modelled formally in most cases. By analyzing those differences, one can determine whether the applications themselves are sufficiently compatible at the conceptual level to enable integration. Keywords: concept, integration, modelling, ontology, reuse, semantics 1 Introduction An explicit conceptual model is a conceptual model that has a persistent representation and is intended to capture knowledge of lasting value in a reusable form. Explicit conceptual models are knowledge representations in the broadest sense; they could model the concepts relevant to a software project, a domain of discourse, or any world view of whatever scope. Explicit conceptual models are sometimes distinguished from implicit conceptual models, which are mental models or intangible models that are implied by the design of an artifact.
    [Show full text]