Montesquieu, Liberalism and the Critique of Political Universalism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Montesquieu, Liberalism and the Critique of Political Universalism Montesquieu, Liberalism and the Critique of Political Universalism by Keegan Callanan Department of Political Science Duke University Date:_______________________ Approved: ___________________________ Ruth W. Grant, Supervisor ___________________________ J. Peter Euben ___________________________ Michael Allen Gillespie ___________________________ Jack Knight ____________________ Thomas A. Spragens Dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of Political Science in the Graduate School of Duke University 2011 ABSTRACT Montesquieu, Liberalism and the Critique of Political Universalism by Keegan Callanan Department of Political Science Duke University Date:_______________________ Approved: ___________________________ Ruth W. Grant, Supervisor ___________________________ J. Peter Euben ___________________________ Michael Allen Gillespie ___________________________ Jack Knight ____________________ Thomas A. Spragens An abstract of a dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of Political Science in the Graduate School of Duke University 2011 Copyright by Keegan Callanan 2011 Abstract In this dissertation, I advance a new interpretation of Montesquieu’s Spirit of the Laws . I argue that his liberal constitutionalism and his political anti-universalism are theoretically harmonious and mutually reinforcing elements of his political philosophy. But because Montesquieu’s thought is a species of the genus known as liberal theory, this interpretation of his thought also advances a theoretical and normative thesis: Liberal theory is not inherently or necessarily allied with projects of political universalism but rather possesses in-built resources for critiquing, educating and even resisting such projects. The dissertation makes this case through a critical analysis of Montesquieu’s Spirit of the Laws , its sources and its legacy. The unity of Montesquieu’s political philosophy becomes evident as we consider the ancient and modern intellectual influences and rhetorical purposes of his political particularism; his regime-pluralist understanding of political freedom and moderation; his account of liberal political culture; his treatment of political and social change; and the legacy of his liberal particularism in the work of Rousseau, Burke, Constant and Mill. As I suggest, this study represents a contribution to contemporary debates concerning liberal democracy’s global career and a challenge to common understandings of the essential character of modern liberalism. iv Dedication For Rachel v Contents Abstract …………...……..…………………..…………………………………….…... iv Acknowledgments ………..……………………………..………...……………..……. ix Abbreviations……………………………………………………………………………x 1. Introduction………………………..………………………..……………………….. 1 1.1 Montesquieu’s Political Particularism……………………………………... 8 1.2 Sources of Liberal Universalism…………………………………………… 19 1.3. Montesquieu’s Liberal Political Particularism and Its Implications………. 25 1.4 Outline of the Dissertation…………………………………………………. 30 1.5 A Note on Method…………………………………………………………. 36 2. The Sources of Montesquieu’s Political Particularism…………..………………….. 39 2.1 Political Particularism and Early French Constitutionalist Thought………..45 2.2 Classical Political Particularism and the Critique of Classical Republicanism…………………………………………………………………..60 2.3 Conclusion……………………………………………………………….….90 3. The Liberal Regime……………………………………………..…………………... 93 3.1 Mode of Normative Political Theory………………………………………. 99 3.2 Liberty and Moderation in the Constitution………………………………...106 3.3 Liberty and Moderation in the Laws……………………………………….. 131 3.4 Foundations………………………………………………………………… 139 3.5 Conclusion…………………………………………………………………. 154 vi 4. The Elements of Liberal Culture……...……………………………………………...157 4.1 Climate, Terrain and ‘the character of the spirit’…………………………...165 4.2 Hearth and Court, Household and City……………………………………..170 4.3 Judging Shadows and Abysses: Religion and Liberal Culture…………….. 178 4.4 Commercial Society and Political Liberty…………………………………. 211 4.5 Liberal Politics as a Source of Liberal Culture…………………………….. 235 4.6 Conclusion…………………………………………………………………. 246 5. Liberal Political Change……………..……………………..……………………….. 248 5.1 The Psychology of Liberal Constitutionalism……………………………... 254 5.2 Institutional Change and the ‘Tyranny of Opinion’……………………….. 261 5.3 The General Spirit and the Means of Political Change……………………..270 5.4 Stuck with Despotism? The Prospects of Political Reform………………...282 5.5 Conclusion…………………………………………………………………. 290 6. A Strained Marriage? Particularism, Liberalism & Montesquieu’s Legacy………… 294 6.1 Political Particularism against Universal Values?…………………………. 296 6.2 From Liberal Particularism to ‘Liberal Imperialism’?……………………...303 6.3 From Liberal Particularism to Traditionalist Conservatism?……………….322 6.4 Conclusion…………………………………………………………………. 333 7. Conclusion……………………………………….………………………………….. 335 Bibligraphy………………………………….…………………………………………. 350 Biography…………………………………..…….……………………………………..371 vii Acknowledgements I swear that this book nearly killed me; I am going to rest now; I shall work no more. Montesquieu I too am going to rest, at least for a couple of days, but not before thanking those who have helped to keep this study from taking as much out of me as Montesquieu’s big book seems to have taken out of him. I thank Jed Atkins, Brian Callanan, Nick Troester, Joel Schlosser, James Bourke, Ali Aslam, Ben Hertzberg, Jean Yarbrough, Jeremiah Russell, Owen Strachan, Asma Abbas, Bill Parsons, Paul Rahe, Hank Clark, Jim Ceaser, Céline Spector and David Schmitz for helpful comments and conversations that enhanced the quality and hastened the completion of this project. For the wisdom and energy she has invested into it, I am especially grateful to my attentive advisor, Ruth Grant. I am indebted as well to Michael Gillespie, Tom Spragens and Peter Euben for their good judgment and encouragement at early stages of the research, and to Jack Knight for his willingness to join the committee. Thanks are due to the Department of Political Science at Duke University and the H. B. Earhart Foundation for funding my graduate training. I am likewise grateful to the Program on Constitutionalism and Democracy at the University of Virginia for providing a final year of generous financial support—and good cheer. On the subject of good cheer, there has been no steadier source of laughter and lively diversion during these years of writing than my beloved daughter, Fiona. And of course I owe an immeasurable debt of long standing to my parents for their care and support. Finally, thanks are due to my wife, Rachel Callanan, whose loving encouragement has been the sine qua non of this effort. I have dedicated the dissertation to her. Oeuvres de Montesquieu , ed. Andre Masson, 3 vols (Paris: Nagel, 1950-1954), vol. 3, 1200. viii Abbreviations EL Montesquieu. [1748] 1989. The Spirit of the Laws , ed. Anne Cohler. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. MP Montesquieu. [1899] Forthcoming 2012. My Thoughts , ed. Henry C. Clark. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund. LP Montesqueiu. [1721] 2008. Persian Letters , ed. Andrew Kahn. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ix OE: Introduction …One likes to establish elsewhere what is established at home. - Montesquieu, The Spirit of the Laws , XIX.27 Few serious political observers would claim that the American invasions of Iraq and Afghanistan were motivated solely by an aspiration to export liberal democracy. But fewer still would suggest that this was not among the reasons wrapped into cumulative arguments for the campaigns, especially in the case of Iraq. The wars themselves and the monumental difficulties that have attended state-building efforts in these nations have triggered, in some circles, a reconsideration of global democracy promotion by force or indeed, by any means whatever. 1 These events have pressed upon us the question of liberal democracy’s limits and cultural preconditions. Is there a universal longing for western-style liberal democratic institutions? And if so, does a universal longing guarantee the existence of universal capacities to sustain these institutions? Does a commitment to liberal principles require a nation to seek the spread of liberal institutions to oppressed peoples? These are deeply controversial questions, particularly as they come on the heels of thirty years of liberal democratic expansion throughout the world. 1 See Zoltan Barany and Robert G. Moser, eds., Is Democracy Exportable? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009); Amichai Magen, Thomas Risse, Michael McFaul, eds., Promoting Democracy and the Rule of Law: American and European Strategies (Houndsmill, UK: Palgrave MacMillan, 2009); Robert Kagan, The Return of History and the End of Dreams (New York: Vintage, 2009); Tony Smith, A Pact with the Devil: Washington's Bid for World Supremacy and the Betrayal of the American Promise (New York: Routledge, 2007); Michael Cox, G. John Ikenberry and Takashi Inoguchi, eds., American Democracy Promotion: Impulses, Strategies, and Impacts (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000). 1 The final quarter of the twentieth century was a very good one for liberal democracy. Democratically elected regimes supplanted authoritarian governments on five continents as the third wave of democratization surged. In 1973, approximately 29 percent of all countries in the world were liberal democracies. By 2000, that number had jumped to 45 percent.
Recommended publications
  • Unjust Law As a Justification for Civil Disobedience
    Mgbakoigba: Journal of African Studies, Volume 4, 2015. UNJUST LAW AS A JUSTIFICATION FOR CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE Arinze Agbanusi Department of Philosophy Nnamdi Azikiwe University Awka. Introduction Laws are bodies of rules for human conduct. They are meant to guide human actions, indicating those that are permitted or accepted and those that are prohibited, which performance attracts one form of punishment or the other. Laws are supposed to guide the behavior of citizens of a nation. A nation without laws is like a vehicle without wheels. Without laws people cannot live peacefully together as there will be the problem of reconciling conflicting human rights. As Thomas Hobbes pointed out in his theory of the state, when man was alone, there was no need for laws. The need for laws was necessitated by the increase in human population, to help reconcile naturally conflicting rights of different individuals. It is therefore expected that citizens should obey laws, to avoid an anarchical state where jungle justice (the principle of survival of the fittest) operates. According to Hobbes, the commonwealth was formed because men had a foresight of their own preservation, and thus had to find a way of averting that miserable condition of war and strife which are natural consequences of ever conflicting human rights. For John Locke, the main aim of forming the commonwealth (government) is the preservation of the „Property‟ of Citizens. Since the commonwealth and laws were created for the noble sake of the preservation of life and property, through the avoidance of war and uncertainties; it behooves on all citizens to obey the laws of the state or nation.
    [Show full text]
  • Hugo Grotius's Modern Translation of Aristotle
    Digital Commons @ Assumption University Political Science Department Faculty Works Political Science Department 2016 Natural Rights and History: Hugo Grotius's Modern Translation of Aristotle Jeremy Seth Geddert Assumption College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.assumption.edu/political-science-faculty Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, and the Political Theory Commons Recommended Citation Geddert, Jeremy Seth. "Natural Rights and History: Hugo Grotius's Modern Translation of Aristotle." Concepts of Nature: Ancient and Modern. Edited by R. J. Snell and Steven F. McGuire. Lexington Books, 2016. Pages 71-90. This Book Chapter is brought to you for free and open access by the Political Science Department at Digital Commons @ Assumption University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Political Science Department Faculty Works by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Assumption University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Natural Rights and History: Hugo Grotius's Modern Translation of Aristotle Jeremy Seth Geddert Cicero writes in de Finibus that "nature never forgets its own primary prop­ erties." This leads him to inquire, "then how comes it that human nature alone abandons man?"1 If Hugo Grotius were alive today, he might wonder the same thing. Grotius's language of nature remains surprisingly enduring in contemporary discourse. Yet most students of political thought seem to have forgotten the man. This inattention is a notable change from the seventeenth through nineteenth centuries, during which one contemporary described Gro­ tius as "the greatest universal scholar since Aristotle."2 Grotius's fame began in 1598, when King Henry IV of France pronounced the fifteen-year-old prodigy as "the miracle of Holland." By his early twenties he became the Pensionary of Rotterdam, and by his early thirties he penned major works of history, literature, political philosophy, and theology.
    [Show full text]
  • The Enlightenment and Democratic Revolutions MAIN IDEA WHY IT MATTERS NOW TERMS & NAMES
    4 The Enlightenment and Democratic Revolutions MAIN IDEA WHY IT MATTERS NOW TERMS & NAMES REVOLUTION Enlightenment These revolutions and the • Enlightenment • representative ideas helped bring about the documents they produced have • social contract government American and French inspired other democratic • natural rights • federal system revolutions. movements. • separation of • United Nations powers SETTING THE STAGE The Renaissance continued to affect European thinking throughout the 17th century. The Renaissance emphasis on the individual and on expanding human potential were especially influential. At the same time, Europeans began to explore their physical world. They extended the boundaries of the known world in what came to be called the Age of Exploration. New ideas and discoveries had a great impact on Europeans’ understanding of themselves and the world. TAKING NOTES Enlightenment Thinkers and Ideas Outlining Use an outline During the 17th and 18th centuries, an intellectual movement called the to organize the main ideas and details. Enlightenment developed. Enlightenment thinkers tried to apply the principles of reason and the methods of science to all aspects of society. They built upon I. Enlightenmentg the long history of Western thought. Thinkers and Ideas The philosophers of ancient Greece had established the idea of natural laws A. that could be discovered by careful observation and reasoned inquiry. B. Christianity contributed the belief in the equality of all human beings. (This belief II. The Beggginnings of Democracy in America would later lead to the principle of equal rights in society.) During the Renaissance, thinkers had focused on worldly concerns. They criticized medieval philosophy A. for concentrating on questions that seemed unrelated to human conditions.
    [Show full text]
  • Algernon Sidney on Public Right
    University of Arkansas at Little Rock Law Review Volume 10 Issue 2 Article 3 1987 Algernon Sidney on Public Right Edward Dumbauld Follow this and additional works at: https://lawrepository.ualr.edu/lawreview Part of the European Law Commons, and the Legal History Commons Recommended Citation Edward Dumbauld, Algernon Sidney on Public Right, 10 U. ARK. LITTLE ROCK L. REV. 317 (1988). Available at: https://lawrepository.ualr.edu/lawreview/vol10/iss2/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Bowen Law Repository: Scholarship & Archives. It has been accepted for inclusion in University of Arkansas at Little Rock Law Review by an authorized editor of Bowen Law Repository: Scholarship & Archives. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ALGERNON SIDNEY ON PUBLIC RIGHT Hon. Edward Dumbauld* In response to criticisms that the Declaration of Independence lacked originality,' its author Thomas Jefferson explained that the political purpose and object of that document was: not to find out new principles, or new arguments, never before thought of, not merely to say things which had never been said before; but to place before mankind the common sense of the sub- ject, in terms so plain and firm as to command their assent, and to justify ourselves in the independent stand we are compelled to take. Neither aiming at originality of principle or sentiment, nor yet cop- ied from any particular and previous writing,' it was intended to be an expression of the American mind, and to give to that expression the proper tone and spirit called for by the occasion.
    [Show full text]
  • Democracy in the United States
    Democracy in the United States The United States is a representative democracy. This means that our government is elected by citizens. Here, citizens vote for their government officials. These officials represent the citizens’ ideas and concerns in government. Voting is one way to participate in our democracy. Citizens can also contact their officials when they want to support or change a law. Voting in an election and contacting our elected officials are two ways that Americans can participate in their democracy. Voting booth in Atascadero, California, in 2008. Photo by Ace Armstrong. Courtesy of the Polling Place Photo Project. Your Government and You H www.uscis.gov/citizenship 1 Becoming a U.S. Citizen Taking the Oath of Allegiance at a naturalization ceremony in Washington, D.C. Courtesy of USCIS. The process required to become a citizen is called naturalization. To become a U.S. citizen, you must meet legal requirements. You must complete an interview with a USCIS officer. You must also pass an English and Civics test. Then, you take the Oath of Allegiance. This means that you promise loyalty to the United States. When you become a U.S. citizen, you also make these promises: ★ give up loyalty to other countries ★ defend the Constitution and laws of the United States ★ obey the laws of the United States ★ serve in the U.S. military (if needed) ★ do important work for the nation (if needed) After you take the Oath of Allegiance, you are a U.S. citizen. 2 Your Government and You H www.uscis.gov/citizenship Rights and Responsibilities of Citizens Voting is one important right and responsibility of U.S.
    [Show full text]
  • Table of Contents
    Table of Contents Note for the Revised Edition 11 Introduction 13 emmeline besamusca and jaap verheul Neither Wooden Legs nor Wooden Shoes: Elusive Encounters with Dutchness 16 wiljan van den akker Society 1 Citizens, Coalitions, and the Crown 21 emmeline besamusca Queen Máxima: Enchanting the Monarchy 23 Binnenhof: Traditional Heart of a Modern Democracy 26 2 Politics between Accommodation and Commotion 33 ido de haan Pillarization: Pacification and Segregation 34 Pim Fortuyn: Libertarian Populist 39 3 Economy of the Polder 45 jan luiten van zanden Bulbs, Flowers, and Cheese: The Agricultural Face of an Urban Economy 45 Royal Dutch Shell: Corporate Legacy of Colonialism 49 4 Dilemmas of the Welfare State 57 lex heerma van voss Labor Productivity: Balancing Work and Leisure 58 Pensions: Well-Deserved and Well-Funded 63 5 Randstad Holland 69 ben de pater and rob van der vaart The Amsterdam Canal Ring: Urban Heritage of the Golden Age 70 The Port of Rotterdam: Logistical Hub of Europe 75 6 Distinctive within the Global Fold? 83 paul schnabel The Elfstedentocht: Beating the Forces of Nature 86 Sinterklaas: A Controversial Morality Tale 91 5 History 7 From the Periphery to the Center 97 marco mostert The Roman Limes: A Cultural Meeting Place 99 Hebban Olla Vogala: The Beginnings of Literature 105 8 The Golden Age 109 maarten prak The Tulip Bubble: Horticultural Speculation 111 William of Orange: Founding Father 113 9 A Tradition of Tolerance 121 wijnand mijnhardt Hugo Grotius: Founder of Enlightenment Thought 124 Baruch de Spinoza: Philosopher
    [Show full text]
  • One Hundred Years of Arrogance: Why 'Western' Liberalism Won't Save Latin America
    LSE Latin America and Caribbean Blog: One hundred years of arrogance: why ‘Western’ liberalism won’t save Latin America Page 1 of 4 One hundred years of arrogance: why ‘Western’ liberalism won’t save Latin America Liberalism is often seen as a Western gift to the world that became tragically warped on contact with less developed nations. But where once the region’s intellectuals themselves subscribed to this vision, more recent scholarship shows that Latin American countries charted their own courses towards “liberal” rights and constitutions. Despite even the recent ravages of neoliberalism, the key tenets and institutions of liberalism remain deeply popular, write Catherine Andrews (CIDE, Mexico) and Ariadna Acevedo Rodrigo (Cinvestav, Mexico). • Disponible también en español (versión extendida) In a recent article musing on the state of governance in Latin America, The Economist‘s columnist Bello asks himself whether “liberal ideas suffer in the region because they are imported”. He thinks so, but he nonetheless encourages Latin Americans to persist with them because they will bring “equality of opportunity” and “better public services at an affordable cost”. In a single stroke, Bello resolves all of liberalism’s contradictions and limitations by absolving it of blame for failing in Latin America. It is not liberalism – an “imported” idea – but rather its faulty application, which is in crisis. He conveniently forgets that the 2008 financial crisis left liberalism in crisis everywhere. He also overlooks at least two decades of research
    [Show full text]
  • Holland and the Rise of Political Economy in Seventeenth-Century Europe
    Journal of Interdisciplinary History, xl:2 (Autumn, 2009), 215–238. ACCOUNTING FOR GOVERNMENT Jacob Soll Accounting for Government: Holland and the Rise of Political Economy in Seventeenth-Century Europe The Dutch may ascribe their present grandeur to the virtue and frugality of their ancestors as they please, but what made that contemptible spot of the earth so considerable among the powers of Europe has been their political wisdom in postponing everything to merchandise and navigation [and] the unlimited liberty of conscience enjoyed among them. —Bernard de Mandeville, The Fable of the Bees (1714) In the Instructions for the Dauphin (1665), Louis XIV set out a train- ing course for his son. Whereas humanists and great ministers had cited the ancients, Louis cited none. Ever focused on the royal moi, he described how he overcame the troubles of the civil war of the Fronde, noble power, and ªscal problems. This was a modern handbook for a new kind of politics. Notably, Louis exhorted his son never to trust a prime minister, except in questions of ªnance, for which kings needed experts. Sounding like a Dutch stadtholder, Louis explained, “I took the precaution of assigning Colbert . with the title of Intendant, a man in whom I had the highest conªdence, because I knew that he was very dedicated, intelli- gent, and honest; and I have entrusted him then with keeping the register of funds that I have described to you.”1 Jean-Baptiste-Colbert (1619–1683), who had a merchant background, wrote the sections of the Instructions that pertained to ªnance. He advised the young prince to master ªnance through the handling of account books and the “disposition of registers” Jacob Soll is Associate Professor of History, Rutgers University, Camden.
    [Show full text]
  • Montesquieu, Methodological Pluralism and Comparative Constitutional Law 481
    Montesquieu, Methodological Pluralism and Comparative Constitutional Law 481 Montesquieu, Methodological Pluralism and Comparative Constitutional Law Lorenzo Zucca* Montesquieu’s lessons for modern comparative constitutional law – The Spirit of the Laws – The textual bias of normative constitutionalism – The utility of other disci- plines to comparative constitutional law – Constitutions as more than mere texts Introduction Modern comparative constitutional law begins in Esfahan, the old capital of Iran, in a majestic seraglio, where some of the most beautiful women are held captive. Uzbek, an Iranian prince, set out for a trip to Europe. He travels to Qom, the holy city, then to Tabriz. He stops for a while in Turkey and embarks in Smyrna on the way to Livorno. Then he quickly arrives in Paris, the centre of modern Europe. From there, Uzbek and Rica, a close friend, report back on European laws, habits and culture from the perspective of two Persian observers. There are two impor- tant, albeit conflicting, insights in Montesquieu’s Persian Letters. First, we can im- prove the understanding of our society by adopting an external viewpoint. In this case, Montesquieu wears the clothes of two Persian visitors, Uzbek and Rica. Through this fiction, he can critically report on a number of interesting aspects of contemporary France. Montesquieu stresses a second point: self-understanding through comparison is limited, as we always tend to excuse our own habits more than we criticise them. Uzbek, for example, sees many weaknesses in the French political and cultural system, but tends to justify his position of slave owner and incarcerator of women back home.
    [Show full text]
  • Park Assistant Professor of History, Sam Houston State University
    Benjamin E. Park Assistant Professor of History, Sam Houston State University Mailing Address: Contact Information: Department of History email: [email protected] Box 2239 phone: (505) 573-0509 Sam Houston State University website: benjaminepark.com Huntsville, TX 77341 twitter: @BenjaminEPark EDUCATION 2014 Ph.D., History, University of Cambridge 2011 M.Phil., Political Thought and Intellectual History, University of Cambridge -with distinction 2010 M.Sc., Historical Theology, University of Edinburgh -with distinction 2009 B.A., English and History, Brigham Young University RESEARCH INTERESTS 18th and 19th Century US history, intersections of culture with religion and politics, intellectual history, history of gender, religious studies, slavery and antislavery, Atlantic history. ACADEMIC APPOINTMENTS 2016- Assistant Professor of History, Sam Houston State University HIST 1301: United States History to 1876 HIST 3360: American Religious History HIST 3377: America in Mid-Passage, 1773-1876 HIST 3378: Emergence of Modern America, 1877-1945 HIST 5371: Revolutionary America (Grad Seminar) HIST 5378: American Cultural and Religious History (Grad Seminar) 2014-2016 Kinder Postdoctoral Fellow, Department of History, University of Missouri HIST 1100: United States History to The Civil War HIST 4000: The Age of Jefferson HIST 4004: 18th Century Revolutions: America, France, Haiti HIST 4972: Religion and Politics in American History 2012-2014 Lecturer and Supervisor, Faculty of History, University of Cambridge Paper 22: American History through 1865 PUBLICATIONS Books American Nationalisms: Imagining Union in the Age of Revolutions, 1783-1833 (Cambridge University Press, January 2018). Benjamin Park C.V. Peer-Reviewed Articles “The Angel of Nullification: Imagining Disunion in an Era Before Secession,” Journal of the Early Republic 37:3 (Fall 2017): 507-536.
    [Show full text]
  • H-France Review Volume 4 (2004) Page 397
    H-France Review Volume 4 (2004) Page 397 H-France Review Vol. 4 (November 2004), No. 113 Alan S. Kahan, Liberalism in Nineteenth-Century Europe: The Political Culture of Limited Suffrage. Basingstoke, Hampshire, and New York, N.Y: Palgrave Macmillan, 2003. vii + 239 pp. Notes, works cited, and index. $69.95 US (hb). ISBN 1-4039-1174-6. Review by Jean Elisabeth Pedersen, Eastman School of Music, University of Rochester. Alan Kahan’s new book on liberalism in nineteenth-century Europe represents a thoughtful attempt to define the core characteristics of that rich and complex intellectual tradition by focusing on liberals’ parliamentary debates over how to institute various forms of limited suffrage in England, France, and the German states before and after unification in the period from 1830 to 1885. Kahan’s earlier work has illuminated the intellectual biographies of Jacob Burckhardt, John Stuart Mill, and, especially, Alexis de Tocqueville; his new project now explores the political and intellectual history of the more general national movements in which these three figures played such important parts.[1] Kahan initially presents nineteenth-century liberals in familiar terms as “both the confident heirs of Voltaire and the frightened successors of Robespierre” (p. 1), or, in other words, as historical figures who hoped to sponsor progressive reform without provoking either radical revolution or conservative reaction. Unlike those historians, social theorists, and political activists who have defined liberals in economic terms by focusing on their commitment to the preservation of private property, however, Kahan seeks to define liberals in political terms by focusing instead on their commitment to what he calls “the discourse of capacity” (p.
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Views of Market Society
    ANRV316-SO33-14 ARI 31 May 2007 12:29 Moral Views of Market Society Marion Fourcade1 and Kieran Healy2 1Department of Sociology, University of California, Berkeley, California 94720-1980; email: [email protected] 2Department of Sociology, University of Arizona, Tucson, Arizona 85721; email: [email protected] Annu. Rev. Sociol. 2007. 33:285–311 Key Words First published online as a Review in Advance on markets, capitalism, moral order, culture, performativity, April 5, 2007 governmentality The Annual Review of Sociology is online at http://soc.annualreviews.org Abstract This article’s doi: Upon what kind of moral order does capitalism rest? Conversely, by University of California - Berkeley on 08/30/07. For personal use only. 10.1146/annurev.soc.33.040406.131642 does the market give rise to a distinctive set of beliefs, habits, and Annu. Rev. Sociol. 2007.33:285-311. Downloaded from arjournals.annualreviews.org Copyright c 2007 by Annual Reviews. social bonds? These questions are certainly as old as social science All rights reserved itself. In this review, we evaluate how today’s scholarship approaches 0360-0572/07/0811-0285$20.00 the relationship between markets and the moral order. We begin with Hirschman’s characterization of the three rival views of the market as civilizing, destructive, or feeble in its effects on society. We review recent work at the intersection of sociology, economics, and political economy and show that these views persist both as theories of market society and moral arguments about it. We then argue that a fourth view, which we call moralized markets, has become increasingly prominent in economic sociology.
    [Show full text]