Aristotle on the Motion of Projectiles: a Reconsideration

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Aristotle on the Motion of Projectiles: a Reconsideration Ancient Philosophy 38 (2018) ©Mathesis Publications 1 Aristotle on the Motion of Projectiles: A Reconsideration Pantelis Golitsis Aristotle is still credited in several studies dealing mostly with medieval sci - ence with the so-called theory of antiperistasis , by which he allegedly explained the motion of the projectiles. 1 Nonetheless, antiperistasis is the first of two theo - ries to which Aristotle refers with regard to the motion of the projectiles, pass - ingly in Physics iv 8 and more amply in Physics viii 10, where it is actually rejected in favour of the second theory. Several commentators fail to notice the strict analogy between the two passages and wrongly take Aristotle as expound - ing and endorsing just one theory in Physics viii 10, which would be (a refined version of) the theory of antiperistasis . As a result, Aristotle’s account of forced motion has been repeatedly misunderstood. 2 As is well known, according to the Stagirite, the natural elements that consti - tute the universe are either heavy or light or weightless; the heavy elements, i.e., earth and water, naturally move towards the centre, the light elements, i.e., air and fire, naturally move away from the centre, and the weightless element, i.e., the ether that occupies the supralunary region of the universe, naturally moves around the centre. 3 The problem with the projectiles, which are heavy by nature (φύσει ), was not that they do not immediately move downwards, since this was explained as the result of a forced, unnatural ( βίαιος or παρὰ φύσιν) motion pro - vided by the thrower’s hand. The real problem was that the projectile continued to move for some time, while there was no mover to move it. Here is how a histo - rian of science presents the difficulty that Aristotle had to face: Projectile motion posed a…problem for Aristotle. In the case of a thrown object, the force was provided by the hand of the thrower as long as the object was in contact with the hand. But one needed an explanation of why the object continued to move once it had left the thrower’s hand. Aristotle concluded that the medium through which the projectile moved provided the force that kept it moving. This occurred either by antiperis - tasis (replacement), in which the medium rushes around the 1 See, for instance, Gabrovsky 2015, 40: ‘There were many problems with Aristotle’s theory of antiperistasis : in Aristotle’s argument a stone that is thrown moves the air, and the air propels the stone as it fills in the vacuum left behind.’ 2 Various accounts of medieval science treat the theory of antiperistasis as a standard part of a general Aristotelian theory of motion; see, e.g., Grant 1974, 275-280. Nevertheless, medieval thinkers themselves, such as Thomas Aquinas and Jean Buridan, clearly distinguished between the two theo - ries in both passages; cf. Maggiòlo 1965, §1163; Benoît 1996, IV, q. 2, 21-28. 3 For a concise presentation of this theory, see Aristotle On the Heavens i 3. 2 body to prevent the formation of a void or vacuum and pushed the body from behind, or by the medium itself having acquired the power to be a mover from the original projector… The medium itself does not have to move, but rather possesses the power to move something else. This power is, however, imper - fectly transmitted from one layer of the medium to the next and gradually dies away. (Franklin 1998, 251) I would like to revisit the two relevant Aristotelian passages and argue three things: (i) that Aristotle was not heavily concerned by the theory of antiperistasis as such; (ii) that he rejected this theory and proposed a different explanation of the motion of the projectiles, which corresponds to the second of the two expla - nations described above by Allan Franklin but is not fully grasped in his account; and (iii) that Aristotle’s explanation was a preliminary excursus from a larger argument, which sought to establish that there is an eternally continuous motion in the universe, of one thing and due to one thing, namely, the diurnal motion of the outer celestial sphere, a motion that is eternally generated by the First Unmoved Mover. Franklin, presumably following W.D. Ross, correctly specifies that the theory of antiperistasis was in reality not Aristotelian but probably Platonic in origin. 4 Plato does not use this specific term but he explains nonetheless the mechanics of respiration in Timaeus 79a-e as a round pushing ( περιωθεῖν) of air exhaled and inhaled, which goes on without interruption because there can be no void left in the universe. 5 Plato also invites his readers to explain by a similar reasoning, among other phenomena, the motion of the projectiles. 6 It was the Platonist Plutarch (2nd cent. AD) who first undertook the task to expand the teaching of the Timaeus by describing the kind of round motion that keeps the motion of the projectiles, a round motion that he precisely calls antiperistasis : In what sense does Plato say [in the Timaeus ] that, because there is void nowhere, the antiperistasis of motion is the cause of what happens in the case of medical-cupping instruments and in that of swallowing and of weights that are thrown and of flowing waters and of thunderbolts and of the apparent attrac - 4 See Ross 1936, 726. Other scholars trace the origins of the theory back to Empedocles, who also argued from the mutual replacement of bodies that there can be no void in the universe (cf. DK 31 A5); see Taylor 1934, 558, and Barnes 1982, 399-401. I believe, however, that what we see in Empedocles is not an antecedent of the specific theory of antiperistasis but a more general case of antimetastasis (see below). Although pseudo-Aristotle ( MXG 976b22-29 = DK 31 A5) uses the verb περιίστασθαι to explain Empedocles’ doctrine, other doxographers (see DK 31 A35) refer to it more properly with such verbs as μεταλαμβάνειν and ἀντιπαραχωρεῖν, which have the more general mean - ing of changing places (and not of round displacement). 5 See Opsomer 1999. Opsomer rightly speaks of the Platonic ‘concept of periôsis ’. Note, how - ever, that this word, too, does not appear as a technical term in Plato but in Aristotle; cf. Aristotle, On Respiration 472b6: ἡ δ᾽ ἐν τῷ Τιμαίῳ γεγραμμένη περίωσις… 6 Plato, Timaeus 80a1-2: καὶ τὰ τῆς καταπόσεως τά τε τῶν ῥιπτουμένων [sc . αἴτια] , ὅσα ἀφεθέ - ντα μετέωρα καὶ ὅσα ἐπὶ γῆς φέρεται, ταύτῃ διωκτέον. 3 tion to amber and the lodestone and of the consonances of sounds? …Weights that are thrown cleave the air and separate it because of the impact with which they have fallen upon it; and the air because of its nature always to seek out and fill up the space left empty flows around behind and follows along with the object discharged , helping to accelerate its motion. 7 The theory of antiperistasis , therefore, was not considered to be Aristotelian in antiquity. The word antiperistasis , however, is first found in Aristotle, who also uses the related term antimetastasis . Most scholars tend to treat the two terms as synonymous but they are not (see Barnes 1982, 400). On the one hand, antimetastasis relates to the impossibility of having any void left in the universe, since when a body leaves its place, another body immediately occupies the place left. Aristotle uses it as an endoxon in order to establish the existence of place in Physics iv .8 To take Aristotle’s example: when I pour water from a vessel into a bowl, the vessel does not remain void but is instantaneously filled with air; thus, air and water change places ( ἀντιμεθίστανται ). On the other hand, antiperistasis occurs twice in Aristotle’s Physics and is used to refer not to a mere interchange of bodies, which could happen in any direction, but to a round displacement of bodies until the last displaced body occupies the place of the first displaced body. 9 (This is more or less equivalent to the action of periôthein , with which Plato explains the process of respiration: the air, which is heated in the body and thus exhaled, pushes around several portions of air that are outside the body until a freshly inhaled air occupies inside the body the place left by the exhaled air.) Aristotle uses the term antiperistasis in a context that relates specifically to the motion of the projectiles: Moreover, the projectiles move when the thrower is not in con - tact with them either (i) because of antiperistasis , as some say, or (ii) because the air pushed [by the thrower] pushes [the air] 10 7 Plutarch, Platonicae Quaestiones 1004d9-1005a: Πῶς ποτέ φησιν ὁ Πλάτων τὴν ἀντιπερίστα - σιν τῆς κινήσεως διὰ τὸ μηδαμοῦ κενὸν ὑπάρχειν αἰτίαν εἶναι τῶν περὶ τὰς ἰατρικὰς σικύας παθημά - των, καὶ τῶν περὶ τὴν κατάποσιν καὶ τὰ ῥιπτούμενα βάρη καὶ τὰ τῶν ὑδάτων ῥεύματα καὶ κεραυνούς, τήν τε φαινομένην πρὸς ἥλεκτρα καὶ τὴν λίθον τὴν Ἡρακλείαν ὁλκην τάς τε τῶν φθόγγων συμφω - νίας; …Τὰ δὲ ῥιπτούμενα βάρη τὸν ἀέρα σχίζει μετὰ πληγῆς ἐμπεσόντα καὶ διίστησιν· ὁ δὲ περιρ - ρέων ὀπίσω, τῷ φύσιν ἔχειν ἀεὶ τὴν ἐρημουμένην χώραν διώκειν καὶ ἀναπληροῦν συνέπεται τῷ ἀφιεμένῳ τὴν κίνησιν συνεπιταχύνων . Cherniss 1976, 63 trans., which renders antiperistasis by ‘cyclical replacement’. 8 Cf. Phys . iv 1.208b1-8: ὅτι μὲν οὖν ἔστιν ὁ τόπος, δοκεῖ δῆλον εἶναι ἐκ τῆς ἀντιμεταστάσεως· ὅπου γὰρ ἔστι νῦν ὕδωρ, ἐνταῦθα ἐξελθόντος ὥσπερ ἐξ ἀγγείου πάλιν ἀὴρ ἔνεστιν, ὁτὲ δὲ τὸν αὐτὸν τόπον τοῦτον ἄλλο τι τῶν σωμάτων κατέχει· τοῦτο δὴ τῶν ἐγγιγνομένων καὶ μεταβαλλόντων ἕτερον πάντων εἶναι δοκεῖ· ἐν ᾧ γὰρ ἀὴρ ἔστι νῦν, ὕδωρ ἐν τούτῳ πρότερον ἦν, ὥστε δῆλον ὡς ἦν ὁ τόπος τι καὶ ἡ χώρα ἕτερον ἀμφοῖν, εἰς ἣν καὶ ἐξ ἧς μετέβαλον.
Recommended publications
  • The Philosophy of Physics
    The Philosophy of Physics ROBERTO TORRETTI University of Chile PUBLISHED BY THE PRESS SYNDICATE OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CAMBRIDGE The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 2RU, UK www.cup.cam.ac.uk 40 West 20th Street, New York, NY 10011-4211, USA www.cup.org 10 Stamford Road, Oakleigh, Melbourne 3166, Australia Ruiz de Alarcón 13, 28014, Madrid, Spain © Roberto Torretti 1999 This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published 1999 Printed in the United States of America Typeface Sabon 10.25/13 pt. System QuarkXPress [BTS] A catalog record for this book is available from the British Library. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data is available. 0 521 56259 7 hardback 0 521 56571 5 paperback Contents Preface xiii 1 The Transformation of Natural Philosophy in the Seventeenth Century 1 1.1 Mathematics and Experiment 2 1.2 Aristotelian Principles 8 1.3 Modern Matter 13 1.4 Galileo on Motion 20 1.5 Modeling and Measuring 30 1.5.1 Huygens and the Laws of Collision 30 1.5.2 Leibniz and the Conservation of “Force” 33 1.5.3 Rømer and the Speed of Light 36 2 Newton 41 2.1 Mass and Force 42 2.2 Space and Time 50 2.3 Universal Gravitation 57 2.4 Rules of Philosophy 69 2.5 Newtonian Science 75 2.5.1 The Cause of Gravity 75 2.5.2 Central Forces 80 2.5.3 Analytical
    [Show full text]
  • A Philosophical and Historical Analysis of Cosmology from Copernicus to Newton
    University of Central Florida STARS Electronic Theses and Dissertations, 2004-2019 2017 Scientific transformations: a philosophical and historical analysis of cosmology from Copernicus to Newton Manuel-Albert Castillo University of Central Florida Part of the History of Science, Technology, and Medicine Commons Find similar works at: https://stars.library.ucf.edu/etd University of Central Florida Libraries http://library.ucf.edu This Masters Thesis (Open Access) is brought to you for free and open access by STARS. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations, 2004-2019 by an authorized administrator of STARS. For more information, please contact [email protected]. STARS Citation Castillo, Manuel-Albert, "Scientific transformations: a philosophical and historical analysis of cosmology from Copernicus to Newton" (2017). Electronic Theses and Dissertations, 2004-2019. 5694. https://stars.library.ucf.edu/etd/5694 SCIENTIFIC TRANSFORMATIONS: A PHILOSOPHICAL AND HISTORICAL ANALYSIS OF COSMOLOGY FROM COPERNICUS TO NEWTON by MANUEL-ALBERT F. CASTILLO A.A., Valencia College, 2013 B.A., University of Central Florida, 2015 A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in the department of Interdisciplinary Studies in the College of Graduate Studies at the University of Central Florida Orlando, Florida Fall Term 2017 Major Professor: Donald E. Jones ©2017 Manuel-Albert F. Castillo ii ABSTRACT The purpose of this thesis is to show a transformation around the scientific revolution from the sixteenth to seventeenth centuries against a Whig approach in which it still lingers in the history of science. I find the transformations of modern science through the cosmological models of Nicholas Copernicus, Johannes Kepler, Galileo Galilei and Isaac Newton.
    [Show full text]
  • UC Davis UC Davis Previously Published Works
    UC Davis UC Davis Previously Published Works Title The anthropology of incommensurability Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/3vx742f4 Journal Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 21(2) ISSN 0039-3681 Author Biagioli, M Publication Date 1990 DOI 10.1016/0039-3681(90)90022-Z Peer reviewed eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California MARIO BIAGIOLP’ THE ANTHROPOLOGY OF INCOMMENSURABILITY I. Incommensurability and Sterility SINCE IT entered the discourse of history and philosophy of science with Feyerabend’s “Explanation, Reduction, and Empiricism” and Kuhn’s The Structure of Scient$c Revolutions, the notion of incommensurability has problematized the debate on processes of theory-choice.’ According to Kuhn, two scientific paradigms competing for the explanation of roughly the same set of natural phenomena may not share a global linguistic common denominator. As a result, the possibility of scientific communication and dialogue cannot be taken for granted and the process of theory choice can no longer be reduced to the simple picture presented, for example, by the logical empiricists. By analyzing the dialogue (or rather the lack of it) between Galileo and the Tuscan Aristotelians during the debate on buoyancy in 1611-1613, I want to argue that incommensurability between competing paradigms is not just an unfortunate problem of linguistic communication, but it plays an important role in the process of scientific change and paradigm-speciation. The breakdown of communication during the
    [Show full text]
  • 6 X 10.5 Long Title.P65
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-80279-6 - God and Reason in the Middle Ages Edward Grant Index More information INDEX Page numbers cited directly after a semicolon following a final text subentry refer to relatively minor mentions in the text of the main entry. Abelard, Peter: application of logic to theology, Questions on Generation and Corruption, 186; 57–9; importance of, 48; opposed reason to Questions on the Physics, 186, 187, 190–1; 153, authority, 357; Sic et Non, 60, 62, 79; 26, 46, 170, 275nn, 276nn 50, 51, 62, 63, 64, 73, 100, 144, 333, 337 Albertus Magnus: and the senses, 160; as accidents: lacking a subject, 252; 183 theologian-natural philosopher, 191; few acoustics, 163 mentions of God, 194–5; on God’s absolute Adalberon of Laon, 47 power, 193; on other worlds, 193; on relations Adelard of Bath: as translator, 69; attitude toward between natural philosophy and theology, authority and reason, 69–72; natural 192–5; Commentary on De caelo, 192, 193, 194; philosophy of, 69–72; opposed reason to Commentary on the Physics, 192, 194; 104, 161, authority, 357; Natural Questions, 69, 84; 73, 74 179, 180, 196, 344 Age of Enlightenment: based on seventeenth- Albigenses, 336 century thought, 284 Albucasis, 109 Age of Faith: rather than Age of Reason, 351; 335 Alexander of Aphrodisias, 86 Age of Reason: and Middle Ages, 15, 16, 285; Alexander of Hales, 207, 254nn arrived at religion based on reason, 289; al-Farghani, see Alfraganus began in Middle Ages, 8–9, 289, 290; could Alfraganus, 341 not have occurred without Middle Ages, 292;
    [Show full text]
  • Overturning the Paradigm of Identity with Gilles Deleuze's Differential
    A Thesis entitled Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy Dr. Ammon Allred, Committee Chair Dr. Benjamin Grazzini, Committee Member Dr. Benjamin Pryor, Committee Member Dr. Patricia R. Komuniecki, Dean College of Graduate Studies The University of Toledo May 2014 An Abstract of Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy The University of Toledo May 2014 Taking Gilles Deleuze to be a philosopher who is most concerned with articulating a ‘philosophy of difference’, Deleuze’s thought represents a fundamental shift in the history of philosophy, a shift which asserts ontological difference as independent of any prior ontological identity, even going as far as suggesting that identity is only possible when grounded by difference. Deleuze reconstructs a ‘minor’ history of philosophy, mobilizing thinkers from Spinoza and Nietzsche to Duns Scotus and Bergson, in his attempt to assert that philosophy has always been, underneath its canonical manifestations, a project concerned with ontology, and that ontological difference deserves the kind of philosophical attention, and privilege, which ontological identity has been given since Aristotle.
    [Show full text]
  • The Metaphysics of Light in the Hexaemeral Literature
    The Metaphysics of Light in the Hexaemeral Literature From Philo of Alexandria to Ambrose of Milan I S I D O R O S C H A R A L A M P O S K A T S O S Pembroke College December 2018 This dissertation is submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy D e c l a r a t i o n This dissertation is the result of my own work and includes nothing which is the outcome of work done in collaboration except as declared in the Acknowledgements and specified in the text. It is not substantially the same as any that I have submitted, or, is being concurrently submitted for a degree or diploma or other qualification at the University of Cambridge or any other University or similar institution except as declared in the Acknowledgements and specified in the text. I further state that no substantial part of my dissertation has already been submitted, or, is being concurrently submitted for any such degree, diploma or other qualification at the University of Cambridge or any other University or similar institution except as declared in the Acknowledgements and specified in the text. It does not exceed the prescribed word limit. Isidoros Charalampos Katsos Pembroke College CB2 1RF [email protected] The Metaphysics of Light in the Hexaemeral Literature From Philo of Alexandria to Ambrose of Milan Summary This study investigates the concept of light in the early Jewish-Christian exegesis of the biblical creation narrative (Gen. 1, so-called ‘hexaemeron’). The study argues that the early hexaemeral exegetes theorised light from a dual perspective, both physical and metaphysical.
    [Show full text]
  • Cosmology, Extraterrestrial Life, and the Development and Character Of
    COSMOLOGY, EXTRATERRESTRIAL LIFE, AND THE DEVELOPMENT AND CHARACTER OF WESTERN EUROPEAN THOUGHT IN THE SEVENTEENTH AND EIGHTEENTH CENTURIES Emily Simpson, B.A. Thesis Prepared for the Degree of MASTER OF ARTS UNIVERSITY OF NORTH TEXAS August 2011 APPROVED: Marilyn Morris, Major Professor Laura Stern, Committee Member Michael Leggiere, Committee Member Richard B. McCaslin, Chair of the Department of History James D. Meernik, Acting Dean of the Toulouse Graduate School Simpson, Emily. Cosmology, Extraterrestrial Life, and the Development and Character of Western European Thought in the Seventeenth and Eighteenth Centuries. Master of Arts (History), August 2011, 108 pp., 132 titles. Cosmology, as an all-encompassing theoretical construction of universal reality, serves as one of the best indicators for a variety of philosophical, scientific, and cultural values. Within any cosmological system, the question of extraterrestrial life is an important element. Mere existence or nonexistence, however, only exposes a small portion of the ideological significance behind the contemplation of life outside of earth. The manners by which both believers and disbelievers justify their opinions and the ways they characterize other worlds and their inhabitants show much more about the particular ideas behind such decisions and the general climate of thought surrounding those who consider the topic. By exploring both physical and abstract structures of the universe, and specifically concepts on the plurality of worlds and extraterrestrial life, Western European thought in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries reveals not an era of pure advancement and modernization, but as a time of both tradition and change. Copyright 2011 by Emily Simpson ii TABLE OF CONTENTS CHAPTERS Page 1 INTRODUCTION……………………………………………………………………………1 2 THE POSITION AND QUALITIES OF EARTH, PHYSICAL AND METAPHYSICAL 154 3 MAN’S PLACE IN THE COSMOS ..................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Bajodah Abdulrahman.Pdf
    CEU eTD Collection ABSTRACT The aim of my inquiry is to examine Ikhwan al-Safa’s (“Brethren of Purity”) creationist arguments against the Aristotelian doctrine of the world’s eternity. Arguing for creationism, Ikhwan al-Safa employ the Neoplatonic emanation theory as it is developed in their tenth- century Arabic encyclopedia. However, some historians have claimed that Ikhwan al-Safa’s emanation theory is a veiled attack on creationism that embraces the Aristotelian doctrine of the world’s eternity. Ikhwan al-Safa’s philosophical project is thus characterized as a project that aims either to reconcile or propagate a presupposed conflict between philosophy and religion, expressed for instance in this tension between Aristotelianism and creationism. This characterization allegedly lurks behind opposing historical testimonies regarding Ikhwan al- Safa’s identity and doctrine which I claim is contemporarily reproduced in similar terms with Ikhwan al-Safa’s scholarship. While both historical and contemporary characterizations tempt a double reading approach to Ikhwan al-Safa’s philosophy, I consider their philosophical project within the tradition of early Arabic philosophy, whose enterprise can be characterized as a natural theology project which does not presuppose a conflict between philosophy and religion. While Ikhwan al-Safa identify the philosophical tension between creationism and the world’s eternity doctrine, I demonstrate that Ikhwan al-Safa use emanation theory rather to substantiate their creationist arguments in light of their overall identification of creation with emanation. Consequently, Ikhwan al-Safa’s reception of Aristotelian and Neoplatonic sources should be recognized as a particular CEU eTD Collection philosophical synthesis of both with creationism, for they did not merely transmit these sources, but assimilated them into the Islamic context of 10th century Iraq.
    [Show full text]
  • God's Life-Generating Power and Its Transmission in Aristotle's Biology
    1 God’s Life-Generating Power and Its Transmission in Aristotle’s Biology and Cosmology Is it possible that Aristotle presented three very different phases in his philoso- phy and that only one of these was scientifically important? Such was Werner Jaeger’s claim in 1923, and still there is no alternative theory. Is it likely that, during his lectures in the Peripatos, Aristotle talked about a vital pneuma connected with the soul as the principle of life, but that pneuma plays no role in his seminal work On the Soul? Is it conceivable that he called God the “Great Leader” of the cosmos, but saw no divine governance in Nature? These critical questions about the standard theory on Aristotle have spurred the author of this book to develop a perspective on Aristotle’s philosophy that breaks with the accepted view. A crucial part is assigned to pneuma as the vital principle in all that lives. Pneuma is the fine-material carrier of all psychic functions and is governed by the soul as entelechy. The soul is the principle that controls the activity of pneuma in a goal-oriented way (oriented, that is, to the form of the living being). The entelechy is a cognitive principle that acts on the vital pneuma and is active from the very beginning of life, as a kind of automatic pilot. In human beings, however, the entelechy can also be “awakened” to intellectual- ity. All entelechies of living beings, including those of the stars and planets, are actuated by the Power that proceeds inexhaustibly from the divine, tran- scendent Intellect.
    [Show full text]
  • Erich Trapp / Sonja Schönauer (Hg.)
    Super alta perennis Studien zur Wirkung der Klassischen Antike Band 4 Herausgegeben von Uwe Baumann, Marc Laureys und Winfried Schmitz Erich Trapp / Sonja Schönauer (Hg.) Lexicologica Byzantina Beiträge zum Kolloquium zur byzantinischen Lexikographie (Bonn, 13.–15. Juli 2007) V&R unipress Bonn University Press Bibliografische Information der Deutschen Nationalbibliothek Die Deutsche Nationalbibliothek verzeichnet diese Publikation in der Deutschen Nationalbibliografie; detaillierte bibliografische Daten sind im Internet über http://dnb.d-nb.de abrufbar. ISBN 978-3-89971- 484-5 Veröffentlichungen der Bonn University Press erscheinen im Verlag V&R unipress GmbH. © 2008, V&R unipress in Göttingen / www.vr-unipress.de Alle Rechte vorbehalten. Das Werk und seine Teile sind urheberrechtlich geschützt. Jede Verwertung in anderen als den gesetzlich zugelassenen Fällen bedarf der vorherigen schriftlichen Einwilligung des Verlages. Hinweis zu § 52a UrhG: Weder das Werk noch seine Teile dürfen ohne vorherige schriftliche Einwilligung des Verlages öffentlich zugänglich gemacht werden. Dies gilt auch bei einer entsprechenden Nutzung für Lehr- und Unterrichtszwecke. Printed in Germany. Titelbild: Photios. In: http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Image:StPhotios.jpg Gedruckt auf alterungsbeständigem Papier. Inhalt VORWORT........................................................................................................ 7 PROGRAMM DES KOLLOQUIUMS ZUR BYZANTINISCHEN LEXIKOGRAPHIE........ 9 ABKÜRZUNGEN.............................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Konya/TÜRKĠYE TURAN-SAM 10
    TURAN-SAM * YIL: 2011 * CĠLT: 3 * SAYI: 11 * YAZ 2011 TURAN STRATEJĠK ARAġTIRMALAR MERKEZĠ DERGĠSĠ www.turansam.org (2) GENERAL ONTOLOGIC AND AXIOLOGIC ASPECTS OF HUMAN BEING Zahra HASSANI34 ABSTRACT Due to peripatetic school representatives human being is consisting of matter and form (that is to say spirit). From this reason he belongs to moral world and the matter in the formal world. Due to this his place and motion in the existence hierarchy is two-sided. As if, he was born two times: from the unique to plurality. Mashai school representatives think the mystery of this is not in matter, is in the spirit of human being. In thanks to of its character he is higher from other beings live in the world. He is well-wisher, clever, wisdom and kind. He is the Khalif of God in the world, that is to say human being is new existed as structural. That same character is consist of intelligence and sense and consciousness. Keywords: mashaism; human; existance; God; necessary being. Generally, for Eastern peripatetic school is characterized the structural commentary of the existence and the attitude to the world from different consciousness levels as total. They showed that The God stays in a high stage of the existence. It would be noted in contact with this; the mashshaists give specifically mean to the God idea, and characterized it as commonest and most abstract and pure philosophical notion. Also in Middle Asia, or Azerbaijan`s creative God conception was realized Platonist mean Allah-rifah, Allah-vahdat (rifah - prosperty; Vahdat - oneness), on the other side, Aristotelian God and Idea mean [1, 55-56].
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy 203: History of Modern Western Philosophy Hamilton College Spring 2016 Russell Marcus
    Philosophy 203: History of Modern Western Philosophy Hamilton College Spring 2016 Russell Marcus Notes on Unit #2: Monism (Hobbes and Spinoza) §I. Monism: An Introduction I.1. Monism and the Problem of Interaction Our second unit consists of readings from the master works of two monists: Thomas Hobbes and Baruch (Benedict) Spinoza. Monism is motivated largely by the problem of interaction in the theory of mind. The problem of interaction is to describe how our bodies and minds could interact, if they are indeed, as Descartes argues, two independent substances. Our bodies affect our minds; our minds affect our bodies. If they are independent substances, it is hard to see how they could do so. Gilbert Ryle, defending behaviorism about the mind in the twentieth century, accused Descartes of having to rely on “theoretical shuttlecocks” to transfer information from one domain to the other. Or, to put it in a Hamilton-relevant way: Why does the mind get drunk when the body does the drinking? To some people, the problem of interaction for a substance dualist like Descartes appears intractable. In order to focus the question, Descartes posits that interactions between the mind and body take place in one particular place in the human body, the seat of the soul. Descartes located the seat of the soul in the pineal gland. Here is a copy of a letter Descartes wrote about the pineal gland. Descartes’s view that the pineal gland is the location where the soul interacts with the body does not solve the problem of interaction; it merely locates the problem.
    [Show full text]