Characterizing Circuit Complexity Classes by Logics with Recursion∗

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Characterizing Circuit Complexity Classes by Logics with Recursion∗ Characterizing Circuit Complexity Classes by Logics with Recursion∗ Anselm Haak1 1 Theoretische Informatik, Leibniz Universität Hannover, Appelstraße, D-30167, Germany, [email protected] In this submission we introduce a certain recursion scheme into first-order logic variants of which allow us to capture a number of classes from circuit complexity, namely AC1, SAC1 and NC1 as well as their counting analogues. The advantage of our new approach is that it allows for a unified characterization of multiple important classes. The idea of descriptive complexity is to characterize complexity classes in a model- theoretic way in order to better understand their structure and use logical methods in order to get new insights about the considered classes. The starting point for this strand of research was Fagin’s theorem [3]. It tells us that the complexity class NP of problems decidable by non-deterministic polynomial-time Turing machines can be characterized as the class of problems definable in existential second order logic. Many characterizations followed, among them characterizations of the circuit complexity classes AC0, NC1 and TC0, see e.g. [1, 5]. Characterizations of uniform classes from circuit complexity are of special interest, because the definitions of these classes usually build upon two disconnected models: The uniformity condition is defined via some logic or using a machine model, while the main power of computation stems from the name-giving circuits. Model-theoretic characterizations allow to define these classes in purely logical terms. Another important kind of classes are so called counting classes. These are classes of functions from inputs to natural numbers that are usually defined by counting the number of some kind of witness for membership in a language. Of course, what kind of witness is considered depends on the specific class. For these kind of classes, only very few model- theoretic characterizations are known. The most prominent one is probably the general- ization of Fagin’s theorem, stating that #P = #FO: Counting the number of accepting paths of NP-machines can be characterized as counting the number of satisfying assign- ments to free relational variables in FO-formulae [6]. Besides that, we recently showed that Immermans result AC0 = FO [5] can also be generalized to the counting setting, showing #AC0 = #Win-FO [4]. Since the area of descriptive complexity for counting classes is not really well devel- oped, more characterizations of such classes are desirable. In this regard we want to focus on classes from circuit complexity and try to give characterizations of classes defined via Boolean circuits that also extend to the counting setting. Towards this goal, the best known characterizations of NC1 [1] does not seem to be helpful. On the other hand, we feel like the generalization of AC0 = FO to the whole AC-hierarchy using formulae of logarithmic length does seem a little unnatural. Instead, we sought inspiration from a result by Compton and Laflamme, characterizing NC1 by FO with a certain kind of linear recursion [2]. This approach does not seem to generalize to the classes SAC1 and AC1, though. Instead of focus- ing on transferring this kind of recursion to other classes, we define a new kind of recursion that more direcly captures the essence of uniform circuit classes with the counting setting in mind. Introducing this kind of recursion into first-order logic allows us to characterize NC1, SAC1 and AC1 in similar ways. Furthermore, the approach also works in the counting ∗ This submission is based on joint research with Arnaud Durand and Heribert Vollmer. © Anselm Haak; licensed under Creative Commons License CC-BY Leibniz International Proceedings in Informatics Schloss Dagstuhl – Leibniz-Zentrum für Informatik, Dagstuhl Publishing, Germany XX:2 Characterizing Circuit Complexity Classes by Logics with Recursion setting. While the recursion scheme is more directly connected to the definition of uniform circuit complexity classes, the approach still bears the advantage of yielding descriptions of the classes in purely logical terms. We now want to briefly recall the definition of FO-uniform families of Boolean circuits. A Boolean circuit is a directed acyclic graph. The nodes of this graph—also called gates—are marked with “∧”, “∨” or with an index of an input position. Also, one gate is marked as the output gate. To talk about these circuits in first-order logic, we use the vocabulary τcirc = 2 1 1 2 2 1 (E ,G∧,G∨, Input , negatedInput , output ). The meaning of the predicates E, G∧,G∨ and output is straightforward. Input(x, i) holds, if gate x is an input gate and associated with the i-th input position. An FO-uniform circuit family is a family of circuits C = (Cn)n∈N for which there is an FO-interpretation (FO-query) I : STRUC[τstring] → STRUC[τcirc] such ∗ that for all w ∈ {0, 1} : I(Aw) = C|w|. Here, τstring is the vocabulary of binary strings, Aw is the structure representing string w and C|w| is given as a τcirc-structure. The recursion scheme we introduce allows for the recursive definition of a predicate P . Syntactically, the constructions looks as follows: [P (x, y) ≡ Qz.(z < y/2 ∧ ψ(y, z))θ(x, y, P (x, z))]. The recursion runs over the parameter y. Q is a quantifier, which will either be ∃ or ∀ depending on the parity of y. The quantification of z is guarded by the formula z < y/2 ∧ ψ(y, z). This means that the value of the second input is at least halved in each step. If Q is an existential quantifier, the semantics is: P (x, y), if there is a z among those satisfying z < y/2∧ψ(y, z) such that θ(x, y, P (x, z)) holds. If Q is a universal quantifier, the semantics is: P (x, y), if for all z among those satisfying z < y ∧ ψ(y, z) also θ(x, y, P (x, z)) holds. We denote this kind of recursion by GRP(guarded recursive predicate definition). In this unrestricted way, the recursion branches polynomially. The depth of the recursion is bounded logarithmically due to the condition z < y/2. This intuatively suggests, that this kind of recursion captures the essence of AC1-computations. The definition can be altered by bounding the quantifier Q in the universal case or in both cases, resulting in characaterizations of SAC1 and NC1, respectively. This is done by changing the semantics e.g. in the universal case to: P (x, y), if for all z among the maximal two satisfying z < y/2∧ ψ(y, z) also θ(x, y, P (x, z)) holds. We call the restricted versions GRPsemi and GRPbounded, respectively. In order to capture said classes, we add the above kind of recursive definition in FO- formulae. We call the resulting logics FO(GRP), FO(GRPsemi) and FO(GRPbounded), re- spectively. We define these logics as follows: I Definition 1. FO(GRP) is first-order logic with occurrences of GRP. That is, it consists of all formulae of the form [P1(x, y) ≡ Qz.(z < y/2 ∧ ψ1(y, z)) θ1(x, y, P (x, z))] ··· [Pk(x, y) ≡ Qz.(z < y/2 ∧ ψk(y, z)) θk(x, y, P (x, z))] ϕ(P1,...,Pk), where the semantics of the recursive definitions is as described above. FO(GRPsemi) and FO(GRPbounded) are defined analogously. As usual, we also denote by FO(GRP) the class of languages that exactly consist of those words that are encodings of structures with a specific FO(GRP)-definable property. Since we only consider τstring-structures here, this can be stated as L ∈ FO(GRP) ·⇐⇒ there is a formula ϕ ∈ FO(GRP) such that w ∈ L ⇔ Aw ϕ for all w Anselm Haak XX:3 We use FO(GRPsemi) and FO(GRPbounded) to denote classes of languages in the same way. This leads us to one of our main theorems. I Theorem 2. (i) FO(GRP) = AC1 1 (ii) FO(GRPsemi) = SAC 1 (iii) FO(GRPbounded) = NC We will sketch the proof for the unbounded version here. Proof Sketch for Theorem 2.(i). ⊇: Let L ∈ AC1 via the FO-uniform AC1 circuit family C = (Cn)n∈N. Let I = (ϕE, ϕG∧ , ϕG∨ , ϕInput, ϕnegatedInput, ϕoutput) be an FO-interpretation witnessing that C is FO-uniform. We can assume without loss of generality that within all Cn, all ∨-gates are even and all ∧-gates are odd. We can also assume that for all gates g1, g2 g1 in any Cn it holds that E(g1, g2) ⇒ g2 < 2 . Then we can express acceptance of an input by C with the FO(GRP)-formula [P (y) ≡ Qz.(z < y/2 ∧ ϕE(y, z)) P (z) ∧ ¬ϕLiteral(z) ∨ ϕtrueLiteral(z)] ∃out ϕoutput(out) ∧ P (out) with ϕLiteral(x) ·= ∃i ϕInput(x, i) ∨ ϕnegatedInput(x, i) and ϕtrueLiteral ·= ∃i (ϕInput(x, i) ∧ S(i)) ∨ (ϕnegatedInput(x, i) ∧ ¬S(i)). The predicate P defined recursively gives us exactly the evaluation of the gates in the circuit. Thus, the formula ∃out ϕoutput(out)∧P (out) expresses that the output gate of the circuit evaluates to 1. ⊆: Let L ∈ FO(GRP) via the formula [P (x, y) ≡ Qz.(z < y/2 ∧ ψ(y, z)) θ(x, y, P (x, z))] ϕ(P ). For simplicity in this proof sketch, we assume that only one predicate P is defined recur- sively within the formula. Also, P does not occur inside any negation in θ or ϕ. Ignoring occurrences of P , ϕ is an FO-formula. Hence, we can build an FO-uniform AC0 circuit family evaluating ϕ except for these occurrences. In order to compute the predicate P , we proceed as follows: For all x, y, z build a circuit that computes θ(x, y, P (x, z)) from P (x, z).
Recommended publications
  • Database Theory
    DATABASE THEORY Lecture 4: Complexity of FO Query Answering Markus Krotzsch¨ TU Dresden, 21 April 2016 Overview 1. Introduction | Relational data model 2. First-order queries 3. Complexity of query answering 4. Complexity of FO query answering 5. Conjunctive queries 6. Tree-like conjunctive queries 7. Query optimisation 8. Conjunctive Query Optimisation / First-Order Expressiveness 9. First-Order Expressiveness / Introduction to Datalog 10. Expressive Power and Complexity of Datalog 11. Optimisation and Evaluation of Datalog 12. Evaluation of Datalog (2) 13. Graph Databases and Path Queries 14. Outlook: database theory in practice See course homepage [) link] for more information and materials Markus Krötzsch, 21 April 2016 Database Theory slide 2 of 41 How to Measure Query Answering Complexity Query answering as decision problem { consider Boolean queries Various notions of complexity: • Combined complexity (complexity w.r.t. size of query and database instance) • Data complexity (worst case complexity for any fixed query) • Query complexity (worst case complexity for any fixed database instance) Various common complexity classes: L ⊆ NL ⊆ P ⊆ NP ⊆ PSpace ⊆ ExpTime Markus Krötzsch, 21 April 2016 Database Theory slide 3 of 41 An Algorithm for Evaluating FO Queries function Eval(', I) 01 switch (') f I 02 case p(c1, ::: , cn): return hc1, ::: , cni 2 p 03 case : : return :Eval( , I) 04 case 1 ^ 2 : return Eval( 1, I) ^ Eval( 2, I) 05 case 9x. : 06 for c 2 ∆I f 07 if Eval( [x 7! c], I) then return true 08 g 09 return false 10 g Markus Krötzsch, 21 April 2016 Database Theory slide 4 of 41 FO Algorithm Worst-Case Runtime Let m be the size of ', and let n = jIj (total table sizes) • How many recursive calls of Eval are there? { one per subexpression: at most m • Maximum depth of recursion? { bounded by total number of calls: at most m • Maximum number of iterations of for loop? { j∆Ij ≤ n per recursion level { at most nm iterations I • Checking hc1, ::: , cni 2 p can be done in linear time w.r.t.
    [Show full text]
  • Interactive Proof Systems and Alternating Time-Space Complexity
    Theoretical Computer Science 113 (1993) 55-73 55 Elsevier Interactive proof systems and alternating time-space complexity Lance Fortnow” and Carsten Lund** Department of Computer Science, Unicersity of Chicago. 1100 E. 58th Street, Chicago, IL 40637, USA Abstract Fortnow, L. and C. Lund, Interactive proof systems and alternating time-space complexity, Theoretical Computer Science 113 (1993) 55-73. We show a rough equivalence between alternating time-space complexity and a public-coin interactive proof system with the verifier having a polynomial-related time-space complexity. Special cases include the following: . All of NC has interactive proofs, with a log-space polynomial-time public-coin verifier vastly improving the best previous lower bound of LOGCFL for this model (Fortnow and Sipser, 1988). All languages in P have interactive proofs with a polynomial-time public-coin verifier using o(log’ n) space. l All exponential-time languages have interactive proof systems with public-coin polynomial-space exponential-time verifiers. To achieve better bounds, we show how to reduce a k-tape alternating Turing machine to a l-tape alternating Turing machine with only a constant factor increase in time and space. 1. Introduction In 1981, Chandra et al. [4] introduced alternating Turing machines, an extension of nondeterministic computation where the Turing machine can make both existential and universal moves. In 1985, Goldwasser et al. [lo] and Babai [l] introduced interactive proof systems, an extension of nondeterministic computation consisting of two players, an infinitely powerful prover and a probabilistic polynomial-time verifier. The prover will try to convince the verifier of the validity of some statement.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Randomness Complexity of Interactive Proofs and Statistical Zero-Knowledge Proofs*
    On the Randomness Complexity of Interactive Proofs and Statistical Zero-Knowledge Proofs* Benny Applebaum† Eyal Golombek* Abstract We study the randomness complexity of interactive proofs and zero-knowledge proofs. In particular, we ask whether it is possible to reduce the randomness complexity, R, of the verifier to be comparable with the number of bits, CV , that the verifier sends during the interaction. We show that such randomness sparsification is possible in several settings. Specifically, unconditional sparsification can be obtained in the non-uniform setting (where the verifier is modelled as a circuit), and in the uniform setting where the parties have access to a (reusable) common-random-string (CRS). We further show that constant-round uniform protocols can be sparsified without a CRS under a plausible worst-case complexity-theoretic assumption that was used previously in the context of derandomization. All the above sparsification results preserve statistical-zero knowledge provided that this property holds against a cheating verifier. We further show that randomness sparsification can be applied to honest-verifier statistical zero-knowledge (HVSZK) proofs at the expense of increasing the communica- tion from the prover by R−F bits, or, in the case of honest-verifier perfect zero-knowledge (HVPZK) by slowing down the simulation by a factor of 2R−F . Here F is a new measure of accessible bit complexity of an HVZK proof system that ranges from 0 to R, where a maximal grade of R is achieved when zero- knowledge holds against a “semi-malicious” verifier that maliciously selects its random tape and then plays honestly.
    [Show full text]
  • Week 1: an Overview of Circuit Complexity 1 Welcome 2
    Topics in Circuit Complexity (CS354, Fall’11) Week 1: An Overview of Circuit Complexity Lecture Notes for 9/27 and 9/29 Ryan Williams 1 Welcome The area of circuit complexity has a long history, starting in the 1940’s. It is full of open problems and frontiers that seem insurmountable, yet the literature on circuit complexity is fairly large. There is much that we do know, although it is scattered across several textbooks and academic papers. I think now is a good time to look again at circuit complexity with fresh eyes, and try to see what can be done. 2 Preliminaries An n-bit Boolean function has domain f0; 1gn and co-domain f0; 1g. At a high level, the basic question asked in circuit complexity is: given a collection of “simple functions” and a target Boolean function f, how efficiently can f be computed (on all inputs) using the simple functions? Of course, efficiency can be measured in many ways. The most natural measure is that of the “size” of computation: how many copies of these simple functions are necessary to compute f? Let B be a set of Boolean functions, which we call a basis set. The fan-in of a function g 2 B is the number of inputs that g takes. (Typical choices are fan-in 2, or unbounded fan-in, meaning that g can take any number of inputs.) We define a circuit C with n inputs and size s over a basis B, as follows. C consists of a directed acyclic graph (DAG) of s + n + 2 nodes, with n sources and one sink (the sth node in some fixed topological order on the nodes).
    [Show full text]
  • The Complexity Zoo
    The Complexity Zoo Scott Aaronson www.ScottAaronson.com LATEX Translation by Chris Bourke [email protected] 417 classes and counting 1 Contents 1 About This Document 3 2 Introductory Essay 4 2.1 Recommended Further Reading ......................... 4 2.2 Other Theory Compendia ............................ 5 2.3 Errors? ....................................... 5 3 Pronunciation Guide 6 4 Complexity Classes 10 5 Special Zoo Exhibit: Classes of Quantum States and Probability Distribu- tions 110 6 Acknowledgements 116 7 Bibliography 117 2 1 About This Document What is this? Well its a PDF version of the website www.ComplexityZoo.com typeset in LATEX using the complexity package. Well, what’s that? The original Complexity Zoo is a website created by Scott Aaronson which contains a (more or less) comprehensive list of Complexity Classes studied in the area of theoretical computer science known as Computa- tional Complexity. I took on the (mostly painless, thank god for regular expressions) task of translating the Zoo’s HTML code to LATEX for two reasons. First, as a regular Zoo patron, I thought, “what better way to honor such an endeavor than to spruce up the cages a bit and typeset them all in beautiful LATEX.” Second, I thought it would be a perfect project to develop complexity, a LATEX pack- age I’ve created that defines commands to typeset (almost) all of the complexity classes you’ll find here (along with some handy options that allow you to conveniently change the fonts with a single option parameters). To get the package, visit my own home page at http://www.cse.unl.edu/~cbourke/.
    [Show full text]
  • Interactive Proofs for Quantum Computations
    Innovations in Computer Science 2010 Interactive Proofs For Quantum Computations Dorit Aharonov Michael Ben-Or Elad Eban School of Computer Science, The Hebrew University of Jerusalem, Israel [email protected] [email protected] [email protected] Abstract: The widely held belief that BQP strictly contains BPP raises fundamental questions: Upcoming generations of quantum computers might already be too large to be simulated classically. Is it possible to experimentally test that these systems perform as they should, if we cannot efficiently compute predictions for their behavior? Vazirani has asked [21]: If computing predictions for Quantum Mechanics requires exponential resources, is Quantum Mechanics a falsifiable theory? In cryptographic settings, an untrusted future company wants to sell a quantum computer or perform a delegated quantum computation. Can the customer be convinced of correctness without the ability to compare results to predictions? To provide answers to these questions, we define Quantum Prover Interactive Proofs (QPIP). Whereas in standard Interactive Proofs [13] the prover is computationally unbounded, here our prover is in BQP, representing a quantum computer. The verifier models our current computational capabilities: it is a BPP machine, with access to few qubits. Our main theorem can be roughly stated as: ”Any language in BQP has a QPIP, and moreover, a fault tolerant one” (providing a partial answer to a challenge posted in [1]). We provide two proofs. The simpler one uses a new (possibly of independent interest) quantum authentication scheme (QAS) based on random Clifford elements. This QPIP however, is not fault tolerant. Our second protocol uses polynomial codes QAS due to Ben-Or, Cr´epeau, Gottesman, Hassidim, and Smith [8], combined with quantum fault tolerance and secure multiparty quantum computation techniques.
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 11 1 Non-Uniform Complexity
    Notes on Complexity Theory Last updated: October, 2011 Lecture 11 Jonathan Katz 1 Non-Uniform Complexity 1.1 Circuit Lower Bounds for a Language in §2 \ ¦2 We have seen that there exist \very hard" languages (i.e., languages that require circuits of size (1 ¡ ")2n=n). If we can show that there exists a language in NP that is even \moderately hard" (i.e., requires circuits of super-polynomial size) then we will have proved P 6= NP. (In some sense, it would be even nicer to show some concrete language in NP that requires circuits of super-polynomial size. But mere existence of such a language is enough.) c Here we show that for every c there is a language in §2 \ ¦2 that is not in size(n ). Note that this does not prove §2 \ ¦2 6⊆ P=poly since, for every c, the language we obtain is di®erent. (Indeed, using the time hierarchy theorem, we have that for every c there is a language in P that is not in time(nc).) What is particularly interesting here is that (1) we prove a non-uniform lower bound and (2) the proof is, in some sense, rather simple. c Theorem 1 For every c, there is a language in §4 \ ¦4 that is not in size(n ). Proof Fix some c. For each n, let Cn be the lexicographically ¯rst circuit on n inputs such c that (the function computed by) Cn cannot be computed by any circuit of size at most n . By the c+1 non-uniform hierarchy theorem (see [1]), there exists such a Cn of size at most n (for n large c enough).
    [Show full text]
  • Simple Doubly-Efficient Interactive Proof Systems for Locally
    Electronic Colloquium on Computational Complexity, Revision 3 of Report No. 18 (2017) Simple doubly-efficient interactive proof systems for locally-characterizable sets Oded Goldreich∗ Guy N. Rothblumy September 8, 2017 Abstract A proof system is called doubly-efficient if the prescribed prover strategy can be implemented in polynomial-time and the verifier’s strategy can be implemented in almost-linear-time. We present direct constructions of doubly-efficient interactive proof systems for problems in P that are believed to have relatively high complexity. Specifically, such constructions are presented for t-CLIQUE and t-SUM. In addition, we present a generic construction of such proof systems for a natural class that contains both problems and is in NC (and also in SC). The proof systems presented by us are significantly simpler than the proof systems presented by Goldwasser, Kalai and Rothblum (JACM, 2015), let alone those presented by Reingold, Roth- blum, and Rothblum (STOC, 2016), and can be implemented using a smaller number of rounds. Contents 1 Introduction 1 1.1 The current work . 1 1.2 Relation to prior work . 3 1.3 Organization and conventions . 4 2 Preliminaries: The sum-check protocol 5 3 The case of t-CLIQUE 5 4 The general result 7 4.1 A natural class: locally-characterizable sets . 7 4.2 Proof of Theorem 1 . 8 4.3 Generalization: round versus computation trade-off . 9 4.4 Extension to a wider class . 10 5 The case of t-SUM 13 References 15 Appendix: An MA proof system for locally-chracterizable sets 18 ∗Department of Computer Science, Weizmann Institute of Science, Rehovot, Israel.
    [Show full text]
  • Glossary of Complexity Classes
    App endix A Glossary of Complexity Classes Summary This glossary includes selfcontained denitions of most complexity classes mentioned in the b o ok Needless to say the glossary oers a very minimal discussion of these classes and the reader is re ferred to the main text for further discussion The items are organized by topics rather than by alphab etic order Sp ecically the glossary is partitioned into two parts dealing separately with complexity classes that are dened in terms of algorithms and their resources ie time and space complexity of Turing machines and complexity classes de ned in terms of nonuniform circuits and referring to their size and depth The algorithmic classes include timecomplexity based classes such as P NP coNP BPP RP coRP PH E EXP and NEXP and the space complexity classes L NL RL and P S P AC E The non k uniform classes include the circuit classes P p oly as well as NC and k AC Denitions and basic results regarding many other complexity classes are available at the constantly evolving Complexity Zoo A Preliminaries Complexity classes are sets of computational problems where each class contains problems that can b e solved with sp ecic computational resources To dene a complexity class one sp ecies a mo del of computation a complexity measure like time or space which is always measured as a function of the input length and a b ound on the complexity of problems in the class We follow the tradition of fo cusing on decision problems but refer to these problems using the terminology of promise problems
    [Show full text]
  • BQP and the Polynomial Hierarchy 1 Introduction
    BQP and The Polynomial Hierarchy based on `BQP and The Polynomial Hierarchy' by Scott Aaronson Deepak Sirone J., 17111013 Hemant Kumar, 17111018 Dept. of Computer Science and Engineering Dept. of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology Kanpur Indian Institute of Technology Kanpur Abstract The problem of comparing two complexity classes boils down to either finding a problem which can be solved using the resources of one class but cannot be solved in the other thereby showing they are different or showing that the resources needed by one class can be simulated within the resources of the other class and hence implying a containment. When the relation between the resources provided by two classes such as the classes BQP and PH is not well known, researchers try to separate the classes in the oracle query model as the first step. This paper tries to break the ice about the relationship between BQP and PH, which has been open for a long time by presenting evidence that quantum computers can solve problems outside of the polynomial hierarchy. The first result shows that there exists a relation problem which is solvable in BQP, but not in PH, with respect to an oracle. Thus gives evidence of separation between BQP and PH. The second result shows an oracle relation problem separating BQP from BPPpath and SZK. 1 Introduction The problem of comparing the complexity classes BQP and the polynomial heirarchy has been identified as one of the grand challenges of the field. The paper \BQP and the Polynomial Heirarchy" by Scott Aaronson proves an oracle separation result for BQP and the polynomial heirarchy in the form of two main results: A 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Multiparty Communication Complexity and Threshold Circuit Size of AC^0
    2009 50th Annual IEEE Symposium on Foundations of Computer Science Multiparty Communication Complexity and Threshold Circuit Size of AC0 Paul Beame∗ Dang-Trinh Huynh-Ngoc∗y Computer Science and Engineering Computer Science and Engineering University of Washington University of Washington Seattle, WA 98195-2350 Seattle, WA 98195-2350 [email protected] [email protected] Abstract— We prove an nΩ(1)=4k lower bound on the random- that the Generalized Inner Product function in ACC0 requires ized k-party communication complexity of depth 4 AC0 functions k-party NOF communication complexity Ω(n=4k) which is in the number-on-forehead (NOF) model for up to Θ(log n) polynomial in n for k up to Θ(log n). players. These are the first non-trivial lower bounds for general 0 NOF multiparty communication complexity for any AC0 function However, for AC functions much less has been known. for !(log log n) players. For non-constant k the bounds are larger For the communication complexity of the set disjointness than all previous lower bounds for any AC0 function even for function with k players (which is in AC0) there are lower simultaneous communication complexity. bounds of the form Ω(n1=(k−1)=(k−1)) in the simultaneous Our lower bounds imply the first superpolynomial lower bounds NOF [24], [5] and nΩ(1=k)=kO(k) in the one-way NOF for the simulation of AC0 by MAJ ◦ SYMM ◦ AND circuits, showing that the well-known quasipolynomial simulations of AC0 model [26]. These are sub-polynomial lower bounds for all by such circuits are qualitatively optimal, even for formulas of non-constant values of k and, at best, polylogarithmic when small constant depth.
    [Show full text]
  • Complexity of Matching Problems
    ,r. Symbolic Computation (1987) 3, 203-216 Complexity of Matching Problems DAN BENANAV, DEEPAK KAPUR AND PALIATH NARENDRAN Corporate Research and Development General Electric Company Schenectady, NY The associative-commutative matching problem is shown to be NP- complete; more precisely, the matching problem for terms in which some function symbols are uninterpreted and others are both associative and commutative, is NP-complete. It turns out that the similar problems of associative-matching and commutative-matching are also N'P-complete. However, if every variable appears at most once in a term being matched, then the associative-commutative matching problem is shown to have an upper-bound of O([ s [ * [ t [3), where [s I and [ t [ are respectively the sizes of the pattern 8 and the subject t. 1. Ingroduction Matching and unification algorithms play an important role in such areas as logic programming, functional and relational programming, au- tomated reasoning, program verification and specification analysis. Several papers have appeared that investigate the complexity of general term matching and related problems (])work et al. (1986), Hoffman and O'Donnell (1982), Overmars and Van Leeuwen (1979), Steyaert and Fla- jolet (1983)). Here we consider specialized instances of these problems, namely when certain operators under consideration have the associative and commutative properties. To our knowledge, Plotkin (1972) was the first one to have studied an approach for handling such operators by in- tegrating them into unification algorithms. Since then, methods have 0747-7171/87/010203 + 14 $03.00]0 ~ 1987 Academic Press Inc. (London) Ltd. 204 D. Benanav et el. been suggested for handling such operators in resolution proof systems using the paramodulation and narrowing techniques (Lankford (1975), Lankford and Ballantyne (1979), Slagle (1974)) and in term rewriting systems by suitably extending the Knuth-Bendix (1970) completion pro- cedure (Lankford and Ballantyne (1977), Peterson and Stickel (1981)).
    [Show full text]