Free Will Is Not a Mystery

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Free Will Is Not a Mystery FREE WILL IS NOT A MYSTERY laura w. ekstrom This essay aims centrally to defend two claims. First, the nature of free will is not mysterious. Certainly, it is contentious, but it is not mysterious. I defend this claim by illustrating the fact that a range of philosophical accounts of the nature of freedom—including those of historical and contemporary writers—are plausibly interpreted as aiming to capture both an autonomy and an alternative possibilities component. Second, a prominent argument aiming to press us to the view of “free will mysterianism” can reasonably be resisted. According to the view of mysterian- ism concerning free will, there is a powerful, unanswered case for the impossibility of free will, yet free will undeniably does exist. By recommending a particular event- causal indeterminist account of free action and by distinguishing various senses of the term “chance,” I argue that mysterianism concerning free will is not well founded. Two Features of Freedom More than twenty years ago, in an overview of the modern literature on free agency that remains valuable today, Gary Watson (1987 a ) structured the discussion by way of the “two different features of freedom that must be captured in any reasonable conception—namely self-determination (or autonomy) and the availability of alternative possibilities” (145). The fi rst feature is meant to capture the idea that a free act derives from, and is governed by, the self, not from or by heteronomous 00001252190.INDD001252190.INDD 336666 22/10/2011/10/2011 88:19:06:19:06 PPMM free will is not a mystery 367 sources. The second condition expresses the idea that free acts are traditionally regarded as ones chosen from among options, however these options are to be con- ceived. Watson continues: “Any adequate notion of free agency must provide for possibility and autonomy in some sense, and, in my view, the traditional concep- tions that are still taken seriously were meant to do so” (145). Contemporary free agency theorists would do well to return to Watson’s (1987 a ) instructive article. The structure it gives to debates among writers ranging from Hobbes to van Inwagen, through Bramhall, Kant, Reid, Ayer, Chisholm, Frankfurt, Dennett, and Davidson, makes sense of a wide array of literature on the free will problem and can be applied to understanding more recent literature, including some that has diverged in disparate directions into subfi elds that exist in relative isolation from each other. Consider these as freedom’s central features: (i) self-determination, or autonomy; and (ii) the availability of alternative possibilities. An early suggestion of both of these features is in Aristotle’s discussion of the vol- untary in Nicomachean Ethics (1973): the voluntary has its origin “in” the agent— “A human being originates his own actions . as he fathers his own children” (1113b6)— and it involves a dual ability—“where it is in our power to act it is also in our power not to act” (1113b6). 1 Many philosophers from diverse periods make note of the alternative possi- bilities condition of freedom. David Hume (1748 /1977 ) defi nes liberty as “a power of acting or not acting according to the determinations of the will; that is, if we choose to remain at rest, we may; if we choose to move, we also may” (sec. 8) Thomas Reid (1983 , 523) claims that the “power to produce any effect implies the power not to produce it.” Kant (1960 , 45) likewise proposes that for an act to be truly free, “the act as well as its opposite must be within the power of the subject at the moment of its taking place.” According to A. J. Ayer (1982 , 15) , “When I am said to have done something of my own free will it is implied that I could have acted otherwise.” Bernard Williams (1995 a , 5) describes the claim that free will exists as consisting in “something to the effect that agents sometimes act voluntarily, and that when they do so they have a real choice between more than one course of action; or more than one course is open to them; or it is up to them which of sev- eral actions they perform.” The interest in capturing the notion of autonomy in an account of freedom is clear in Hobbes (1969 ) , who stresses the idea that external limits on one’s agency, such as coercion by another agent, hinder freedom of action, whereas what is inter- nal to the actor himself cannot be an impediment: “Liberty is the absence of all impediments to action that are not contained in the nature and intrinsical quality of the agent” (47). Locke’s (1975 /1847 ) interest in providing for a notion of self-determination is also plain: “. every man is put under a necessity, by his constitution as an intelligent being, to be determined in willing by his own thought and judgment what is best for him to do, else he would be under the determination 00001252190.INDD001252190.INDD 336767 22/10/2011/10/2011 88:19:07:19:07 PPMM 368 libertarian perspectives on free agency and free will of some other than himself, which is want of liberty” (II. 21. 48). Free action derives from the agent’s will and intelligence, not from something other than himself. Dispute over the right interpretation of both of these conditions—self-deter- mination and the availability of alternative possibilities—has fueled debates between those who view determinism as a threat to freedom and those who do not, as well as among theorists who stand on the same side of that debate. Traditional compati- bilist conceptions of freedom, inspired by the intuition that free action lacks exter- nal obstacles and is dependent on, and derivative from, what is internal to the self, interpret the relevant alternative possibilities counterfactually, in terms of what the agent would have done had she willed, desired, or chosen otherwise. Incompatibilists have tended to view conditional accounts of alternative possibilities as lacking: They have insisted instead on an interpretation that requires suitable causal indetermin- ism and “forking pathways” into the future that are, at least sometimes, each acces- sible to the free agent as extensions of the actual past. Self-determination, too, is open to incompatibilist and compatibilist readings. Determination of action by the self may be alleged to be, in the end, heteronomous, if the self is, itself, determined to be as it is by prior factors and natural laws. In recent philosophical literature on free agency, we fi nd concern with both of these features, alternatives and autonomy. Some discussions have focused more on one feature than the other, leaving us with current bodies of literature that do not always intermingle. We have literature, on the one hand, commonly conceived as work in contemporary metaphysics, on issues centrally concerning alternative pos- sibilities (whether these are to be understood “conditionally” or “dispositionally” or “categorically,” and in what senses of these terms) and their relations to causal deter- minism, causation, natural laws, and what is called “free will.” 2 We fi nd in this “free will literature” discussions of the Consequence Argument for incompatibilism, its refi nements, and the modal principles used therein, as well as continuing debates over what is, or is not, shown by counterfactual intervention (“Frankfurt-style”) cases concerning the relations between morally responsible action and the avail- ability of alternative possibilities, and the implication of these debates, if any, on the question of freedom’s compatibility with causal determinism. On the other hand, we have current literature considered by many as work in moral psychology, action theory, and practical reason—some might say, broadly speaking, ethics—on the notion of personal autonomy and related issues concerning wholeheartedness, identifi cation with and alienation from desire, on being “true to one’s self,” and on some actions’ being more “one’s own” or more “full-blooded” than others.3 Much of this recent literature on personal autonomy, identifi cation, and related notions has sprung from attraction to proposals in the early 1970s by Dworkin (1970 , 1976 ) and Frankfurt (1971 ) , and a suggestive response to their approach by Watson (1975 ) , which are discussed a bit further below. These debates derive from recognition that the Hobbesian view provides a shallow account of the self, over- looking the fact that desires themselves can be external in a sense that makes them impedimental. The aim of recent work in this area is to give a more plausible and expansive account of the self and hence a richer account of self-determination. 00001252190.INDD001252190.INDD 336868 22/10/2011/10/2011 88:19:07:19:07 PPMM free will is not a mystery 369 Literature of this second sort, which tends to be collected into anthologies with such titles as Personal Autonomy (J. S. Taylor 2005 ) ,4 is often not included in anthologies or handbooks such as the present one, though many of the issues in this literature bear on concerns of free will theorists and should be more widely recognized as important and overlapping. Although we have seen some subspecialization in recent literature, nonetheless, various contemporary conceptions of free agency may be understood as sensibly aiming to capture both features of freedom: autonomy and alternative possibilities. For instance, John Martin Fischer’s compatibilist account of the freedom required for moral responsibility includes both a “reasons-responsiveness” requirement as well as an “ownership” requirement, and it is plausible to construe the fi rst of these as an attempt to capture a relevant sense of alternative possibilities and the second as an attempt to capture an autonomy condition. Fischer’s requirement that the mechanism producing a free action must be suitably “reasons-responsive” is, as I view it, a complex and highly developed way of stating that, in acting in a free and responsible way, it must be the case that the agent would have done otherwise, if .
Recommended publications
  • Defending the Subjective Component of Susan Wolf's
    Defending the Subjective Component of Susan Wolf’s “Fitting Fulfillment View” About Meaning in Life. Andreas Hjälmarö Andreas Hjälmarö Kandidatuppsats Filosofi, 15 hp. Ht 2016 Handledare Frans Svensson Umeå Universitet, Umeå Table of content Abstract ................................................................................................................................................... 3 1. Introduction ..................................................................................................................................... 4 2. Background ...................................................................................................................................... 5 2.1 The question .................................................................................................................................. 5 2.2 Common answers .......................................................................................................................... 8 The nihilistic view ............................................................................................................................ 8 The super-naturalistic view ............................................................................................................. 8 The naturalistic view ....................................................................................................................... 9 2.3 Wolf’s view – a combination ......................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Models of Sociality After Idealism in Gadamer, Levinas, Rosenzweig, and Bonhoeffer Christopher J
    University of South Florida Scholar Commons Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School November 2017 From Object to Other: Models of Sociality after Idealism in Gadamer, Levinas, Rosenzweig, and Bonhoeffer Christopher J. King University of South Florida, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the Philosophy Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Scholar Commons Citation King, Christopher J., "From Object to Other: Models of Sociality after Idealism in Gadamer, Levinas, Rosenzweig, and Bonhoeffer" (2017). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. http://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/7047 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. From Object to Other: Models of Sociality after Idealism in Gadamer, Levinas, Rosenzweig, and Bonhoeffer by Christopher J. King A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy with a concentration in Philosophy and Religion College of Arts and Sciences University of South Florida Co-Major Professor: Lee Braver, Ph.D. Co-Major Professor: Michael DeJonge, Ph.D. Cass Fisher, Ph.D. Michael Morris, Ph.D. Date of Approval: November 3, 2017 Keywords: ontology, dialogue, intersubjectivity, anthropology,
    [Show full text]
  • Quantum Logical Causality, Category Theory, and the Metaphysics of Alfred North Whitehead
    Quantum Logical Causality, Category Theory, and the Metaphysics of Alfred North Whitehead Connecting Zafiris’ Category Theoretic Models of Quantum Spacetime and the Logical-Causal Formalism of Quantum Relational Realism Workshop Venue: Swiss Federal Institute of Technology (ETH) Chair for Philosophy (building RAC) Raemistrasse 36, 8001 Zurich Switzerland January 29 – 30, 2010 I. Aims and Motivation Recent work in the natural sciences—most notably in the areas of theoretical physics and evolutionary biology—has demonstrated that the lines separating philosophy and science have all but vanished with respect to current explorations of ‘fundamental’ questions (e.g., string theory, multiverse cosmologies, complexity-emergence theories, the nature of mind, etc.). The centuries-old breakdown of ‘natural philosophy’ into the divorced partners ‘philosophy’ and ‘science,’ therefore, must be rigorously re- examined. To that end, much of today’s most groundbreaking scholarship in the natural sciences has begun to include explicit appeals to interdisciplinary collaboration among the fields of applied natural sciences, mathematics and philosophy. This workshop will be dedicated to the question of how a philosophical-metaphysical theory can be fruitfully applied to basic conceptualizations in the natural sciences. More narrowly, we will explore the process oriented metaphysical scheme developed by philosopher and mathematician Alfred North Whitehead (1861-1947) and Michael Epperson’s application of this scheme to recent work in quantum mechanics, and the relation of these to Elias Zafiris’s category theoretic model of quantum event structures. Our aim is to give participants from various fields of expertise (see list below) the opportunity to exchange their specialized knowledge in the context of a collaborative exploration of the fundamental questions raised by recent scholarship in physics and mathematics.
    [Show full text]
  • HUI What Is a Digital Object Metaphilosophy.Pdf
    bs_bs_banner © 2012 The Author Metaphilosophy © 2012 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd Published by Blackwell Publishing Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK, and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA METAPHILOSOPHY Vol. 43, No. 4, July 2012 0026-1068 WHAT IS A DIGITAL OBJECT? YUK HUI Abstract: We find ourselves in a media-intensive milieu comprising networks, images, sounds, and text, which we generalize as data and metadata. How can we understand this digital milieu and make sense of these data, not only focusing on their functionalities but also reflecting on our everyday life and existence? How do these material constructions demand a new philosophical understand- ing? Instead of following the reductionist approaches, which understand the digital milieu as abstract entities such as information and data, this article pro- poses to approach it from an embodied perspective: objects. The article contrasts digital objects with natural objects (e.g., apples on the table) and technical objects (e.g., hammers) in phenomenological investigations, and proposes to approach digital objects from the concept of “relations,” on the one hand the material relations that are concretized in the development of mark-up languages, such as SGML, HTML, and XML, and on the other hand, Web ontologies, the temporal relations that are produced and conditioned by the artificial memories of data. Keywords: digital objects, phenomenology, metadata, Stiegler, Simondon. In this article I attempt to outline what I call digital objects, showing that a philosophical investigation is necessary by revisiting the history of philosophy and proposing that it is possible to develop a philosophy of digital objects.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Determinism in Physics Has No Implications for Free Will
    Why determinism in physics has no implications for free will Michael Esfeld University of Lausanne, Department of Philosophy [email protected] (draft 8 October 2017) (paper for the conference “Causality, free will, divine action”, Vienna, 12 to 15 Sept. 2017) Abstract This paper argues for the following three theses: (1) There is a clear reason to prefer physical theories with deterministic dynamical equations: such theories are both maximally simple and maximally rich in information, since given an initial configuration of matter and the dynamical equations, the whole (past and future) evolution of the configuration of matter is fixed. (2) There is a clear way how to introduce probabilities in a deterministic physical theory, namely as answer to the question of what evolution of a specific system we can reasonably expect under ignorance of its exact initial conditions. This procedure works in the same manner for both classical and quantum physics. (3) There is no cogent reason to subscribe to an ontological commitment to the parameters that enter the (deterministic) dynamical equations of physics. These parameters are defined in terms of their function for the evolution of the configuration of matter, which is defined in terms of relative particle positions and their change. Granting an ontological status to them does not lead to a gain in explanation, but only to artificial problems. Against this background, I argue that there is no conflict between determinism in physics and free will (on whatever conception of free will), and, in general, point out the limits of science when it comes to the central metaphysical issues.
    [Show full text]
  • Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Papers, 1646-1716
    http://oac.cdlib.org/findaid/ark:/13030/kt2779p48t No online items Finding Aid for the Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Papers, 1646-1716 Processed by David MacGill; machine-readable finding aid created by Caroline Cubé © 2003 The Regents of the University of California. All rights reserved. Finding Aid for the Gottfried 503 1 Wilhelm Leibniz Papers, 1646-1716 Finding Aid for the Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Papers, 1646-1716 Collection number: 503 UCLA Library, Department of Special Collections Manuscripts Division Los Angeles, CA Processed by: David MacGill, November 1992 Encoded by: Caroline Cubé Online finding aid edited by: Josh Fiala, October 2003 © 2003 The Regents of the University of California. All rights reserved. Descriptive Summary Title: Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Papers, Date (inclusive): 1646-1716 Collection number: 503 Creator: Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, Freiherr von, 1646-1716 Extent: 6 oversize boxes Repository: University of California, Los Angeles. Library. Dept. of Special Collections. Los Angeles, California 90095-1575 Abstract: Leibniz (1646-1716) was a philosopher, mathematician, and political advisor. He invented differential and integral calculus. His major writings include New physical hypothesis (1671), Discourse on metaphysics (1686), On the ultimate origin of things (1697), and On nature itself (1698). The collection consists of 35 reels of positive microfilm of more than 100,000 handwritten pages of manuscripts and letters. Physical location: Stored off-site at SRLF. Advance notice is required for access to the collection. Please contact the UCLA Library, Department of Special Collections Reference Desk for paging information. Language: English. Restrictions on Use and Reproduction Property rights to the physical object belong to the UCLA Library, Department of Special Collections.
    [Show full text]
  • Evaluating Object Manipulation Interaction Techniques in Mixed Reality: Tangible User Interfaces and Gesture
    2021 IEEE Virtual Reality and 3D User Interfaces (VR) Evaluating Object Manipulation Interaction Techniques in Mixed Reality: Tangible User Interfaces and Gesture Evren Bozgeyikli,* Lal “Lila” Bozgeyikli† School of Information University of Arizona subjective reality of the user [51]. ABSTRACT Although the aim is for the users to perceive the virtual content Tangible user interfaces (TUIs) have been widely studied in as part of their real-world surroundings, when they reach out to computer, virtual reality and augmented reality systems and are them and don’t feel anything physical in air, the illusion of the known to improve user experience in these mediums. However, reality of these virtual objects may be broken. Tangible user there have been few evaluations of TUIs in wearable mixed reality interfaces (TUIs) of matching forms and sizes can be promising in (MR). In this study, we present the results from a comparative increasing the tangibility of the digital experience in MR and study evaluating three object manipulation techniques in wearable helping users perceive that they are physically feeling the virtual MR: (1) Space-multiplexed identical-formed TUI (i.e., a physical content. Currently, there are three widely known off-the-shelf MR cube that acted as a dynamic tangible proxy with identical real headsets: Magic Leap One [47] that includes controller and virtual forms); (2) Time-multiplexed TUI (i.e., a tangible interaction, and Microsoft HoloLens [49] and Meta 2 [48] that controller that was used to manipulate virtual content); (3) Hand both include hand gesture interaction. gesture (i.e., reaching, pinching and moving the hand to Tangible interaction refers to interactions that exploit tangibility manipulate virtual content).
    [Show full text]
  • Perception and Representation in Leibniz
    PERCEPTION AND REPRESENTATION IN LEIBNIZ by Stephen Montague Puryear B.S., Mechanical Engineering, North Carolina State University, 1994 M.A., Philosophy, Texas A&M University, 2000 M.A., Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh, 2004 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Department of Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2006 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY This dissertation was presented by Stephen Montague Puryear It was defended on December 5, 2005 and approved by Nicholas Rescher University Professor of Philosophy Robert B. Brandom Distinguished Service Professor of Philosophy Stephen Engstrom Associate Professor of Philosophy J. E. McGuire Professor of History and Philosophy of Science Dissertation Director: Nicholas Rescher University Professor of Philosophy ii Copyright °c by Stephen Montague Puryear 2006 iii PERCEPTION AND REPRESENTATION IN LEIBNIZ Stephen Montague Puryear, Ph.D. University of Pittsburgh, 2006 Though Leibniz’s views about perception and representation go to the heart of his philosophy, they have received surprisingly little attention over the years and in many ways continue to be poorly understood. I aim to redress these shortcomings. The body of the work begins with an exploration of Leibniz’s proposed analysis of representation (Chapter 2). Here I argue that on this analysis representation consists in a kind of structural correspondence— roughly an isomorphism—between representation and thing represented. Special attention is given to the application of this analysis to the challenging cases of linguistic and mental representation. The next two chapters concern what I take to be the central issue of the work: the nature of distinct perception.
    [Show full text]
  • Creativity in the Metaphysics of Alfred North Whitehead
    CREATIVITY IN WIDTEHEAD'S l\1ETAPHYSICS CREATIVITY IN THE METAPHYSICS OF ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD By JEFFREY A. MCPHERSON, B.A.(Hons.) A Thesis Submitted to the School of Graduate Studies in Partial Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Arts © Copyright by Jeffrey A. McPherson, SEPTEMBER, 1996 MASTER OF ARTS (1996) McMaster University (Religious Studies) Hamilton, Ontario TITLE: Creativity in the Metaphysics of Alfred North Whitehead. AUTHOR: Jeffrey A. McPherson, B.A.(Hons.) (York University) SUPERVISOR: Dr. J.C. Robertson, Jr. NUMBER OF PAGES: vi, 127 ii ABSTRACT This is a study of the role that creativity plays in the metaphysics of Alfred North Whitehead ( 1861-1947). As the title generally indicates, there are two parts to this project. The first part develops an understanding of Whitehead's metaphysics through the careful analysis of two key texts, namely Religion in the Making ( 1926), and Process and Reality (1929). The second part examines and carefully analyses the role that creativity plays within this metaphysic. The second part focuses on two questions. The first question considers the ontological status which creativity requires to perform the role which it is given within the metaphysical system. The second question discusses implications of this status for creativity's relationship to God. This second section further discusses the implications of such an understanding of "process theology" for Christian theology in general. Specifically it comments on the various responses of theology to creatio ex nihilo and the problem of evil. This thesis concludes that creativity functions as an ultimate explanatory principle in Whitehead's metaphysics.
    [Show full text]
  • Quantum Mechanics and Free Will: Counter−Arguments
    Quantum mechanics and free will: counter−arguments Martín López−Corredoira Astronomisches Institut der Universitaet Basel, Venusstrasse 7, CH−4102−Binningen, Switzerland E−mail: [email protected] Abstract Since quantum mechanics (QM) was formulated, many voices have claimed this to be the basis of free will in the human beings. Basically, they argue that free will is possible because there is an ontological indeterminism in the natural laws, and that the mind is responsible for the wave function collapse of matter, which leads to a choice among the different possibilities for the body. However, I defend the opposite thesis, that free will cannot be defended in terms of QM. First, because indeterminism does not imply free will, it is merely a necessary condition but not enough to defend it. Second, because all considerations about an autonomous mind sending orders to the body is against our scientific knowledge about human beings; in particular, neither neurological nor evolutionary theory can admit dualism. The quantum theory of measurement can be interpreted without the intervention of human minds, but other fields of science cannot contemplate the mentalist scenario, so it is concluded that QM has nothing to say about the mind or free will, and its scientific explanation is more related to biology than to physics. A fatalistic or materialist view, which denies the possibility of a free will, makes much more sense in scientific terms. 1. Definition of free will First of all, we must clarify the meaning of the term to which we refer: Free will: a source totally detached from matter (detached from nature) which is the origin (cause) of options, thoughts, feelings,..
    [Show full text]
  • Embracing Determinism: the Benefits of Rejecting Free Will Belief
    Embracing Determinism: The Benefits of Rejecting Free Will Belief Steven Priddis A Thesis Submitted for the degree of Master of Research Western Sydney University 2017 Acknowledgements I would like to give thanks to my supervisor Dr John Hadley, for his expert advice in shaping both this thesis, and my development as a student and philosopher. I would also like to thank Dr Holly Priddis for her help not only in editing this thesis, but for raising a son that was capable of writing all these big words. Finally, I would like to thank Amp. We may not have freely chosen each other, but I’m glad we’re together all the same. This thesis wouldn’t have been possible without you. i Table of Contents Preface ............................................................................................................................... 1 Chapter 1 – The Defences of Free Will .............................................................................. 3 The Ancient Approaches ................................................................................................ 3 The Ancient Greek Philosophers................................................................................. 4 The Stoics .................................................................................................................... 5 The Christian Theologians ........................................................................................... 8 Critiquing the Ancient Approaches ........................................................................... 11 Hobbes
    [Show full text]
  • Spinoza and the Intellectual Dialogue with God-Nature
    CHAPTER 39 SPINOZA AND THE INTELLECTUAL DIALOGUE WITH GOD-NATURE my peace is mine, and it seeks to be actualized between you and me. not “mine” as in possessions, for it is freedom we seek: “mine” as in my in-born ability to offer it to another being. those who love know that love is inexhaustible, except when we don’t give it to another being. in that case it extinguishes itself like a candle in the rain. for there is grace in the-between of you and me and everywhere in this world. just look. just touch. the world will show you. in that sense, when “the tragic jew of Amsterdam,” as unamuno called baruch spinoza, said ‘deus sive natura,’ he was saying that to love god is to love nature and to love nature is to love god. in other words, all real life is meeting. spinoza said “all happiness or unhappiness solely depends upon the quality of the object to which we are attached by love.” this statement recognizes both the connection between happiness and love, and the independent objective reality of the outer world. the outer world is one of the elements that conditions the quality of our individual lives. for spinoza it is not all psychology, or a projection of our own inner consciousness: happiness is the existential dialogue between the inner and the outer. compare this with the popular saying: “if you change the way you look at things, the things you look at change.” this statement denies that there is an objective reality that exists independent of our perception of it.
    [Show full text]