MAT 102 - Discrete Mathematics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

MAT 102 - Discrete Mathematics RHODES UNIVERSITY Grahamstown 6140, South Africa Lecture Notes CCR MAT 102 - Discrete Mathematics Claudiu C. Remsing DEPT. of MATHEMATICS (Pure and Applied) 2005 Mathematics is not about calculations but about ideas. [...] Calculations are merely a means to an end. [...] Not all ideas are mathematics; but all good mathematics must contain an idea. [...] There are [...] at least five distinct sources of mathematical ideas. They are number, shape, arrangement, movement, and chance. [...] The driving force of mathematics is problems. [...] Another important source of mathematical inspiration is examples. Ian Stewart It is not easy to say what mathematics is, but “I know it when I see it” is the most likely response of anyone to whom this question is put. The most striking thing about mathematics is that it is very different to science, and this compounds the problem of why it should be found so useful in describing and predicting how the Universe works. Whereas science is like a long text that is constantly being redrafted, updated, and edited, mathematics is entirely cumu- lative. Contemporary science is going to be proven wrong, but mathematics is not. The scientists of the past were well justified in holding na¨ıve and er- roneous views about physical phenomena in the context of the civilizations in which they lived, but there can never be any justification for establishing erro- neous mathematical results. The mechanics of Aristotel is wrong, but the geometry of Euclid is, was, and always will be correct. Right and wrong mean different things in science and mathematics. In the former, “right” means cor- respondence with reality; in mathematics it means logical consistency. John D. Barrow C.C. Remsing i Mathematics is a way of representing and explain- ing the Universe in a sym- bolic way. John D. Barrow Mathematics may be de- fined as the subject in which we never know what are we talking about, nor whether what we are say- ing is true. Bertrand Russell What is mathematics, anyway ? In a broad sense, mathematics include all the related areas which touch on quantitative, geometric, and logical themes. This includes Statistics, Computer Science, Logic, Applied Mathematics, and other fields which are frequently considered distinct from mathematics, as well as fields which study the study of mathematics (!) – History of Mathematics, Mathematics Education, and so on. We draw the line only at experimental sciences, philosophy, and computer applications. Personal perspectives vary widely, of course. Probably the only absolute definition of mathematics is : that which mathematicians do. Contrary to common perception, mathematics does not consists of “crunch- ing numbers” or “solving equations”. There are branches of mathematics con- cerned with setting up equations, or analyze their solutions, and there are ii MAT 102 - Discrete Mathematics parts of mathematics devoted to creating methods for doing computations. But there are also parts of mathematics which have nothing at all to do with numbers and equations. The current mathematics literature can be divided, roughly, into two parts : “pure” mathematics (i.e. mathematics for mathematics) and “applied” math- ematics (i.e. mathematics for something else). The first group divides roughly into just a few broad overlapping areas : Foundations : considers questions in logic or set theory – the very • language of mathematics. Algebra : is principally concerned with symmetry, patterns, discrete • sets, and the rules for manipulating arithmetic operations (one might think of this as the outgrowth of arithmetic and algebra classes in pri- mary and secondary school). Geometry : is concerned with shapes and sets, and the properties of • them which are preserved under various kinds of transformations (this is related to elementary geometry and analytic geometry). Analysis : studies functions, the real number line, and the ideas of • continuity and limit (this is the natural succesor to courses in graphing, trigonometry, and calculus). The second broad part of mathematics literature includes those areas which could be considered either independent disciplines or central parts of mathe- matics, as well as areas which clearly use mathematics but are interested in non-mathematical ideas too : Probability and Statistics : has a dual nature – mathematical and • experimental. Computer Sciences : consider algorithms and information handling. • C.C. Remsing iii Application to Sciences : significant mathematics must be devel- • opped to formulate ideas in the physical sciences (e.g. mechanics, optics, electromagnetism, relativity, astronomy, etc.), engineering (e.g. control, robotics, etc.), and other branches of science (e.g. biology, economics, social sciences). The division between mathematics and its applications is of course vague. Contents 1 Propositions and Predicates 1 1.1 Propositionsandconnectives . 2 1.2 Propositionalequivalences . 10 1.3 Predicatesandquantifiers . 14 1.4 Exercises .............................. 22 2 Sets and Numbers 27 2.1 Sets ................................. 28 2.2 Operationsonsets ......................... 34 2.3 Theintegersanddivision . 41 2.4 Exercises .............................. 54 3 Functions 60 3.1 Generalfunctions.. ... ... ... ... ... .. ... ... 61 3.2 Specificfunctions.. ... ... ... ... ... .. ... ... 74 3.3 Permutations ............................ 78 3.4 Exercises .............................. 89 4 Mathematical Induction 94 4.1 Sequencesofnumbers .. ... ... ... ... .. ... ... 95 4.2 Summations............................. 97 4.3 Mathematicalinduction . 102 4.4 Exercises .............................. 112 iv C.C. Remsing v 5 Counting 116 5.1 Basiccountingprinciples. 117 5.2 Permutationsandcombinations . 126 5.3 Binomialformula.. ... ... ... ... ... .. ... ... 136 5.4 Exercises .............................. 140 6 Recursion 144 6.1 Recursively defined sequences . 145 6.2 Modellingwithrecurrencerelations. 150 6.3 Linearrecurrencerelations. 158 6.4 Exercises .............................. 165 7 Linear Equations and Matrices 171 7.1 Systemsoflinearequations . 172 7.2 MatricesandGaussianelimination . 176 7.3 Matrixoperations . ... ... ... ... ... .. ... ... 188 7.4 Exercises .............................. 199 8 Determinants 205 8.1 Determinants ............................ 206 8.2 Propertiesofdeterminants. 210 8.3 Applications............................. 220 8.4 Exercises .............................. 225 9 Vectors, Lines, and Planes 231 9.1 Vectorsintheplane ... ... ... ... ... .. ... ... 232 9.2 Vectorsinspace. .. ... ... ... ... ... .. ... ... 244 9.3 Linesandplanes .......................... 259 9.4 Exercises .............................. 268 10 Complex Numbers 273 10.1 Numbersystems .. ... ... ... ... ... .. ... ... 274 vi MAT 102 - Discrete Mathematics 10.2 Algebraicoperations on complex numbers . 280 10.3 DeMoivre’sformula . 285 10.4 Applications... .. ... ... ... ... ... .. ... ... 291 10.5Exercises .............................. 302 A Answers and Hints to Selected Exercises 305 B Revision Problems 323 Chapter 1 Propositions and Predicates Topics : 1. Propositions and connectives 2. Propositional equivalences 3. Predicates and quantifiers Logic is the basis of all mathematical reasoning. The rules of logic specify the precise meaning of mathematical statements. Most of the definitions of formal logic have been developed so that they agree with the natural or intuitive logic used by people who have been educated to think clearly and use language carefully. The difference that exists between formal and intuitive logic are necessary to avoid ambiguity and obtain consistency. Copyright c Claudiu C. Remsing, 2005. All rights reserved. 1 2 MAT 102 - Discrete Mathematics 1.1 Propositions and connectives In any mathematical theory, new terms are defined by using those that have been previously defined. However, this process has to start somewhere. A few initial terms necessarily remain undefined. In logic, the words sentence, true, and false are initial undefined terms. Propositions 1.1.1 Definition. A proposition (or statement) is a sentence that is either TRUE or FALSE (but not both). 1.1.2 Examples. All the following sentences are propositions. (1) Pretoria is the capital of South Africa. (2) 3+3=5. (3) If x is a real number, then x2 < 0. (FALSE) (4) All kings of the United States are bald. (TRUE) (5) There is intelligent life outside our solar system. 1.1.3 Examples. The following are not propositions. (6) Is this concept important ? (7) Wow,what a day ! (8) x +1=7. (9) When the swallows return to Capistrano. (10) This sentence is false. C.C. Remsing 3 A proposition ends in a period, not a question mark or an exclamation point. Thus (6) and (7) are not propositions. (8) is not a proposition, even though it has the proper form, until the variable x is replaced by meaningful terms. Because (9) makes no sense, it cannot be TRUE or FALSE. Sentence (10) is deceiving; it looks like a proposition. If it is a proposition, then it is either TRUE or FALSE, but not both. Suppose it is TRUE. Then what it says is TRUE, and it is FALSE. But it cannot be both TRUE and FALSE. Hence (10) cannot be TRUE. Well, suppose (10) is FALSE. Then what it says is FALSE, and (10) is not FALSE, itis TRUE. Again, it cannot be both TRUE and FALSE. Therefore, (10) cannot be classified as either TRUE or FALSE. Hence it is not a proposition. We will use lower case letters, such as p,q,r,s,... to denote propositions. Any proposition symbolized by a single letter is called a primitive proposi- tion. If p is
Recommended publications
  • 1 Sets and Set Notation. Definition 1 (Naive Definition of a Set)
    LINEAR ALGEBRA MATH 2700.006 SPRING 2013 (COHEN) LECTURE NOTES 1 Sets and Set Notation. Definition 1 (Naive Definition of a Set). A set is any collection of objects, called the elements of that set. We will most often name sets using capital letters, like A, B, X, Y , etc., while the elements of a set will usually be given lower-case letters, like x, y, z, v, etc. Two sets X and Y are called equal if X and Y consist of exactly the same elements. In this case we write X = Y . Example 1 (Examples of Sets). (1) Let X be the collection of all integers greater than or equal to 5 and strictly less than 10. Then X is a set, and we may write: X = f5; 6; 7; 8; 9g The above notation is an example of a set being described explicitly, i.e. just by listing out all of its elements. The set brackets {· · ·} indicate that we are talking about a set and not a number, sequence, or other mathematical object. (2) Let E be the set of all even natural numbers. We may write: E = f0; 2; 4; 6; 8; :::g This is an example of an explicity described set with infinitely many elements. The ellipsis (:::) in the above notation is used somewhat informally, but in this case its meaning, that we should \continue counting forever," is clear from the context. (3) Let Y be the collection of all real numbers greater than or equal to 5 and strictly less than 10. Recalling notation from previous math courses, we may write: Y = [5; 10) This is an example of using interval notation to describe a set.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Abstract Algebra (Math 113)
    Introduction to Abstract Algebra (Math 113) Alexander Paulin, with edits by David Corwin FOR FALL 2019 MATH 113 002 ONLY Contents 1 Introduction 4 1.1 What is Algebra? . 4 1.2 Sets . 6 1.3 Functions . 9 1.4 Equivalence Relations . 12 2 The Structure of + and × on Z 15 2.1 Basic Observations . 15 2.2 Factorization and the Fundamental Theorem of Arithmetic . 17 2.3 Congruences . 20 3 Groups 23 1 3.1 Basic Definitions . 23 3.1.1 Cayley Tables for Binary Operations and Groups . 28 3.2 Subgroups, Cosets and Lagrange's Theorem . 30 3.3 Generating Sets for Groups . 35 3.4 Permutation Groups and Finite Symmetric Groups . 40 3.4.1 Active vs. Passive Notation for Permutations . 40 3.4.2 The Symmetric Group Sym3 . 43 3.4.3 Symmetric Groups in General . 44 3.5 Group Actions . 52 3.5.1 The Orbit-Stabiliser Theorem . 55 3.5.2 Centralizers and Conjugacy Classes . 59 3.5.3 Sylow's Theorem . 66 3.6 Symmetry of Sets with Extra Structure . 68 3.7 Normal Subgroups and Isomorphism Theorems . 73 3.8 Direct Products and Direct Sums . 83 3.9 Finitely Generated Abelian Groups . 85 3.10 Finite Abelian Groups . 90 3.11 The Classification of Finite Groups (Proofs Omitted) . 95 4 Rings, Ideals, and Homomorphisms 100 2 4.1 Basic Definitions . 100 4.2 Ideals, Quotient Rings and the First Isomorphism Theorem for Rings . 105 4.3 Properties of Elements of Rings . 109 4.4 Polynomial Rings . 112 4.5 Ring Extensions . 115 4.6 Field of Fractions .
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1310.3297V1 [Math.AG] 11 Oct 2013 Bertini for Macaulay2
    Bertini for Macaulay2 Daniel J. Bates,∗ Elizabeth Gross,† Anton Leykin,‡ Jose Israel Rodriguez§ September 6, 2018 Abstract Numerical algebraic geometry is the field of computational mathematics concerning the numerical solution of polynomial systems of equations. Bertini, a popular software package for computational applications of this field, includes implementations of a variety of algorithms based on polynomial homotopy continuation. The Macaulay2 package Bertini provides an interface to Bertini, making it possible to access the core run modes of Bertini in Macaulay2. With these run modes, users can find approximate solutions to zero-dimensional systems and positive-dimensional systems, test numerically whether a point lies on a variety, sample numerically from a variety, and perform parameter homotopy runs. 1 Numerical algebraic geometry Numerical algebraic geometry (numerical AG) refers to a set of methods for finding and manipulating the solution sets of systems of polynomial equations. Said differently, given f : CN → Cn, numerical algebraic geometry provides facilities for computing numerical approximations to isolated solutions of V (f) = z ∈ CN |f(z)=0 , as well as numerical approximations to generic points on positive-dimensional components. The book [7] provides a good introduction to the field, while the newer book [2] provides a simpler introduction as well as a complete manual for the software package Bertini [1]. arXiv:1310.3297v1 [math.AG] 11 Oct 2013 Bertini is a free, open source software package for computations in numerical alge- braic geometry. The purpose of this article is to present a Macaulay2 [3] package Bertini that provides an interface to Bertini. This package uses basic datatypes and service rou- tines for computations in numerical AG provided by the package NAGtypes.
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematical Logic
    Mathematical logic Jouko Väänänen January 16, 2017 ii Contents 1 Introduction 1 2 Propositional logic 3 2.1 Propositional formulas . .3 2.2 Turth-tables . .7 2.3 Problems . 12 3 Structures 15 3.1 Relations . 15 3.2 Structures . 16 3.3 Vocabulary . 19 3.4 Isomorphism . 20 3.5 Problems . 22 4 Predicate logic 23 4.1 Formulas . 30 4.2 Identity . 36 4.3 Deduction . 37 4.4 Theories . 43 4.5 Problems . 51 5 Incompleteness of number theory 55 5.1 Primitive recursive functions . 57 5.2 Recursive functions . 65 5.3 Definability in number theory . 67 5.4 Recursively enumerable sets . 73 5.5 Problems . 79 6 Further reading 83 iii iv CONTENTS Preface This book is based on lectures the author has given in the Department of Math- ematics and Statistics in the University of Helsinki during several decades. As the title reveals, this is a mathematics course, but it can also serve computer science students. The presentation is self-contained, although the reader is as- sumed to be familiar with elementary set-theoretical notation and with proof by induction. The idea is to give basic completeness and incompleteness results in an unaf- fected straightforward way without delving into all the elaboration that modern mathematical logic involves. There is a section “Further reading” guiding the reader to the rich literature on more advanced results. I am indebted to the many students who have followed the course as well as to the teachers who have taught it in addition to myself, in particular Tapani Hyttinen, Åsa Hirvonen and Taneli Huuskonen.
    [Show full text]
  • Math 203A - Solution Set 1 2 Problem 1
    Math 203A - Solution Set 1 2 Problem 1. Show that the Zariski topology on A is not the product of the Zariski topologies 1 1 on A × A . Answer: Clearly, the diagonal 2 Z = f(x; y): x − y = 0g ⊂ A 2 is closed in the Zariski topology of A . We claim this Z is not closed in the product 1 1 2 topology of A × A . Assume otherwise. Then, the complement A n Z is open in the 1 product topology. Therefore, there are nonempty open sets U; V in A such that 2 U × V ⊂ A n Z: Now, the sets U and V have finite complements: 1 U = A n fp1; : : : ; png; 1 V = A n fq1; : : : ; qmg: We obtain a contradiction picking 1 z 2 A n fp1; : : : ; pn; q1; : : : ; qmg: In this case, we clearly have 2 (z; z) 2 U × V; while (z; z) 62 A n Z: Problem 2. A topological space X is said to be Noetherian if it satisfies the ascending chain condition on open sets, i.e. any ascending chain of open sets eventually stabilizes. (i) Check that any subset Y ⊂ X of a Noetherian space is also Noetherian in the subspace topology. (ii) Check that a Noetherian space which is also Hausdorff must be a finite set of points. (iii) Show that a Noetherian space is quasi-compact i.e., show that any open cover of a Noe- therian space has a finite subcover. n (iv) Show that A is Noetherian in the Zariski topology. Conclude that any affine algebraic set is Noetherian.
    [Show full text]
  • Basic Topological Structures of the Theory of Ordinary Differential Equations
    TOPOLOGY IN NONLINEAR ANALYSIS BANACH CENTER PUBLICATIONS, VOLUME 35 INSTITUTE OF MATHEMATICS POLISH ACADEMY OF SCIENCES WARSZAWA 1996 BASIC TOPOLOGICAL STRUCTURES OF THE THEORY OF ORDINARY DIFFERENTIAL EQUATIONS V. V. FILIPPOV Chair of General Topology and Geometry, Department of Mathematics Moscow State University, 119899, Moscow V-234, Russia E-mail: fi[email protected] If you open any book on the theory of ordinary differential equations (TODE) you can observe that almost every proof in the TODE uses the continuity of the dependence of a solution of the Cauchy problem on initial data and parameters of the right-hand side. But the classical TODE has few theorems assuring this continuity. In general they suppose the continuity of the right-hand side. We can note a trivial Example 0.1. Let g(t; y) be a continuous function. The dependence of solutions of the equations y0 = g(t; y) + α(t2 + y2 + α2)−1 on the parameter α is continuous though the right-hand side is not continuous at the point t = y = α = 0. So we meet the problem to describe a topological structure adequate to the idea of the continuity of the dependence of solutions on parameters of the right-hand side of the equation. Solving this problem we develop a new large working theory which gives a natural framework of topological contents of the TODE. The theory deals with equations of classical types, with equations having various singularities in the right-hand sides, with differential inclusions etc. Some account of the theory may be found in [7] (see also the Chapter IX in the book [4] and the book [8]).
    [Show full text]
  • Almost PI Algebras Are PI
    ALMOST PI ALGEBRAS ARE PI MICHAEL LARSEN AND ANER SHALEV Abstract. We define the notion of an almost polynomial identity of an associative algebra R, and show that its existence implies the existence of an actual polynomial identity of R. A similar result is also obtained for Lie algebras and Jordan algebras. We also prove related quantitative results for simple and semisimple algebras. By a well known theorem of Peter Neumann [N], for all ǫ> 0 there exists N > 0 such that if G is a finite group with at least ǫ|G|2 pairs (x,y) ∈ G2 satisfying [x,y] = 1, then [xN ,yN ]N = 1 for all x,y ∈ G. We can express this by saying that if [x,y] is an ǫ-probabilistic identity for G, then [xN ,yN ]N is an identity for G. See also Mann [M] for a similar result on finite groups in which x2 is an ǫ-probabilistic identity. It is an open question whether every probabilistic identity in finite and residually finite groups implies an actual identity; see [LS2] and [Sh] for further discussion of this question. In this paper, we consider the analogous problem for associative algebras (as well as Lie algebras). Here, the possible identities are polynomials in a non-commuting set of variables (or Lie polynomials) rather than elements of a free group. We introduce the notion of an almost identity of an algebra as an analogue of a probabilistic identity and show that algebras with an almost identity satisfy an actual identity. While we focus here on infinite- dimensional algebras we also prove related quantitative results for finite dimensional simple algebras.
    [Show full text]
  • Computing the Equidimensional Decomposition of an Algebraic Closed Set by Means of Lifting fibers
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector ARTICLE IN PRESS Journal of Complexity 19 (2003) 564–596 http://www.elsevier.com/locate/jco Computing the equidimensional decomposition of an algebraic closed set by means of lifting fibers Gre´ goire Lecerfà Laboratoire de Mathe´matiques, UMR 8100 CNRS, Universite´ de Versailles St-Quentin-en-Yvelines, 45, Avenue des E´tats-Unis, Baˆtiment Fermat, Versailles, 78035 France Received 3 September 2002; accepted 27 February 2003 Abstract We present a new probabilistic method for solving systems of polynomial equations and inequations. Our algorithm computes the equidimensional decomposition of the Zariski closure of the solution set of such systems. Each equidimensional component is encoded by a generic fiber, that is a finite set of points obtained from the intersection of the component with a generic transverse affine subspace. Our algorithm is incremental in the number of equations to be solved. Its complexity is mainly cubic in the maximum of the degrees of the solution sets of the intermediate systems counting multiplicities. Our method is designed for coefficient fields having characteristic zero or big enough with respect to the number of solutions. If the base field is the field of the rational numbers then the resolution is first performed modulo a random prime number after we have applied a random change of coordinates. Then we search for coordinates with small integers and lift the solutions up to the rational numbers. Our implementation is available within our package Kronecker from version 0.166, which is written in the Magma computer algebra system.
    [Show full text]
  • Cutting Planes in Constraint Logic Programming
    Cutting Planes in Constraint Logic Programming Alexander Bockmayr MPI{I{94{207 February 1994 Author's Address Alexander Bockmayr, Max-Planck-Institut f¨urInformatik, Im Stadtwald, D-66123 Saarbr¨ucken, [email protected] Publication Notes The present report has been submitted for publication elsewhere and will be copyrighted if accepted. Acknowledgements This work benefited from discussions with P. Barth and S. Ceria. It was supported by the German Ministry for Research and Technology (BMFT) (contract ITS 9103), the ESPRIT Basic Research Project ACCLAIM (contract EP 7195) and the ESPRIT Working Group CCL (contract EP 6028). Abstract In this paper, we show how recently developed techniques from combinatorial optimization can be embedded into constraint logic programming. We develop a constraint solver for the constraint logic programming language CLP(PB) for logic programming with pseudo-Boolean constraints. Our approach is based on the generation of polyhedral cutting planes and the concept of branch-and-cut. In the case of 0-1 constraints, this can improve or replace the finite domain techniques used in existing constraint logic programming systems. Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Constraint Logic Programming with 0-1 Constraints 3 2.1 Main problems ::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::: 5 2.2 Pseudo-Boolean and finite domain constraints :::::::::::::::::::::: 6 3 Solving 0-1 Constraints 6 3.1 Equality descriptions of the solution set ::::::::::::::::::::::::: 6 3.2 Inequality descriptions ::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::: 7 3.3 Size of the representation ::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::: 8 3.4 Strength of the representation ::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::: 9 3.5 Defining a solved form ::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::: 9 4 Computing the Solved Form 12 5 Branch and Cut 15 6 Conclusion and Further Research 17 A Correctness and Completeness of the Specialized Cutting Plane Algorithm 20 B Cut Lifting 22 1 1 Introduction Constraint logic programming has been one of the major developments in declarative programming in recent years [JM94].
    [Show full text]
  • Lesson 1: Solutions to Polynomial Equations
    NYS COMMON CORE MATHEMATICS CURRICULUM Lesson 1 M3 PRECALCULUS AND ADVANCED TOPICS Lesson 1: Solutions to Polynomial Equations Student Outcomes . Students determine all solutions of polynomial equations over the set of complex numbers and understand the implications of the fundamental theorem of algebra, especially for quadratic polynomials. Lesson Notes Students studied polynomial equations and the nature of the solutions of these equations extensively in Algebra II Module 1, extending factoring to the complex realm. The fundamental theorem of algebra indicates that any polynomial function of degree 푛 will have 푛 zeros (including repeated zeros). Establishing the fundamental theorem of algebra was one of the greatest achievements of nineteenth-century mathematics. It is worth spending time further exploring it now that students have a much broader understanding of complex numbers. This lesson reviews what they learned in previous grades and provides additional support for their understanding of what it means to solve polynomial equations over the set of complex numbers. Students work with equations with complex number solutions and apply identities such as 푎2 + 푏2 = (푎 + 푏푖)(푎 − 푏푖) for real numbers 푎 and 푏 to solve equations and explore the implications of the fundamental theorem of algebra (N-CN.C.8 and N-CN.C.9). Throughout the lesson, students vary their reasoning by applying algebraic properties (MP.3) and examining the structure of expressions to support their solutions and make generalizations (MP.7 and MP.8). Relevant definitions introduced in Algebra II are provided in the student materials for this lesson. A note on terminology: Equations have solutions, and functions have zeros.
    [Show full text]
  • Topology MATH 4181 Fall Semester 1999
    Topology MATH 4181 Fall Semester 1999 David C. Royster UNC Charlotte November 11, 1999 Chapter 1 Introduction to Topology 1.1 History1 Topology is thought of as a discipline that has emerged in the twentieth century. There are precursors of topology dating back into the 1600's. Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646{1716) was the first to foresee a geometry in which position, rather than magnitude was the most important factor. In 1676 Leibniz use the term geometria situs(geometry of position) in predicting the development of a type of vector calculus somewhat similar to topology as we see it today. The first practical application of topology was made in the year 1736 by the Swiss mathematician Leonhard Euler (1707{1783) in the K¨onigsberg Bridge Problem. Carl F. Gauss (1777{1855) predicted in 1833 that geometry of location would become a mathematical discipline of great importance. His studey of closed surfaces such as the sphere and the torus and surfaces much like those encountered in multi- dimensional calculus may be considered as a harbinger of general topology. Gauss was also interested in knots, which are of current interest today in topology. The word topology was first used by the German mathematics Joseph B. Listing (1808{1882) in the title of his book Vorstudien zur Topologie (Introductory Studies in Topology), a textbook published in 1847. Listing book dealt with knots and sur- faces but failed to generate much interest in either the name or the subject matter. Throughout much of the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, much of what now falls under the auspices of topology was studied under the name of analysis situs (analysis of position).
    [Show full text]
  • Solving Systems of Polynomial Equations Bernd Sturmfels
    Solving Systems of Polynomial Equations Bernd Sturmfels Department of Mathematics, University of California at Berkeley, Berkeley, CA 94720, USA E-mail address: [email protected] 2000 Mathematics Subject Classification. Primary 13P10, 14Q99, 65H10, Secondary 12D10, 14P10, 35E20, 52B20, 62J12, 68W30, 90C22, 91A06. The author was supported in part by the U.S. National Science Foundation, grants #DMS-0200729 and #DMS-0138323. Abstract. One of the most classical problems of mathematics is to solve sys- tems of polynomial equations in several unknowns. Today, polynomial models are ubiquitous and widely applied across the sciences. They arise in robot- ics, coding theory, optimization, mathematical biology, computer vision, game theory, statistics, machine learning, control theory, and numerous other areas. The set of solutions to a system of polynomial equations is an algebraic variety, the basic object of algebraic geometry. The algorithmic study of algebraic vari- eties is the central theme of computational algebraic geometry. Exciting recent developments in symbolic algebra and numerical software for geometric calcu- lations have revolutionized the field, making formerly inaccessible problems tractable, and providing fertile ground for experimentation and conjecture. The first half of this book furnishes an introduction and represents a snapshot of the state of the art regarding systems of polynomial equations. Afficionados of the well-known text books by Cox, Little, and O’Shea will find familiar themes in the first five chapters: polynomials in one variable, Gr¨obner bases of zero-dimensional ideals, Newton polytopes and Bernstein’s Theorem, multidimensional resultants, and primary decomposition. The second half of this book explores polynomial equations from a variety of novel and perhaps unexpected angles.
    [Show full text]