Samuel Hirsch, Hegel, and the Legacy of Ethical Monotheism*
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Samuel Hirsch, Hegel, and the Legacy of Ethical Monotheism* Robert Erlewine Illinois Wesleyan University; [email protected] ■ Abstract This essay examines Samuel Hirsch’s Religious Philosophy of the Jews as a forerunner of twentieth-century works of ethical monotheism in modern Jewish thought. In particular, it explores Hirsch’s use of the dichotomy between monotheism and idolatry as a way to resist Hegel’s attempts to incorporate Judaism into his developmental history of religion. Hirsch frames his opposition to the Hegelian account of religion by means of providing a rival interpretation of Genesis 3 to that offered by Hegel in the Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion. After juxtaposing Hegel’s and Hirsch’s respective interpretations of Genesis 3, I explore Hirsch’s account of religion, which, unlike Hegel’s, is presented in terms of the dichotomy of true and false religion. Finally, I will briefly highlight how Hirsch’s basic strategy for understanding Judaism vis-à-vis other religions—namely, casting the dichotomy between monotheism and idolatry in starkly ethical terms—is taken up and utilized by Hermann Cohen and Emmanuel Levinas in the twentieth century. ■ Keywords Die Religionsphilosophie der Juden/The Religious Philosophy of the Jews, Samuel Hirsch, G. W. F. Hegel, Franz Rosenzweig, Hermann Cohen, Emmanuel Levinas, Genesis 3, ethical monotheism * I would like to thank Illinois Wesleyan University for supporting me with an Artistic and Scholarly Development Grant in the Fall 2016. This grant provided me with the resources and time necessary to undertake this project. I would also like to thank Jacqueline Paskow, Dustin N. Atlas, and Martin Kavka for their thoughtful comments and suggestions at different stages of the formulation and revision of this paper. HTR 113:1 (2020) 89–110 Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 170.106.40.139, on 27 Sep 2021 at 18:20:16, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0017816019000361 90 HARVARD THEOLOGICAL REVIEW ■ Introduction In recent years, the question of the nature and character of modern Jewish thought has been actively debated by scholars.1 Jewish thought has customarily been understood as an activity internal to Jews and Judaism, where thinkers seek to reconcile traditional Jewish theology with modern, scientific sensibilities.2 However, as the study of modern Jewish thought has increasingly migrated out of philosophy departments into those of religion and history,3 scholars increasingly attend to the manner in which Jewish thought has been situated, and works to situate itself, with respect to major theological and cultural discourses in Europe and the United States.4 This latter approach accords well with recent characterizations of the world religions discourse as a site for establishing European identity.5 It also complements recent work in the study of German Jewish history that has treated the emergence of modern Jewish studies as a response to the exclusion of Jews from theology departments.6 In approaching modern Jewish thought in this manner, the concern 1 See, for example: Steven Schwarzschild, “Modern Jewish Philosophy,” in Pursuit of the Ideal: Jewish Writings of Steven Schwarzschild (ed. Menachem Kellner; SUNY Series in Jewish Philosophy; Albany: State University of New York Press: 1990) 229–35; Norbert Samuelson, “Is Jewish Philosophy Either Philosophy or Jewish?” in La Storia della Filosofia Ebraica (ed. Irene Kajon; Biblioteca dell’Archivio di filosofia 9; Padua: CEDAM, 1993) 463–85; Michael L. Morgan and Peter Eli Gordon, “Introduction: Modern Jewish Philosophy, Modern Philosophy, and Modern Judaism,” in The Cambridge Companion to Modern Jewish Philosophy (ed. Michael L. Morgan and Peter Eli Gordon; Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007) 1–13; Michael Zank, “Zwischen Den Stühlen? On the Taxonomic Anxieties of Modern Jewish Philosophy,” European Journal for Jewish Studies 1 (2007) 105–34; Aaron W. Hughes and Elliot R. Wolfson, “Introduction: Charting an Alternative Course for the Study of Jewish Philosophy,” in New Directions in Jewish Philosophy (ed. Aaron W. Hughes and Elliot R. Wolfson; Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2010) 1–18; Leora Batnitzky, How Judaism Became a Religion: An Introduction to Modern Jewish Thought (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2011); Michael Zank, “The Heteronomy of Modern Jewish Philosophy,” Journal of Jewish Thought and Philosophy 20 (2012) 99–124; Martin Kavka, introduction to The Modern Era (ed. Martin Kavka, Zachary Braiterman, and David Novak; The Cambridge History of Jewish Philosophy vol 2; Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012) 1–31; Willi Goetschel, “Jewish Philosophy? The Discourse of a Project,” in The Discipline of Philosophy and the Invention of Modern Jewish Thought (New York: Fordham University Press, 2013) 39–57; Aaron W. Hughes, Rethinking Jewish Philosophy: Beyond Particularism and Universalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014); and Robert Erlewine, Judaism and the West: From Hermann Cohen to Joseph Soloveitchik (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2016). 2 For such an approach, see Morgan and Gordon, introduction. 3 For a helpful overview of the history of Jewish thought in the American academy, see Kavka, introduction. On the effects of disciplinary differences in the study of modern Jewish thought and philosophy, see Hughes and Wolfson, “Introduction,” 1. 4 The respective works by Zank, Hughes, Batnitzky, and Erlewine mentioned in n. 1 are in this vein. 5 See Tomoko Masuzawa, The Invention of World Religions: Or, How European Universalism Was Preserved in the Language of Pluralism (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2005). See also Timothy Fitzgerald, The Ideology of Religious Studies (New York: Oxford University Press, 2000), and Daniel Dubuisson, The Western Construction of Religion: Myths, Knowledge, and Ideology (trans. William Sayers; Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2003). 6 On this point, see Susannah Heschel, “Jewish Studies as Counterhistory,” in Insider and Outsider: American Jews and Multiculturalism (ed. David Biale, Michael Galchinsky, and Susannah Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 170.106.40.139, on 27 Sep 2021 at 18:20:16, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0017816019000361 ROBERT ERLEWINE 91 of the scholar is less with assessing the philosophical viability of claims than with examining how these claims position Judaism over against other religious traditions and as belonging, or not, to the contested, charged, and highly fraught notions of “Europe” and “the West.” One strategy for situating Judaism employed by many prominent thinkers in modern Jewish thought is the concept of ethical monotheism. In it, the radical distinction between true and false notions of God, as refracted through the prism of ethics, is utilized in order to present Judaism as possessing a unique, irreplaceable, and unsurpassed standing with regard to all other religions.7 For ethical monotheism, the distinction between monotheism and idolatry has vital relevance for modernity precisely because it understands injustice as bound up with, and ultimately stemming from, improper, idolatrous, and/or pagan conceptions of God. Judaism is then affiliated with a rationalistic theological view which pairs the distinction or difference of God from human beings, often configured in terms of God’s transcendence, with an emphasis on human responsibility, making it a—or the—religion of ethical seriousness and maturity.8 As a corollary of this view of Judaism, Christianity, presented as pagan or as partly pagan, is associated with immanent notions of the divine and the romantic celebration of the mythical and the irrational and is considered ethically suspect. Heschel; Berkeley: University of California Press, 1998) 101–16, and Heschel’s monograph from the same year, Abraham Geiger and the Jewish Jesus (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998); Christian Wiese, Challenging Colonial Discourse: Jewish Studies and Protestant Theology in Wilhelmine Germany (Leiden: Brill, 2005); and Ismar Schorsch, Leopold Zunz: Creativity in Adversity (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2018). 7 To be sure, the dichotomy of true and false notions of God, often framed as that between monotheism and idolatry, is by no means limited to thinkers who embrace ethical monotheism, such as Hermann Cohen and Emmanuel Levinas. One also finds it in Franz Rosenzweig, Martin Buber, and Emil Fackenheim, among others. The dyad of monotheism and idolatry has also been used to structure a wide range of scholarly works within modern Jewish thought in recent years. See, for example: Elliot R. Wolfson, Giving Beyond the Gift: Apophasis and Overcoming Theomania (New York: Fordham University Press, 2014); Gideon Freudenthal, No Religion without Idolatry: Mendelssohn’s Jewish Enlightenment (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 2012); Robert Erlewine, Monotheism and Tolerance: Recovering a Religion of Reason (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2010); Leora Batnitzky, Idolatry and Representation: The Philosophy of Franz Rosenzweig Reconsidered (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2000); and Moshe Halbertal and Avishai Margalit, Idolatry (trans. Naomi Goldblum; Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1994). 8 The philosophers Hermann Cohen and Emmanuel Levinas, as well as the theologians Leo Baeck