On Humanity in Transition: The Past, Present, and Future For Petee in Memorium

Hwayol Jung Professor, Moravian College

Where there is no vision, the people perish. The scholars are the priests of that thought which establishes the foundation of the earth. —Ralph Waldo Emerson

If we keep on speaking the same language together, we’re going to reproduce the same history. —Luce Irigaray

What is your aim in philosophy? —To shew the fly the way out of the fly-bottle. —Ludwig Wittgenstein

Just as there is sleepwalking, there is also sleepthinking. —José Ortega y Gasset

I am truly delighted and deeply honored to have been invited to speak on the weighty subject of “On Humanity in Transition: The Past, Present, and Future” before this distinguished audience. I am doubly delighted because this is also a homecoming for me. I was born in Korea and now a hyphenated or hybrid citizen of the United States. My sincere gratitude goes to the organizers of this conference, particularly Dr. Inwon Choue, who is Rector of Kyung Hee University’s Global Academy for Neo-Renaissance and Professor Dongsoo Lee who initially contacted me and whom I have had the fortune of knowing since his graduate-student days at Seoul National University in the late 1980s—the era of a new political transformation or the birth of a new political consciousness in Korea.

I. PROLOGUE

We are living in interesting times because we are challenged today by multiculturalism and globalization where and when the exchange (ex-change) and interchange (inter-change) of diverse cultural ideas and values take place. The general theme of this conference is “After Ideology: The 21st-Century Talks” which intends to advance the lofty and hopeful ideal of “world peace and human prosperity.” I was specifically asked to speak on the subject of “On Humanity in Transition: The Past, Present, and Future.” It is indeed an exhaustive and demanding subject. The nature of the subject on hand requires me to speak in generalities. At the same time, however, it asks for “a fitting response” to facilitate communication and the Arendtian notion of “judgment,” that is to say, a concrete response to a concrete question and a critical assessment of a specific issue in its specificity. In other words, generalities without specifics are empty, while specifics without generalities are blind. There are two keywords in the suggested subject of my talk: (1) humanity and (2) metamorphosis. The purpose of this conference, as I understand it, is to envision or forge a new humanism after the fashion of the Renaissance which is the epoch sandwiched between the Middle Ages and modernity in the periodization of European history. It is distinguished by its attempt to bring back to Europe the cultural norms and values of ancient Greek civilization. In this sense, the term “neo-Renaissance” as an analytical concept or without reference to the historical context of Europe would be redundant. Be that as it may, Emerson’s and Irigaray’s epigraphs I quoted in the beginning of this essay, which go hand in hand, are a perfect fir for my talk in this plenary session. Emerson is regarded as the first American “public intellectual.” He is an unrivaled essayist whose pithy words and passages are often quoted and misquoted in the American intellectual circle. For that matter, this conference shares the kindred spirit of Emerson in envisioning the revival of Renaissance humanism. I do have, however, one serious reservation concerning Emerson’s epigraph. It is the designation of “scholars” as “priests.” I take a cue from Leszek Kolakowski’s (1968: 9-37) contention that throughout ages there is an incurable antagonism between “a philosophy that perpetuates the absolute” and “a philosophy that questions accepted absolutes.” There is, in other words, the antagonism between the “priestly” and the “jesterly” which are the two most general forms of intellectual disposition at any given period of time and in history. The “priestly” attempts to preserve the absolute and established ideas, while the “jesterly” distrusts the absolute and a stabilized system and intends to deconstruct it.1 There is a strong undercurrent of the “jesterly” in the humanism of the Renaissance, which may be called carnivalesque culture. In this context, it is worth quoting in full a passage from Harvey Cox’s (1969: 82) work The Feast of Fools that describes the anti-ideological “political vision” of carnivalesque culture as follows: The rebirth of fantasy as well as of festivity is essential to the survival of our civilization, including its political institutions. But fantasy can never be fully yoked to a particular political program. To subject the creative spirit to the fetters of ideology kills it. When art, religion, and imagination become ideological tools they shrivel into caged birds and toothless tigers. However, this does not mean that fantasy has no political significance. Its significance is enormous. This is just why ideologues always try to keep it in harness. When fantasy is neither tamed by ideological leashes nor rendered irrelevant by idiosyncrasy, it can inspire new civilizations and bring empires to their knees.2 By making the existing world upside down and inside out, the aim of the carnivalesque dispositif is to bring about a “reversible world.” It symbolizes a culture of dissensus (dis-sensus). The spirit of carnivalesque culture in the Renaissance is embodied in Rabelais, Erasmus, and Bruegel. The carnivalesque is the “jesterly” play of difference that aims at the creation of an alternative or “reversible world” order. As a ludic form of transgression and subversion, it intends to transform playfully a “real” world into a “possible” world: in short, it nonviolently deconstructs the world. Carnivalesque culture attempts to create a “reversible world” in which the “master” is placed at bottom and the “servant” on top. Humans as players (homo ludens) dethrone the stable and established hierarchy of all kinds. In the Bruegelian and Rabelaisian themes of Mikhail Bakhtin’s dialogical body politics, which is opposed to Enlightenment rationalism and contains a hidden critique of Stalin’s totalitarianism based, rightly or wrongly, on the Hegelian and Marxian dialectic, to carnivalize the world is to dialogize it: in them carnivalization and dialogization go hand in hand. As a protest against the monological “misrule” of (Soviet) officialdom, the carnivalesque model of life transgresses and transforms the canonical order of truth and the official order of reality. As Bakhtin writes forcefully: [It] is past millenia’s way of sensing the world as one great communal performance. This sense of the world, liberating one from fear, bringing one person maximally close to another (everything is drawn into the zone of free familiar contact), with its joy at change and its joyful relativity, is opposed to that one-sided and gloomy official seriousness which is dogmatic and hostile to evolution and change, which seeks to absolutize a given condition of existence or a given social order. From precisely that sort of seriousness did the carnival sense of the world liberate man. But there is not a grain of nihilism in it, nor a grain of empty frivolity or vulgar bohemian individualism.3 As it is exemplary of dissensus, the carnivalesque celebrates dialogue and community; it liberates people and brings them together and invites them to participate in communal living. In this light, the scholar is a (Kolakowski’s) jester and (Camus’s) rebel rather than a (Emerson’s) priest and dialectical revolutionary. He changes the world by first changing the conception of it. Parenthetically, the jesterly culture of the Renaissance deconstructs the priestly interpretation of Greek philosophy. It has nothing to do with the essentialist idea of discovering the truth as ready- made or eternally immutable. The eighteenth-century anti-Cartesian and anti-Enlightenment Neapolitan philosopher Giambattista Vico is forthright in formulating the thesis that we understand history with certainty only because we “make”/“remake” and “unmake” it (i.e., verum ipsum factum). On the other hand, the influential political philosopher Leo Strauss put forth an essentialist rendition of classical political philosophy which is exemplified in the philosophy of Plato and Aristotle in arguing against what he calls “historicism” or “relativism” that calls for the historical transformation of truth and the cultural variations of morals. Strauss left behind him a circle of such notable disciplines as Allan Bloom, Francis Fukuyama, and Paul D. Wolfowitz. Bloom authored the bestseller The Closing of the American Mind (1987) which is anti-Nietzschean, anti-feminist, and anti-multiculturalist for obvious reasons; Fukuyama is the famed author of the “end-of-history” thesis; and Wolfowitz was a brain-trust and strategist of the American war in Iraq, whose ultimate task is to export and propagate “missionary democracy” (Robert W. Merry, 2005: 193) beyond the soil of the United States.4 As her epigraph makes it clear, the paradigmatic French feminist philosopher Irigaray, who calls herself une philosophe, means to reverse the mainstream (i.e., “malestream”) tradition of Western philosophy. She offers a helping hand to a paradigm shift in philosophizing. Notably in the East with which she attempts to familiarize herself, the reputed Chinese Book of Changes (I Ching) is predicated upon the basic thesis that change is the order of things in the cosmos, i.e., everything changes except change itself without a philosophical baggage of linear progress as in Western modernity. Standing by a river, Confucius, too, remarked that everything, like a river, flows ceaselessly, day and night. The esprit de corps of the Renaissance as carnivalesque culture, too, defies for its namesake the linear progression of time and cultural meanings as être de longue durée. For it, change is “cyclical” rather than “linear.” Indeed, it rebirthed the Greek conception of time and history as the “myth of the eternal return” (see Eliade, 1954). Time does not travel in a uni- linear direction. It travels multi-directionally: it travels forward and backward and even multilaterally. In this sense, the past is never prosaic and irrelevant. Even the prodigal son of the past is allowed to come back home again. Here again, the invocation of Bakhtin, who admires the personages of Dostoevsky as well as Rabelais, is helpful. For him, the recycling of past meanings for today and tomorrow is infinite. To use his own expression, it is “unfinalizable.” According to the often-quoted epigram of the American novelist William Faulkner, “The past is never dead, it’s not even past.”5 Meanings in the past can be recouped for the present and can conserve them for the future as is the case with the rebirth of Greek culture in the Renaissance. Bakhtin is immeasurably profound when he (1986: 170) writes: There is neither a first nor a last word and there are no limits to the dialogic context (it extends into the boundless past and the boundless future). Even past meanings, that is, those born in the dialogue of past centuries, can never be stable (finalized, ended once and for all)—they will always change (be renewed) in the process of subsequent, future development of the dialogue. . . . Nothing is absolutely dead: every meaning will have its homecoming festival (italics added). Indeed, Bakhtin’s dialogism, which is totally open-ended, transcends the facile ideological dichotomy between “conservatism” (the preservation of the past tradition at all cost) and “radicalism” (change for the future by abandoning the past altogether) because radical changes can be made by the use of the past or past meanings. As the American philosopher George Santayana puts it wisely, those who forget the past or past mistakes are condemned to repeat them.

II. TRANSVERSALITY AS A NEW WAY OF TRANSFORMING THINKING AND DOING

The purpose of using the neologism transversality6 in the context of this paper is to resolve or, better, dissolve the question of the One and the Many in the pluralistic world of multiculturalism in the postmodern age which is already on its way to globalization.7 Recently I came to the realization that I had been speaking, albeit unself-consciously, the prose of transversality since the beginning of my academic career in writing about comparative philosophy, comparative culture, and cultural hermeneutics. Be that as it may, transversality is a new way of thinking that is suitable for and accommodates the changing reality of today’s world. It means to awaken us from the slumber of antiquated universality which has been a Eurocentric idea because what is particular in the West is universalized or universalizable, whereas what is particular elsewhere remains particularized as “ethnophilosophy.”8 Transversality allows border-crossings of all kinds. It facilitates border- crossings both between academic disciplines and diverse cultures. It means to be thoroughly intertextual—to use the expression au courant of literary and philosophical minds today. Enlightenment is the soul of mainstream Western modernity. Its legacy continues today. Some speak of modernity as an unfinished project, a second modernity, even the modernization of modernity, or the second coming of Enlightenment itself. They have an unswerving faith in it as the absolute “end of history.” Enlightenment’s unbridled optimism is alleged to promote and crown the Promethean progress of humanity based on the cultivation and universalization of pure and applied reason. Kant, who had a dim view of the non-Western world (especially Africa), spelled out the civilizing mission of Enlightenment in the clearest and simplest term: to sanctify the autonomous benefits of reason in rescuing and emancipating humanity—perhaps more accurately European humanity—from the dark grotto or slumber of self-incurred immaturity. In so doing, he institutionalized the major agenda of European modernity whose rationality was never seriously challenged until the auspicious advent of postmodernity in Friedrich Nietzsche, Martin Heidegger, Jean-François Lyotard, Michel Foucault, Gilles Deleuze, Emmanuel Levinas, Jacques Derrida, and others in the twentieth century. While privileging and valorizing the authority of reason for allegedly human progress and emancipation, European modernity unfortunately overlooks, marginalizes, and disempowers the (reason’s) other whether it be (1) the Orient (or so-called non- West), (2) body, (3) woman, or (4) nature at the altar of Enlightenment’s reason (see Jung, 2002a). Orient, body, woman, and nature are not randomly isolated but are four interconnected issues: most interestingly, it is no accident that Orient, body, and nature are invariably genderized as feminine, while their counterparts—mind, culture, and Occident—are masculine or “malestream” categories. The institution of Western thought called Eurocentrism (see Said, 1978 and Hassan and Dadi, 2001) as well as the practice of imperialism is that habitus of mind which privileges Europe or the West as cultural, technological, political, economic, and moral capital of the entire globe. Modernization is nothing but the all-encompassing catchword given to the totalizing and hegemonizing process of this Eurocentric phenomenon. As the astute interpreter and critic of modernity Zygmunt Bauman (1987: 110) relates: From at least the seventeenth century and well into the twentieth, the writing elite of Western Europe and its footholds on other continents considered its own way of life as a radical break in universal history. Virtually unchallenged faith in the superiority of its own mode over all alternative forms of life—contemporaneous or past—allowed it to take itself as the reference point for the interpretation of the telos of history. This was a novelty in the experience of objective time; for most of the history of Christian Europe, time-reckoning was organized around a fixed point in the slowly receding past. Now, . . . Europe set the reference point of objective time in motion, attaching it firmly to its own thrust towards colonizing the future in the same way as it had colonized the surrounding space (italics added). Indeed, this Eurocentric “chronopolitics” of colonizing the future born of “a little promontory in the continent of Asia” (Paul Valéry’s expression) gives a new meaning to the conception of modernity as an unfinished project or the end of history. A few words of caution are in order: understanding the other (the “foreign” other in particular), as anthropology and psychoanalysis have shown, is a difficult and demanding undertaking for no other reason than that the other as a moving target is always other than itself. Indeed, the other is the “black hole” of all understanding, all conceptualization, and all relationships. At a moment of frustration and despair, the existential phenomenologist Jean-Paul Sartre faces a real moment of this black hole: “Hell is other people.” Furthermore, we should be aware of Akira Kurosawa’s Rashomon that presents four equally plausible scenarios of one and the same murder scene. Rashomon is a telltale drama that raises a red flag for intercultural understandings. There is also the intriguing question of John Hu or Hu Ruowang (see Spence, 1988)—the first Chinese in record to travel to the West. He sailed to France from Canton (Guagdon) in 1722. Like the Rashomon tale, the question of Hu has an intriguing plot. Because of his “strange” (foreign) behavior which astonished the Parisians, Hu was finally committed to the famous lunatic asylum of Charenton (Sha-lang-don) in 1723 and remained there until 1726 when he was ordered by the French government to return to China. Setting aside for a moment the Foucauldian question of insanity as a socio-cultural control mechanism in the age of reason, the relevance of the Hu question here is the question of whether he was committed to the asylum because he was “really mad” or perceived to be mad to the “foreign” Parisians because he was utterly “alien” to them. Either way, the question of Hu poses the “scandalous” difficulty of translating the dynamic chiasms of intercultural perception, misperception, and even imperception. Transversality is a keyword in the existential phenomenology of Calvin O. Schrag in pursuit of discovering a “diagonal” crossing (Xing) in resolving the deadlock between Western modernity and postmodernity.9 Sitting in a philosophical cockpit, as it were, it is a balancing act of navigating through the stormy time and space between the dichotomous poles of the modernist obsession with identity and universalism, on the one hand, and the postmodernist exhaustive drive for difference and pluralism, on the other. Transversality actively seeks a transformation. It is, according to Schrag (Ramsey and Miller, 2003: 26), the recognition of difference that keeps open “the prospect for invention, intervention, transgression, re-creation, etc.” It looks for “convergence without coincidence”—to use his repeatedly emphasized expression. Thus, it broadens the “in-between” for the sake of the “beyond” by splitting the difference between modern identity and postmodern difference. Transversality is primarily a derivative concept of geometry. It denotes the crossing (Xing) of two diagonal lines in any given parallelogram. Schrag exacts l’esprit de finesse by way of a geometric configuration: in addition to the two “diagonals” crossing or intersecting each other at the epicenter of any rectangle, there are also the hermeneutical “circle” and the rhetorical “triangle.” By way of the “middle voice” of transversality, he means to subvert and transgress particularly the dichotomy between “the Scylla of a hegemonic unification”/“a vacuous universalism” on the one hand, and “the Charybdis of a chaotic pluralism”/“an anarchic historicism” on the other. Insofar as it is a negotiated or compromised “middle voice,” transversality touches the soul and heart of Buddhism. The newly emerging face of transversality may be likened to the famous wooden statue of Buddha at a Zen temple in Kyoto whose face marks a new dawn of awakening (satori) or signals the beginning of a new regime of ontology, ethics, politics, and culture. From the crack in the middle of the old face of the Buddha’s statue, there emerges an interstitial, liminal face that signifies a new transfiguration and transvaluation of the existing world. The icon of the emerging new face symbolizes the arrival of Maitreya (the “future Enlightened One”) or Middle Way—the third enabling term of transversality which is destined to navigate the difficult waters of intercultural border-crossings. We are warned not to take it as a middle point between two poles. Rather, it breaks through bipolarity (e.g., modernity and postmodernity, nature and society, mind and body, femininity and masculinity, and East and West). What is important here is the fact that transversality is the paradigmatic rendition of overcoming bipolarity itself. The bipolar solids melt into the air of transversality, as it were. As disenchantment calls for transcendence, transversality is used here as a deconstructive concept. It deconstructs Eurocentrism the mission of which is to proselytize the universal and the “‘catholicity’ of the rational” (see Sartre, 1965: 113). Transversality first dismantles or unpacks the status quo and then goes beyond what is given, received, or established by constructing a new formation of concepts. It, in short, attempts to challenge the assumed transparency of truth as universal and overcome the limits of universality as the Eurocentric canon of truth in Western modernity. It means to decenter Europe as the site of “universal truth” whose “identitarian” and “unitarian” motivation fails to take into account the world of multiculturalism. The pluralist Johann Gottfried Herder (1969: 199) challenges: “I find myself unable to comprehend how reason can be presented so universally as the single summit and purpose of all human culture, all happiness, all good. Is the whole body just one big eye?” The French philosopher and sinologist François Jullien (2002 and 2003) calls the effort of this decentering Eurocentrism or Western modernity—with Kant in mind—“a new ‘Copernican reversal.’” He contends that in “shaking up” Western modernity, China becomes a “philosophical tool.” He uses Chinese thought to interrogate Western philosophy and to liberate it from its own “mental cage.” Most radically, he wishes to replace the very concept of “truth” itself with that of “intelligibility” because the concept of truth is bound up with the history of Western philosophy. Jullien puts Foucault to test in order to vindicate the Eurocentric “legislation” of truth for all global humanity. In his 1978 visit to Japan, the vintage Foucault remarked that as the warp of knowledge and the woof of political power are interwoven as one fabric, European imperialism and the era of Western philosophy together come to an end. Foucault is not alone in conjecturing that philosophy of the future must be born “outside Europe” or in the “meetings and impacts” between Europe and non-Europe (see Jung, 2002b: 1).10 The interlacing of the East and the West, in other words, will give birth to a new philosophy. For too long, the East has been living in the dark shadow of Western modernity. In this background there lurks an intriguing question that the Singaporean intellectual/statesman Kishore Mahbubani, who is now Dean of the Lee Kuan Yew School of Public Policy, asked a few years ago: “Can Asians think?” (1998). Long before Foucault and Jullien, Maurice Merleau-Ponty spoke of the “lateral universal” and the lateral continuity of all humanity both “primitive” and “civilized” across history. He was unmistakably a consummate transversalist avant la lettre. The lateral universal is for him a new paradigm for world-making as well as philosophy. “Lateral” rather than “vertical” thinking is paradigmatic in that instead of digging the same hold deeper and deeper in which there is no exit in sight, it digs a new hole in another place. For Merleau-Ponty, all history is not only contemporaneous and written in the present tense but also an open notebook in which a new future can be inscribed. It is rather unfortunately, I think, that his deconstructive effort for comparative philosophy and his sensitivity to the global scope of philosophy have escaped the attention of comparativists as well as specialists alike. I would venture to surmise that this inattention is woven out of the same fabric in our Eurocentric propensity and orientation in philosophy. Merleau-Ponty’s deconstructive effort in philosophy, in comparative philosophy, is evidenced in his critique of Eurocentric Hegel who was a priest and missionary of the universal and the rational.11 Merleau-Ponty (1964) is critical of Hegel who arbitrarily draws “a geographical frontier between philosophy and non-philosophy,” that is between the West and the East. Merleau-Ponty argues that philosophy is destined to examine its own idea of truth again and again because truth is “a treasure scattered about in human life prior to all philosophy and not divided among doctrines.” If so, Western philosophy is compelled to re-examine not only its own idea of truth but also related matters and institutions such as science, economy, politics, and technology. Besides philosophy’s own constant vigilance on what it is doing, Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenological orientation demands its attention to the ethnography of the socio-cultural life-worlds without which philosophy is a vacuous if not fatal abstraction. The way of ethnography’s thick description practiced by Marcel Mauss and Claude Lévi- Strauss, who also taught at the Collège de France, provides Merleau-Ponty with the idea of the lateral continuity of humanity between the “primitive” and the “civilized,” that is, with the incessant ethnographic testing of the self by the other and the other by the self which has a “diacritical value” for humanity’s coexistence and its planetary solidarity. Ethnography redeems Western narcissism precisely because it is the human science of understanding the “foreign other.” Merleau-Ponty contends that while for Hegel philosophical truth as absolute and universal knowledge is notarized and certified by the Occidental seal of approval alone, the Oriental past must also have an honored place in the famed hall of philosophies to celebrate its hitherto “secret, muted contributions to philosophy.” He (1964: 139) writes resolutely: “Indian and Chinese philosophies have tried not so much to dominate existence as to be the echo or the sounding board of our relationship to being. Western philosophy can learn from them to rediscover the relationships to being and an initial option which gave it birth, and to estimate the possibilities we have shut ourselves off from in becoming ‘Westerners’ and perhaps reopen them.” “If Western thought is that it claims to be,” he challenges further, “it must prove it by understanding all ‘life-worlds’” (italics added) as multiple geo- sociocultural realities. Thus Merleau-Ponty suggests that in contrast to the “overarching universal” of objective sciences or, we might add, Western metaphysics, the “lateral universal” is acquired through ethnographical experience as the way of “learning to see what is ours as alien and what was alien as our own.” His lateral universal is a passport, as it were, that allows us to cross borders between diverse cultures, enter the zone of intersections and discover cross-cultural connections and convergences. While the European geophilosophical politics of identity claims its validity as universal truth, the lateral universal takes into account “local knowledge” prior to planetary knowledge (dubbed by some as “glocalization”) and allows the hermeneutical autonomy of the other who may very well be right. Indeed, Merleau-Ponty’s lateral universal is contextualized as an open- ended and promiscuous web of temporal and spatial (i.e., chronotopic) interlacings. The (Eurocentric) universalist has failed to take into account seriously the question of diversity or multiplicity in the world of multiculturalism. He is still entangled in the cobweb of absolute universal truth and cultural relativism. As difference marks multiplicity and all relationships, Heidegger’s Differenz as Unter/schied edifies our discussion here because it plays and feeds on the coupled meaning of the words which connects, preserves, and promotes both difference and the relational in one breath. In Differenz as Unterschied, the other is neither assimilated/incorporated nor erased/segregated: the integrity of the other is well preserved. Here we would be remiss if, in light of Merleau-Ponty’s above-mentioned “lateral universal” including a critique of Hegel’s Eurocentrism, we fail to recognize the seminal contribution of the Caribbean francophone Édouard Glissant (1989 and 1997) to the making of the transversal world. Educated in philosophy and ethnography in France, he is a philosopher, a poet, and a novelist whose “poetics of relation” shaped Caribbean (antillais) discourse on “diversality” and “créolité” (“creoleness”). Glissant has an uncanny convergence in the name of transversality with Merleau-Ponty in his critique of Hegel the Eurocentric universalist and absolute rationalist when he articulates without equivocation that transversal relation means to replace “the old concept of the universal.” “Thinking about One,” Glissant puts it concisely, “is not thinking about All.” Speaking of Hegel’s conception of history, Glissant retorts: History is a highly functional fantasy of the West, originating at precisely the time when it alone “made” the history of the world. If Hegel relegated African peoples to the ahistorical, Amerindian peoples to the prehistorical, in order to reserve History for European people exclusively, it appears that it is not because these African or American peoples “have entered History” that we can conclude today that such a hierarchical conception of “the march of History” is no longer relevant. Glissant unpacks Hegel’s history by dissolving it as irrelevant or passé in the postcolonial world of diverse cultures which rejects “the linear, hierarchical vision of a single History.” Transversality is proposed and constructed by Glissant in opposition to and as a replacement of universality. For him, it is the “poetics” of cross-cultural encounters. It is the way of crossing and going beyond (i.e., creolized) ethnic, lingual, and cultural boundaries. It is indeed the site of hybridity. As Glissant himself puts it, transversality is “the site of converging paths” or the “convergence that frees us from uniformity.” The British postcolonial theorist Robert J. C. Young (2001: 68), who regards Eurocentrism as a “white mythology,” makes an interesting and unusually astute observation that “[p]ostcolonialism is neither western nor non-western, but a dialectical product of interaction between the two, articulating new counterpoints of insurgency from the long- running power struggles that predate and post-date colonialism.” It may be said that the postcolonial mind works like a “double helix.” More specifically, Paul Gilroy’s (1993) reputed thesis of “the black Atlantic” is in favor of hybridity or “double consciousness” that sums up the transcultural intermix of African and European things. Hybridity is a converging middle path of “multiple, interconnecting axes of affiliation and differentiation.” In the final analysis, Gilroy’s “black Atlantic” is constructed quintessentially as “a counter-culture of modernity.” The so-called “recognition” or “acknowledgment” of difference, which is not one but many, is not the final but only the first step in the making of hybridity. In In Praise of Creoleness/Éloge de la Créolitié—a Caribbean manifesto which is purposely written bilingually (in French and English), “diversality” (la diversalité) in opposition to universality is defined as “the conscious harmonization of preserved diversities” (l’harmonisation consciente des diversités preservées). When harmonization is understood musically, it enriches the totality and even coloration of “diversality” when two or more tones are put together (i.e., orchestrated), there emerges harmonization (or symphony) in which each individual tone is not lost but preserved, whereas when two colors are mixed together, there is no “harmony” but another color. In the name of “a polyphonic harmony,” “diversality” frowns upon “the obsessional concern with the Universal.” The above-mentioned Caribbean or “creolized” manifesto begins with the sentence: “Neither Europeans, nor Africans, nor Asians, we proclaim ourselves Creoles” (“Ni Europeens, ni Africains, ni Asiatiques, nous nous proclamons Créoles”). The Creole (as hybrid) is neither unitarian nor separatist, but is likened to be a hybrid “butterfly” who frees himself/herself by breaking off from an “ethnocentrist cocoon.” Glissant (1989: 98) himself describes the principium of creoleness as the end of “diversality” which can hardly be paraphrased: Diversity, which is neither chaos nor sterility, means the human spirit’s striving for a cross-cultural relationship, without universalist transcendence. Diversity needs the presence of peoples, no longer as objects to be swallowed up, but with the intention of creating a new relationship. Sameness requires fixed Being, Diversity establishes Becoming. Just as Sameness began with expansionist plunder in the West, Diversity came to light through the political and armed resistance of peoples. As Sameness rises within the fascination with the individual, Diversity is spread through the dynamism of communities. As the Other is a source of temptation of Sameness, Wholeness is the demand of Diversity. You cannot become Trinidadian or Quebecois, if you are not; but it is from now on true that if Trinidad and Quebec did not exist as accepted components of Diversity, something would be missing from the body of world culture—that today we would feel that loss. In other words, if it was necessary for Sameness to be revealed in the solitude of individual Being, it is now imperative that Diversity should “pass” through whole communities and peoples. Sameness is sublimated difference; Diversity is accepted difference.

III. RESPONSIBILITY AS FIRST ETHICS IN THE TWENTY-FIRST CENTURY12

What is humanity? How do we make sense of it in the twenty-first century? The term humanity has “ten-thousand” faces—to use the Sinitic expression. It is indeed a many-faced concept. If the devil can quote the Good Book, anti-humanists can call themselves humanists. If “secular humanism” is immoral, can we speak of religious inhumanism? Generally speaking, however, humanism—just like democracy—is a motherhood issue. Nobody disavows it: everybody claims to be a humanist. In the main, humanity has a twofold meaning. In the first place, it is a collective term for humankind as a multitude. Thus it is not one but many. According to Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri (2004: xiv-xv), humanity stands for neither “people” nor “masses” but a “multitude.” They contend that the idea of “people” folds many into a unitary entity while “masses” is a term driven to indolent uniformity. Both “people” and “masses” fail to take into account difference or diversity. Hannah Arendt, too, thought that without human plurality or diversity the word humankind or humanity is meaningless. To conserve diversity, “multitude” is preferred in describing the everyday socio-cultural world (Lebenswelt) which is nothing but a web of multiple relationships. As it is a plurality of singular individuals, “multitude” for its name sake happens to be a fitting term for both the phenomenon of multiculturalism and the advent of globalization. In the second place, more importantly, humanity stands for the ontological and moral quality of being human whose definition invites disagreements and controversies. Confucius is the standard-bearer of humanity as the moral quality of being human when he defines humaneness or benevolence (jen) as the highest and noblest virtue of humankind: as the wordplay has it, jen (the human) is jen (humaneness). The moral exercise of humanity is predicated upon the fundamental proposition that there is no “human nature” that is enframed theologically or philosophically. By human nature, I mean that quality of being human which is immutable or unchanging beyond the realm of history and culture. It is an invariable set of trans-historical and trans-cultural essences. The theory of human nature defies the idea that being human is constant becoming, that is, humans are capable of making/remaking and unmaking themselves, their history, and their culture. It is flawed, I submit, because it is deterministic: it allows neither change nor hope for the future. Moreover, the principle of making and unmaking for the future as the ontological and moral quality of being human calls for no prediction because it incorporates in them the phenomenon of self- fulfilling and self-denying prophecy. In most instances, so-called prediction in human events happens to be “postdiction” or what is known in American football language as “Monday-morning quarterbacking.” I would like to propose for the consideration of and experiment with this audience that responsibility be made “first ethics” and “first politics” as well as “first philosophy” for the twenty- first century. Philosophy has made the “ethical turn” in the latter part of the twentieth century which was previously unthinkable in the heyday of logical positivism when I was a graduate student in the late 1950s and early 1960s. Is this ethical turn a right turn, a left turn, a wrong turn, or a U-turn? None of the above. I would venture to call it a “Copernican turn” after the fashion of the nineteenth- century German philosopher Ludwig Feuerbach (1966) who discovered (the importance and primacy of) “Thou” in speculating the future of philosophy. The reason for my proposal is twofold. First, it is an alternative to the American exceptionalism of “rights talk” whose (Daniel Bell’s) “end of ideology” and (Francis Fukuyama’s) the “end of history” is tantamount to the triumphant declaration of Anglo-American liberalism turned into one universal ideology in disguise. The American exceptionalism of “rights talk,” I would contend, is a misfit for the world of multiculturalism in the age of globalization which demands the maximum of cooperation and harmony on its way to cosmopolitanism. Instead, it results in “clashes” the end of which is resolved by way of violence rather than dialogue toward the domination of one single ideology and one single nation. In other words, “rights talk” magnifies and even glorifies the self and one nation at the expense of others. Second, a new humanity for the future is in need of the ethics of responsibility for nature or the nonhuman world as well. Unlike the old tradition of humanity, this new humanity is no longer going to be anthropocentric. Anthropocentrism eventually brings the death of humanity as well as that of nature. The ethics of responsibility has been overshadowed by and subservient to “rights talk.” The hegemony of Anglo-American “rights talk” has obscured and misguided the importance of responsibility. “Rights talk” is directly founded in and funded by the liberal thought of John Locke which is judiciously characterized by the late Canadian political theorist C. B. Macpherson (1962) as “possessive individualism.” Possessive individualism places the individual at the center of the inviolable rights of possession which Locke called “property.” Property is for him a composite of “life, liberty, and estate.” “Estate” has been replaced with the “pursuit of happiness” in the American exceptionalism of “rights talk” (cf. Ignatieff, 2005). The American political theorist Louis Hartz accurately measures the temperament of American ideology when he remarks that all Americans are born Lockeans. In Rights Talk, Mary Ann Glendon (1991) characterizes the American “rights talk” as the dialect of the “I’s have it.” She explains its pervasiveness and dominance when he writes concisely that “The American rights dialect is distinguished not only by what we say and how we say it, but also by what we leave unsaid.” As America is the world, the so-called American “rights dialect” has become the universalized language of the world. To repeat: Fukuyama is the “last American liberal” whose “end of history” is a celebration of the global triumph of American liberalism. His “endism” is disguised in the garment of one ideology. Is the twenty-first century becoming American? Perhaps so. In his philosophy of history, Hegel envisioned America as “the land of the future” (see Chisolm, 1963: 25). However, it is far too early to tell with certainty (cf. Valladão, 1996). Lockean liberalism conceives of society as “a series of market relations” in which each and every individual enters voluntarily or contractually into a relationship with others with a view to maximize his own interest. As it heralds “economic man” (homo oeconomicus), economic rationality underwrites it. As the proprietor of his own person, the individual carries on his daily life as if he owes nothing to society. The theory of social contract stipulated in Lockean liberalism insures and warrants its individualism. What must be recognized in Lockeanism is a sea change or paradigmatic shift from the primacy of the political to that of the economic when Locke makes unequivocally clear that the sole function of government is the protection of private property. With Locke political categories have become subservient to economic ones (i.e., economism). Economism is the distinct herald of Lockeanism which has shook and made Western modernity. Notwithstanding its fundamental opposition to Lockean liberalism as possessive individualism, Locke’s economic rationality—especially its labor theory of value—is also the linchpin of Marxism in particular and socialism in general. To put it otherwise, economism is the ideological underpinning of Western modernity. The theory of “economics as a vocation” is yet to be written. For Levinas, who is regarded by many as the most important moral philosopher of the twentieth century, ethics is “first philosophy” (philosophie première or prima philosophia).13 As such it precedes both epistemology (Descartes) and ontology (Heidegger). “When I speak of first philosophy,” he declares, “I am referring to a philosophy of dialogue that cannot not be an ethics.” For him, heteronomy alone is the site of responsibility if not ethics itself.14 By heteronomy, he means to favor the other in an asymmetrical relationship. The heteronomic ethics of responsibility is anchored in the primacy of the other over the self where the other (“Thou” or “you”) rather than the self (“I”) is placed at the altar (“higher place”) of all relationships. Altruism for its name sake, therefore, is exemplary of responsibility. The ethics of responsibility based on the other- centeredness (“heteronomy”) is a radical shift from “rights talk” whose center is the self in everything we do and think. The former is “otherwise” than the latter. What “rights talk” is to Ptolemaic geocentrism, the heteronomic ethics of responsibility is to Copernican heliocentrism. Responsibility thusly defined is a Copernican reversal of social and ethical thought which began with Ludwig Feuerbach who discovered “Thou” at the center of human dialogue for the future of philosophy. In this connection, it is of utmost importance to note that Hannah Arendt’s controversial reportage concerning Adolf Eichmann’s “banality of evil” is correlated to “thoughtlessness.” By “thoughtlessness,” she meant Eichmann’s utter inability to think from the standpoint of an Other, i.e., the amnesia or erasure of the other’s difference. Eichmann’s “banality of evil” is indeed a sobering reminder that the politics of identity or the abolition of the other’s difference results in the inhumane politics of cruelty, suffering, violence, and extermination. The infliction of violence and terror by the invisible enemy was transparent in the faces of Americans on the fateful day of September 11 (9/11), 2001. 9/11 and its ensuing events unmistakably prove that violence has its own vicious cycle. Shashi Tharoor, who was a high senior United Nations official, summed up the magnitude of the demolition of the twin towers of the World Trade Center as birthing of the twenty-first century. For him, then, the new millennium began with violence. It began with a big bang rather than a little whimper. Its birth pang is likely to last for some time. The famous or infamous dictum of Karl Clausewitz’s Realpolitik may be incontrovertibly true. It pertains to the inseparability of violence from politics since for him “war is the continuation of politics by other means.” In his Humanism and Terror (1969/1947 in French), the French phenomenologist Maurice Merleau-Ponty declared that “humanism”—Machiavellianism notwithstanding—is not immune to violence. He asserted with firm conviction that one who abstains from violence toward the violent is an accomplice of violence itself. Not only is violence the common origin of all political regimes, but also violence is our lot as long as we humans are incarnate beings. However, we should not confuse “what is” with “what ought to be” on the one hand and hope with reality on the other. The Southern Confederate General Robert E. Lee was pensive when he warned that we became too fond of war. Violence is without doubt an utter failure of human dialogue, of communication.15 It eschews responsibility: it is intrinsically an irresponsible act because it intends to efface, harm, or kill an Other. The abolition of difference courts violence, while the acceptance of difference is an act of civility (see Ozouf, 1988: 12). Disagreement, too, governs our academic interdiscourses. To contradict or deny it is to authenticate it. As a freshman in college in 1954, I was introduced to Alfred North Whitehead’s inspiring work Adventures of Ideas (1954) which left an indelible impression on me. It taught me the enduring idea that human civilization or human civility is the victory of persuasion over force (Whitehead, 1954: 105). Whitehead convinced me to date that violence has no place in civilization. As a measured failure of persuasion, violence takes a heavy toll on humans and nonhumans alike in abolishing differences. The breach of civility is predicated upon one’s epistemological infallibility and moral inculpability which is a deadly mix: I can never err and be morally wrong. J. Glenn Gray’s The Warriors (1959) is a classic and superb study of homo furens (warriors). Among the issues that Gray describes such as the appeals of battle, camaraderie, death, guilty, and even a delight of “fearful beauty” in destruction, there is the “abstract” image of the enemy that anestheticizes man the fighter. It is the monstrous—totally dehumanized—image of the enemy who is at best “subhuman.” To repeat: violence is an irresponsible act because it intends to eradicate the other’s difference. I would be remiss if I fail to bring Václav Havel into my discussion here. He is a playwright who turned into a statesman of extraordinary courage, sagacity, and moral tenacity in coping with the political exigency of his time: he is truly a postmodern philosopher-statesman of our time. He has been the most prominent voice of post-Communist Eastern Europe. Havel was deeply influenced by Jan Patočka who was a student of phenomenology, an admirer of Masaryk’s democratic humanism and Comenius’s pansophic humanism, and an active political dissident who died in 1977 during a police interrogation. From the side of conservatives, Havel represents the death of communism as a totalitarian political system and the “end” of ideology and history as the transparent triumph of American liberalism. From the side of political radicalism, he is a champion of the powerless. Havel is above all a Levinasian. He closely read Levinas during his prison years in Czechoslovakia. Following Levinas, he considered responsibility as the innermost secret of moral humanity. Havel’s is an ethics of responsibility as humanity’s “destiny” and “first politics.” For Havel, freedom and responsibility are interlocked. Freedom is a requisite element of responsibility. The former, however, is not independent from responsibility. Responsibility is more inclusive than freedom because humans can be free without being responsible but they cannot be responsible without being free. Havel’s signature idea of “living in truth” (1987) marks the heart of his conception of morality. He may also be likened to Bakhtin’s dialogist who transgresses and subverts the canonical or “priestly” order of truth and the monological “misrule” of hierarchized officialdom. Havel’s “dissident” is first and foremost Camus’s “rebel” (l’homme révolté) (1958) who is a critic of Marxism as the dialectical metaphysics and eschatological politics of revolutionary violence. For the rebel is one who justifies the existentialist thesis that the human is the only creature who refuses to be what he/she is. He/she protests against death as well as tyranny, brutality, terror, and servitude. Havel’s dissident is a true rebel who senses and cultivates his allegiance to human solidarity with no intention of obliterating the other. He is able to say that I rebel, therefore we exist. In an interview published as “The Politics of Hope,” Havel (1991: 165-206) also talked about the role of an intellectual as a perpetually “irritant” rebel (or gadfly) who is self-consciously capable of detaching himself/herself from the established order of any kind and who is vigilant to and suspicious of belonging to the “winning side.” Havel shows that—to borrow the eloquent language of Roger Scruton (1990: 88) in writing about Masaryk and Patočka—“the individual soul is the foundation of social order and . . . the care of the soul, and the care of the polis, are two aspects of a single concern.” For Havel, in conclusion, morals are the basic stuff of all politics. Thus, politics is never a tetragrammaton (or four-letter word) precisely because it is deeply rooted in and inseparable from the moral makeup of humanity. He often speaks of politics as “morality in practice” “practical morality,” “anti-political politics,” and even “the art of the impossible” (1997) with Machiavelli’s politics as the “art of the possible” in mind which for Havel promotes “living in untruth,” that is, manipulation, image-making, deception, and above all violence. In the end, the heteronomic ethics of responsibility is for Havel the postmodern alternative to Realpolitik as the modern “art of the possible.” IV. RESPONSIBILITY FOR NATURE WITH A HUMAN(E) FACE

For a very compelling reason, it is often said that we are living in the age of ecology. We have been playing dangerously and recklessly for centuries with the Promethean fire of modernization which is driven by our interminable desire and appetite for more and more things for consumption (pleonexia) in the name of human progress and prosperity. Unfortunately, nature does not issue an insurance policy for humanity. Ecology has rightly become our ultimate concern. It has a religious overtone. It has turned into the question of “to be or not to be.” The ecological crisis persists: there is no waning sign to it. It is a permanent fixture of the human condition everywhere. Alarmingly, this earth, our dwelling place, has progressively become an inhospitable, precarious, ruinous, and even deadly place for all earthlings both human and nonhuman. The ancient Hindu scriptural saying of Bhagavad Gita captures the dire predicament of the earthly condition today: I am become death. Indeed, we stand at the edge of history since the end of the earth or nature is also the end of history. Is there then a saving measure on earth to overcome our human-induced ecological crisis? The ecological crisis signals human disembodiment and alienation from the earth as a “household” (oikos) whose “deed” is being taken away by nature’s mutiny or silent rebellion. In sinography, “crisis” is spelled with two ideograms: “danger” and “opportunity.” It means to seize an “opportunity” to save a situation from “danger.” To overcome the ecological crisis, we are in need of inaugurating a geophilosophy grounded in fundamentals which, according to Deleuze and Guattari, “brings together all the elements within a single embrace”—only in fundamentals since, in following the advice of Einstein, not everything that counts can be counted. Merleau-Ponty’s ontology or “there-being” (“il y a”) of intercorporeality establishes and secures the firm foothold in such fundamentals for erecting the edifice of geophilosophy as if the earth really matters. Only by way of his intercorporeal ontology are humanity and the earth said to be bonded or intertwined. Without doubt the intercorporeal “generosity” of the whole earth will be a promising and defining moment of humanity in the new millennium. Western modernity demystifies, de-naturalizes, and even de-ontologizes nature into an inert pile of use-objects. Francis Bacon (1955) is the most eloquent voice of Western modernity as the age of science, technology, and quantitative economy. He is often called the “poet of science.” Bacon advocated the convergence of theory and practice, of knowledge and utility, and of knowing and making for the sake of advancing what he called philanthropia, that is, for the sole benefit of humanity by cultivating the new experimental “inquisition of nature” in order to conquer it. The rationale of modern technology or technology’s instrumental rationality is spelled out clearly by Bacon when he insisted that knowledge and power are one and discovered “in the womb of nature many secrets of excellent use.” Speaking against the “degenerate learning” of medieval scholastics, Bacon felt that they had plenty of leisure in the cells of monasteries and colleges, but they knew no history of nature or “no great quantity of matter.” In short, their “cobwebs of learning” produced “no substance or profit.” He produced the perfect “instrumental rationality” for the modern-day justification of the earth as one gigantic power-plant or energy station. By so doing, Bacon—like Descartes and Locke—cultivated no responsible and humane ethics for nature. Synchronicity is the inviolable law of ecology (or geophilosophy). It refers to the ontological condition that in the cosmos everything is connected to everything else. M. C. Escher’s lithograph Verbum (1942) endorses synchronicity or the (ecological) continuum of Interbeing (both interhuman and interspeciesistic). In the beginning was the Word (verbum). The Word was the Relation or Interbeing. Therefore, a new vision of humanity must interweave history and nature. The French philosopher Michel Serres (1995: 4) puts the matter poignantly: “At stake is the Earth in its totality, and humanity, collectively. Global history enters nature, global nature enters history: this is something utterly new in philosophy” (italics added). As such, geophilosophy is an entirely new philosophy. Since no earthly element—including humans—exists in isolation, what transpires in one element affects all the others on earth. It is rather moving, I think, to recapture Havel’s defining moment of conscience that includes our responsibility for the order of natural things. As he watched dense brown smoke scattered across the sky from a huge smokestack of a hurriedly built factory, Havel (1987: 136) writes with a poetic flair: “Each time I saw it, I had an intense sense of something profoundly wrong, of humans soiling the heavens. If a medieval man were to see something like that suddenly on the horizon—say, while hunting—he would probably think it the work of the Devil and would fall on his knees and pray that he and his skin be saved.” Of course, his concern for the natural order is hitched to his ontological assumption that everything is “inter-being” with everything else in the world. Havel refers to the synchronistic effect of lepidoptery or—to put it simply—the “butterfly effect” (of chaos theory): “a belief that everything in the world is so mysteriously and completely interconnected that a slight, seemingly insignificant wave of a butterfly’s wings in a single spot on this planet can unleash a typhoon thousands of miles away.” Since humankind and nature are inextricably intertwined, there is no good reason why the responsible sense of humanity and that of nature cannot be synchronized. Furthermore, the death of nature signals the death of humanity with absolute certainty and not the other way around. Even if humanity perishes, nature remains. If the future of humanity depends on the generosity of nature, it stands to reason to emphasize that the responsible sense of nature must come before that of humanity. The “Earth First” movement in ecology tells us that to save humanity, we save nature or the earth FIRST. Today “rights talk” has even invaded and colonized the nonhuman world of nature when speaking, albeit with good intentions, of the “rights of nature” and “animal rights” in addition to “civil rights” and “human rights.” The “rights talk” of nature is nothing short of anthropocentrism— the shaping of nonhuman nature in human forms. Theriomorphism—the shaping of humans in nonhuman forms—is equally misguided because there are radical differences between humans and nonhuman nature. For example, all morals have their origin in humans but they are not necessarily anthropocentric. Long ago Confucius believed that it is impossible to understand humans without knowing the power of language. And he warned that human affairs can be carried out successfully only when their “names” are first rectified (i.e., cheng-ming, the “rectification of names”). Confucius issued his warning in the Analects long before George Orwell in 1984. There are more substantive reasons why ecology and “rights talk” are incompatible. In the first place, “rights talk” knows of no synchronicity. Lockean liberalism as possessive individualism begins with a contractual arrangement. In it, therefore, the individual is autonomous and sovereign, and he controls his own destiny. In the second place, more importantly, the concept of “possessiveness” of “rights talk” (i.e., “economism”) goes against the deep grain of ecology. For Locke’s possessive individualism, the utility of labor and industry is the source of material possession in exploiting the land. Labor alone produces the “value” of the land and the fruits of the earth. For him, wild things of nature have no “values,” which is to say, they are useless, unless it is cultivated by labor and industry. He called the uncultivated land “waste” (his own term). Locke, in sum, was ignorant of the wisdom of the deep ecologist Aldo Leopold (1987) which advances the idea of the earth as “a biotic community,” including not only humans but also—in his own words—“soils, waters, plants, and animals.” Instead of the utilitarian and calculative appropriation of nature, Leopold argued for the aesthetic and meditative appreciation (i.e., what Heidegger calls “Gelasssenheit” rather than “Gestell,” enframing). Leopold spoke of “conservation aesthetic.” For him, the aesthetic delight of things wild is as indispensable as free speech. In his deep reverence for the land, he scorned the insatiable appetite for the “cash value” of land and wildlife or “the tedium of the merely economic attitude toward land.” He had an utter distaste and disdain for reducing the land to a property or a set of commodities, for “skinning” the land for profit, for killing egrets for hats, for making farming only a business rather than an art.16 There is no need for us to emphasize that modern civilization is unmistakably technomorphic. Technology as instrumentum permeates every aspect of modern humanity. It is an absolutely necessary part of modern humanity as homo eoconomicus. It has been a driving force of economic growth from the “take-off” to the “mass consumption” stage. It is a god, as it were, who dwells in the temple of what I call “economism.” In such conditions, therefore, there must be a critique of the technological in addition to three (Kantian) critiques of the knowable, the practical, and the judgeable. We—not all but many of us—have indeed become disenchanted with the world whose dominant prose is written in the language of technology and with the modern condition of humanity which is enframed by the hegemony of technology including the cybernation of knowledge and the computerization and digitalization of society (i.e., what Heidegger aptly calls Gestell). We are all wired to, and become hostages of, the network of technology from which there is no easy and quick exit in sight. We are living, in other words, in the epoch when technology is totalizing, one- dimensional, planetary, and terribly banal and normalizing when micro-technology claims to have invented our “second self” whose “soul” may be imprisoned forever behind the invisible walls of gigantic technological Panopticon. History has become a nightmare from which there is no awakening—to emulate the language of James Joyce. Long ago the Chinese Taoist sage Chuang- Tzu warned that those who are too fond of technology would grow their hearts like machines. The destructive power of technology both visible and invisible unleashed in twentieth-century warfares: it destroys not only humans but also nonhumans alike—for example, the chemical weapons we used during the Vietnam War deforested and made the Vietnamese countryside landscape look like beehives. Moreover, the pervasive and careless use of technology makes us banal or “sleepthinking”: for instance, we ask why animals cross the roads we built to get killed instead of asking why we build roads where animals roam. It is instructive to note that in South Asia the Chipko movement tries to “hug” trees to protect them and prevent deforestation, whereas in the American Northwest environmental radicalism resorts to “spiking” to protect its timberland. In today’s world, more seriously, technology is no longer simply a means of human activity. It is not instrumental: it is not merely the application of science to praxis, but is itself autonomous in transforming praxis. It has become, in other words, an end in itself. As technology has a life of its own in reversing the end-means continuum, autonomous technology is technology-out-of-control. The rationale of technology as instrumentum or instrumental facilitation that serves the telos of human life became anachronistic. This, in fact, is the “categorical imperative” of technology as autonomous. It is not unreasonable, therefore, to argue, albeit against European and Anglo- American jurisprudence, that technology ought to be declared guilty before proven innocent.

V. EPILOGUE Transversality replaces universality: it is spelled and comprehended as “trans(uni)versality.” It is, as I have above proposed and intimated, the touchstone of correlating and negotiating differences in the postmodern world of multiculturalism. It makes connections—as Carol Gilligan (1982) puts it—“in the face of difference.” Instead of coming to hasty judgments and conclusions, therefore, we are obliged to study an anthropology of globalization thoroughly rather than selectively by taking stock of its losses as well as its gains. The transversalist is a “fox” rather than a “hedgehog.” I am alluding here to Isaiah Berlin’s line (1986: 1) from the fragments of the Greek poet Archilochus which reads: “The fox knows many things, but the hedgehog knows one big thing.” For the transversalist is one who has both deftness and agility to weave many ideas, whereas the universalist has one big thought. I am hesitant to use unconditionally the term humanism both new and old because it is more or less anthropocentric. Therefore, I prefer to use the expression “a new philosophy of life” which is intrinsically organic rather than artificial. The hope of constructing a new philosophy of life for the future, more specifically for the twenty-first century, is hitched onto the very existential thesis that humans are capable of making/remaking and unmaking themselves and their world. Hope is nothing but the passionate and never-ending pursuit of the “impossible.” Interbeing (or “Midworld”) has been the pivotal concern of Eastern thought, while Western philosophy has been preoccupied with and consumed by the question of Being. The way of transversality demands drawing insights from both East and West. What is deficient in one is augmented and supplemented by the other. Sinism, which is embodied in Confucianism, Taoism, and Ch’an (Zen) Buddhism, provides us with two indispensable ideas for a new philosophy of life in which the fabric of nature and humanity is inseparably interwoven—one is woof and the other warp: (1) Interbeing and (2) homo ecologicus. They are the two sides of the same coin, as it were, because they share the common ontological assumption that everything or every event is connected to every other in the cosmos and nothing exists in isolation. To be in isolation is no longer to be. It follows, therefore, that there cannot be just one center, the center is everywhere or multitudinous. Consequently, Eurocentrism or Sinocentrism must be decentered and unpacked. A new philosophy of life is intrinsically organic rather than artificial. Life encompasses all life-forms. As such, according to the principle of Interbeing, there is no reason why the helping hand of heteronomic responsibility cannot be extended to the life-world of nonhuman beings and things. What homo ecologicus is to the heteronomic ethics of responsibility, homo oeconomicus is to “rights talk.” There is no need to emphasize here that human prosperity can never be measured solely by material things. To put it philosophically, “Being” cannot be identified with “Having”: the former cannot simply be reduced to the latter. The economic, however important it may be, is only a means to the end (telos) of life. The heteronomic ethics of responsibility is based on an asymmetrical relationship which favors the other, while “rights talk” favors the self. Ethics in general and responsibility in particular, according to the long and cherished tradition of Sinism, is grounded in “fidelity” (hsin—literally, “the human standing by his/her words”) and “sincerity” (ch’eng—literally, “word-performed” or “word-accomplished”). Sincerity is quintessentially performative: it means “we perform in action what we promise in words.” To be sincere, speaking cannot be rendering just a “lip service.” In sincerity, therefore, knowledge and action are correlative: knowledge without action is empty, while action without knowledge is blind. Sincerity is a prescription for what and how to do things with word and deed. It embodies the moral foundation of humanity. Ultimately, the future cultivation of humanity in the world of multiculturalism depends on the interchange (inter-change) of thinking and doing at the “crossroads” (X-roads) of the East and West on the one hand and the North and the South on the other. This transversal interchange may be called an “intercritique” (Dosse, 1999: 345) in search of cultural confluence/convergence, hybridity, or creolization. Globalization is nothing but the way of cross-pollinating and cross-fertilizing cultural meanings, ideas, and values in multiplicity.17 The new phoenix of postmodern cosmopolitanism, whose language is governed by the important prefix inter, con, or trans has risen from the ashes of sovereign nation-states which the modernist Hegel deified as the ultimate telos of his dialectic. With the newly rising phoenix, the “rights” of sovereign individuals, including their moral self-righteousness, give way to the heteronomic ethics of responsibility which is accompanied by a declaration of interdependence. In the postmodern age of cosmopolitanism,18 the virtue of civility promotes our communication and interaction with “foreign” others without holding their “foreignness” against them (i.e., xenophilism) (see Bauman, 2000: 104). In the end, the good fortune (fortuna, moira) of globalization will be determined and sustained by the generosity or hospitality of the earth which provides all earthlings both human and nonhuman a natural habitat (see Derrida, 2001 and Toulmin, 1990).19 In concluding my thought on “humanity in transition” or the cultivation of humanity, let me recite the celebrated devotional meditation of the English poet John Donne in its old original English: “No man is an Iland, intire of it selfe; every man is a peece of the Continent, a part of the maine; . . . Any Mans death diminishes me, because I am involved in Mankinde; And therefore never send to know for whom the bell tolls; it tolls for thee” (quoted in Jung, 2002: 10). NOTES

1. There is a contrast between the masculine “priest” and the feminine “jester.” Arendt (1972: 144) notes that “The greatest enemy of authority, . . . is contempt, and the surest way to undermine it is laughter.” Cf. Woolf (1938: 182) who says: Laughter is “an antidote to dominance.” 2. Cox (1969: 162) writes elsewhere: “The world symbolized by the Feast of Fools is neither [B. F. Skinner’s] Walden Two nor [George Orwell’s] 1984. It is much more heterogeneous, messier, more sensuous, more variegated, more venturesome, more playful. It is a world for which a fiesta or even a love-in is a better symbol than a computer or a rocket. Technology need not be the enemy of the spirit in the modern world. But it should be a means to man’s human fulfillment, not the symbol or goal of that fulfillment itself.” 3. It is most interesting to note that “He [Bakhtin] felt that Rabelais drew his inspiration primarily from the comic grotesque of the Carnival, of life turned upside down and of the parody of everyday life: ‘This was Rabelais’s language.’ Bakhtin condemned the mistaken interpretations of Rabelais as the poet of the flesh and of gluttony (Victor Hugo) and those who saw in him the expression of the bourgeois interest in the economic individual; Rabelais’s style could only be understood as the translation of a popular, comic effect lay a whole cosmogony in Rabelais, and his focus on orifices, protuberances, and outgrowths corresponded to corporeal parts that put the individual into contact with the external world” (Dosse, 1997: 55. Italics added). 4. The episodic accounts of Leo Strauss’s influence on American politics are found in Norton (2004). 5. Raymond Aron is quoted as saying that “we must accord to the past the uncertainty of the future” (see Dosse, 1999: 308). 6. For a decade, I have been on a transversality binge, so to speak. See (Jung, 1995, 2002b, 2002d, forthcoming/a, and forthcoming/b). 7. For Schrag, the idea of transversality initially played the role of mid-wifery between modernity and postmodernity. Most recently, however, he (2004: 76) suggests that “The transversal logos replaces the universal logos as the lynch-pin for the philosophy of the new millennium.” The postmodern world is a transversal world. The anthropologist Michel-Rolph Trouillot makes the following point: “It [the postmodern world] is a world where black American Michael Jackson starts an international tour from Japan and imprints cassettes that mark the rhythm of Haitian peasant families in the Cuban Sierra Maestra; a world where Florida speaks Spanish (once more); where a Socialist prime minister in Greece comes by way of New England and an imam of fundamentalist Iran by way of Paris. It is a world where a political leader in reggae-prone Jamaica traces his roots to Arabia, where United States credit cards are processed in Barbados, and Italian designer shoes made in Hong Kong. It is a world where the Pope is Polish, where the most orthodox Marxists live on the western side of a fallen iron curtain. It is a world where the most enlightened are only part- time citizens of part-time communities of imagination” (quoted in Jung, 1996: 295). 8. In developing his new politics of cultural difference, West (1990: 36) tries to avoid the Scylla of “ethnic chauvinism” and the Charybdis of “faceless universalism.” 9. It is interesting to note that David Farrell Krell sketches das Geviert envisioned by Heidegger in the diagram of a rectangle which connects sky, earth, gods, and mortals with two diagonal lines having Being at its epicenter: the cross of Being is not a crossing out (Durchstreichung) but a crossing through (Durchkreuzen) (see Jung, 1987: 243n.27). 10. before he became interested in Japanese aesthetic culture and the Iranian revolution, Foucault (Afary and Anderson, 2005: 18) wrote with the inerasable sense of a great divide between the East and the West: “In the universality of the Western ratio, there is this divide that is the East; the East thought of as the origin, dreamt of as the dizzy point that is the place of birth, of nostalgia and promises of return, the East which offers itself to the colonizing reason of the West but is indefinitely inaccessible, for it remains always as a boundary, the night of beginning in which the West was formed but where it drew a dividing line, the East is for the West everything which the West is not, yet it is here that it has to seek whatever might be its originating truth. It is necessary to do a history of this great divide.” It is worth noting that Heidegger (see Jung, 1987: 217-218) expressed his bewilderment that the Japanese tend to forget the beginnings of their own thinking in their pursuit of the newest and latest in European thought. 11. Hegel’s lectures on the history of philosophy in three volumes were concerned with “Oriental Philosophy” (Chinese and Indian) in thirty-one meager pages in English translation. However, he was willing to make rather rash judgments about it. Hegel (1892: 121) asserted with no substantiation whatsoever: “We have conversations between Confucius and his followers in which there is nothing definite further than a commonplace moral put in the form of good, sound doctrine, which may be found as well expressed and better, in every place and amongst every people. Cicero gives us De Officiis, a book of moral teaching more comprehensive and better than all the books of Confucius. He is hence only a man who has a certain amount of practical and worldly wisdom—one with whom there is no speculative philosophy” (italics added). 12. In developing the heteronomic ethics of responsibility, I am deeply indebted to four philosophers: the Scottish philosopher John Macmurray, the Jewish-French philosopher Emmanuel Levinas, the Russian literary theorist Mikhail Bakhtin and the émigré American philosopher Hans Jonas. See Jung, 1999a, 2000, 2001, 2002c, and Jonas (1984). 13. Eaglestone (2004: 182) suggests that “postmodernism is first an ethical position before anything else.” Perhaps he has Levinas in mind. 14. Gould (2004) attempts to “universalize” and “globalize” democracy on the basis of interculturalism and “human rights.” Although she focuses on “rights,” Benhabib comes too close to the heteronomic ethics of care and responsibility when she speaks of the “rights of others.” For an attempt to “internationalize” or “globalize” the feminist theory of care, see Robinson (1999). 15. Glover (1999) is concerned with the moral history of humanity in the twentieth century. It is so littered with violence that the twentieth century may be characterized as the century of humanity’s inhumanity to humanity. 16. Carson’s (1965: 88-89) aesthetic appreciation of the earth or what Heidegger calls Gelassenheit is unsurpassable: “Those who dwell, as scientists or laymen, among the beauties and mysteries of the earth are never alone or weary of life. Whatever the vexations or concerns of their personal lives, their thoughts can find paths that lead to inner contentment and to renewed excitement in living. Those who contemplate the beauty of the earth find reserves of strength that will endure as long as life lasts. There is symbolic as well as actual beauty in the migration of the birds, the ebb and flow of the tides, the folded bud ready for the spring. There is something infinitely healing in the repeated refrains of nature—the assurance that dawn comes after night, and spring after the winter.” 17. Multiplicity is typically a postmodern concept. According to Calvino (1988: 110), it refers to our “inability to find an ending.” For him, there are five other memos or categories in addition to multiplicity: they are “lightness,” “quickness,” “exactitude,” and “visibility.” 18. Woolf (1938: 109) defines cosmopolitanism succinctly when she writes: “as a woman, I have no country. As a woman I want no country. As a woman my country is the whole world.” 19. Arendt (1958: 2) affirms humanity’s dependence on the earth or nonhuman world: “The earth is the very quintessence of the human condition and earthly nature, for all we know, may be unique in the universe in providing human beings with a habitat in which they can move and breathe without effort and without artifice. The human artifice of the world separates human existence from all mere animal environment, but life itself is outside this artificial world, and through life man remains related to all other living organisms.” In dealing with the issue of humanity’s dependency on the earth or the natural world, a large number of us, unfortunately and sadly, belongs to what Woolf (1938: 87) calls the “ignorantsia” as opposed to the “intelligentsia.” REFERENCES

Afary, Janet and Kevin B. Anderson. 2005. Foucault and the Iranian Revolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press Arendt, Hannah. 1958. The Human Condition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press ______. 1972. Crises of the Republic. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich Bacon, Francis. 1955. Selected Writings of Francis Bacon. Ed. Hugh G. Dick. New York: Modern Library Bakhtin, Mikhail M. 1986. Speech Genres and Other Late Essays. Trans. Vern W. McGee and ed. Caryl Emerson and Michael Holquist. Austin: University of Texas Press Bauman, Zygmunt. 1987. Legislators and Interpreters. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press ______. 2000. Liquid Modernity. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press Benhabib, Seyla. 2004. The Rights of Others. New York: Cambridge University Press Berlin, Isaiah. 1986. The Hedgehog and the Fox. New York: Simon and Schuster Bloom, Allan. 1987. The Closing of the American Mind. New York: Simon and Schuster Calvino, Italo. 1988. Six Memos for the Next Millennium. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press Camus, Albert. 1956. The Rebel. Trans. Anthony Bower. New York: Alfred A. Knopf Carson, Rachel L. 1965. The Sense of Wonder. New York: Harper and Row Chisolm, Lawrence W. 1963. Fenollosa: The Far East and American Culture. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press Cox, Harvey. 1969. The Feast of Fools. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press Derrida, Jacques. 2001. On Cosmopolitanism and Forgiveness. Trans. Mark Dooley and Michael Hughes. New York: Routledge Dosse, François. 1997. History of Structuralism, vol. 2. Trans. Deborah Glassman. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press ______. 1999. Empire of Meaning. Trans. Hassan Melehy. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press Eaglestone, Robert. 2004. “Postmodernism and Ethics Against the Metaphysics of Comprehension,” pp. 182-195, in The Cambridge Companion to Postmodernism. Ed. Steven Connor. New York: Cambridge University Press Eliade, Mircea. 1954. The Myth of the Eternal Return. Trans. Willard R. Trask. New York: Pantheon Books Feuerbach, Ludwig. 1966. Principles of the Philosophy of the Future. Trans. Manfred H. Vogel. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill Fukuyama, Francis. 1992. The End of History and the Last Man. New York: Free Press Gilligan, Carol. 1982. In a Different Voice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press Gilroy, Paul. 1993. The Black Atlantic. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press Glendon, Mary Ann. 1995. Rights Talk. New York: Free Press Glissant, Edouard. 1989. Caribbean Discourse: Selected Essays. Trans. J. Michael Dash. Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia ______. 1997. Poetics of Relation. Trans. Betsy Wing. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press Glover, Jonathan. 1999. Humanity. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press Gould, Carol C. 2004. Globalizing Democracy and Human Rights. New York: Cambridge University Press Gray, J. Glenn. 1967. The Warriors. New York: Harper and Row Hardt, Michael and Antonio Negri. 2004. Multitude. New York: Penguin Press Hassan, Salah and Iftikhav Dadi (eds.). 2001. Unpacking Europe. Rotterdam, Belgium: Museum Boijmans Van Beuningen and NAi Publishers Havel, Václav. 1987. Living in Truth. Ed. Jan Vladislav. London: Faber and Faber ______. 1991. Disturbing the Peace. Trans. Paul Wilson. New York: Vintage Books ______. 1997. The Art of the Impossible. Trans. Paul Wilson and others. New York: Alfred A. Knopf Hegel, G. W. F. 1892. Hegel’s Lectures on the History of Philosophy, vol. 1. Trans. E. S. Haldane. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trüber Herder, Johann Gottfried. 1969. J. G. Herder on Social and Political Culture. Trans. and ed. F. M. Barnard. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press Ignatieff, Michael (ed.). 2005. American Exceptionalism and Human Rights. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press Jonas, Hans. 1984. The Imperative of Responsibility. Chicago: University of Chicago Press Jullien, François. 2002. “Did Philosophers Have to Become Fixated on Truth?” (trans. Janet Lloyd), Critical Inquiry, 28: 803-824 ______. 2003. “‘China as Philosophical Tool’,” Diogenes, No. 50: 15-21 Jung, Hwa Yol. 1987. “Heidegger’s Way with Sinitic Thinking,” pp. 217-244, in Heidegger and Asian Thought. Ed. Graham Parkes. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press ______. 1995. “The Tao of Transversality as a Global Approach to Truth: A Metacommentary on Calvin O. Schrag,” Man and World, 28: 11-31 ______. 1999a. “Difference and Responsibility,” pp. 129-166, in Phänomenologie der Natur (Phenomenology of Nature), a special issue of Phänomenologische Forschunggen. Ed. Kah Kyung Cho and Young-Ho Lee. Freiburg/München: Karl Alber ______. 1999b. “Postmodernity, Eurocentrism, and the Future of Political Philosophy,” pp. 277-296, in Border Crossings. Ed. Fred Dallmayr. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books ______. 2000. “Taking Responsibility Seriously,” pp. 147-165, in Phenomenology of the Political. Ed. Kevin Thompson and Lester Embree. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer ______. 2001. “John Macmurray and the Postmodern Condition: From Egocentricism to Heterocentricism,” Idealistic Studies, 31: 105-123 ______. 2002a. “Enlightenment and the Question of the Other: A Postmodern Audition,” Human Studies, 25: 297-306 ______. 2002b. (Editor’s) “Introduction,” pp. 1-22, in Comparative Culture in the Age of Globalization. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books ______. 2002c. “Responsibility as First Ethics: Macmurray and Levinas,” pp. 173-188, in John Macmurray: Critical Perspectives. Ed. David Fergusson and Nigel Dower. New York: Peter Lang ______. 2002d. “Transversality and Geophilosophy in the Age of Globalization,” pp. 74-90, in Calvin O. Schrag and the Task of Philosophy After Postmodernity. Ed. Martin Beck Matuštík and William L. McBride. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press ______. Forthcoming/a. “Merleau-Ponty’s Transversal Geophilosophy” ______. Forthcoming/b. “Transversality and Comparative Political Theory: A Tribute to Dallmayr’s Work” Kolakowski, Leszek. 1968. Toward a Marxist Humanism. Trans. Jane Zielonko Peel. New York: Grove Press Leopold, Aldo. 1987. A Sand County Almanac, spec. commemorative ed. New York: Oxford University Press Levinas, Emmanuel. 1999. Alterity and Transcendence. Trans. Michael B. Smith. New York: Columbia University Press Locke, John. 1960. Two Treatises of Government. Cambridge, UK: University Press Macpherson, C. B. 1962. The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press Mahbubani, Kishore. 1998. Can Asians Think? Singapore: Times Books International Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. 1964. “Everywhere and Nowhere,” pp. 121-158, in Signs. Trans. Richard C. McCleary. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press ______. 1969. Humanism and Terror. Trans. John O’Neill. Boston: Beacon Press Merry, Robert W. 2005. Sands of Empire. New York: Simon and Schuster Norton, Anne. 2004. Leo Strauss and the Politics of American Empire. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press Ozouf, Mona. 1988. Festivals and the French Revolution. Trans. Alan Sheridan. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press Ramsey, Ramsey Eric and David James Miller (eds.). Experiences Between Philosophy and Communication. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press Robinson, Fiona. 1999. Globalizing Care. Boulder, CO: Westview Press Said, Edward E. 1978. Orientalism. New York: Random House Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1965. Anti-Semite and Jew. Trans. George J. Becker. New York: Schocken Books Schrag, Calvin O. 2004. Convergence Amidst Difference. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press Scruton, Roger. 1990. “Masaryk, Patocka and the Care of the Soul,” pp. 74-88, in Philosopher on Dover Beach. New York: St. Martin’s Press Serres, Michel. 1995. The Natural Contract. Trans. Elizabeth MacArthur and William Paulson. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press Spence, Jonathan D. 1988. The Question of Hu. New York: Alfred A. Knopf Toulmin, Stephen. 1990. Cosmopolis. New York: Free Press Valladão, Alfredo G. A. 1996. The Twenty-First Century Will be American. Trans. John Howe. London: Verso West, Cornel. 1990. “The New Cultural Politics of Difference,” pp. 19-36, in Out There. Ed. Russell Ferguson, Martha Gever, Trinh T. Minh-ha, and Cornel West. New York: The New Museum of Contemporary Art Whitehead, Alfred North. 1954. Adventures of Ideas. New York: Macmillan Woolf, Virginia. 1938. Three Guineas. New York: Harcourt Brace Young, Robert J. C. 2001. Postcolonialism. Oxford, UK: Blackwell