The Dead-Alive Physicist Gedankenexperiment Debunked
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
The Case for Quantum Key Distribution
The Case for Quantum Key Distribution Douglas Stebila1, Michele Mosca2,3,4, and Norbert Lütkenhaus2,4,5 1 Information Security Institute, Queensland University of Technology, Brisbane, Australia 2 Institute for Quantum Computing, University of Waterloo 3 Dept. of Combinatorics & Optimization, University of Waterloo 4 Perimeter Institute for Theoretical Physics 5 Dept. of Physics & Astronomy, University of Waterloo Waterloo, Ontario, Canada Email: [email protected], [email protected], [email protected] December 2, 2009 Abstract Quantum key distribution (QKD) promises secure key agreement by using quantum mechanical systems. We argue that QKD will be an important part of future cryptographic infrastructures. It can provide long-term confidentiality for encrypted information without reliance on computational assumptions. Although QKD still requires authentication to prevent man-in-the-middle attacks, it can make use of either information-theoretically secure symmetric key authentication or computationally secure public key authentication: even when using public key authentication, we argue that QKD still offers stronger security than classical key agreement. 1 Introduction Since its discovery, the field of quantum cryptography — and in particular, quantum key distribution (QKD) — has garnered widespread technical and popular interest. The promise of “unconditional security” has brought public interest, but the often unbridled optimism expressed for this field has also spawned criticism and analysis [Sch03, PPS04, Sch07, Sch08]. QKD is a new tool in the cryptographer’s toolbox: it allows for secure key agreement over an untrusted channel where the output key is entirely independent from any input value, a task that is impossible using classical1 cryptography. QKD does not eliminate the need for other cryptographic primitives, such as authentication, but it can be used to build systems with new security properties. -
The Parallel Universes Interpretation of Cosmology
Cosmology, the Many Universes Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics and Immortality N H E PRINCE [email protected] July 1, 2016 Abstract Observational evidence suggests that the universe is infinite, geometrically flat, homogeneous and isotropic on large scales. Hence we should expect to find large numbers of identical copies of any object consistent with the laws of physics including conscious identities like people. Under suitable notions of continuity of identity, This would imply that immortality of these conscious identities is a consequence of functionalism. I argue that the same conclusion can be drawn using an Everett Deutsch interpretation of quantum mechanics. I also argue why this is the correct interpretation. Lewis’s “terrifying corollary” is reviewed and I discuss how Bostrom’s simulation argument, if correct, might mitigate our futures. 1 Introduction It has been referred to as “quantum physics dirty little secret” [1, p6] – perhaps because to publicise it might lead those people, who little understand it, to develop suicidal tendencies in the hope that they might get into a better universe – This is definitely not a good idea! We’ll look at this little secret in more detail later. But in order to do this we will need to develop some background. First it must be said that the word “worlds” is often used interchangeably for “universes” in the literature. It is not used to mean planets like our own parochial world. Also, the idea of an observation or experiment translates into ordinary language as “looking”, “listening”, “touching” etc. as well as for more technical approaches such as using Charge Coupled Devices to detect individual photons of light in astronomy or interferometry. -
John Von Neumann's “Impossibility Proof” in a Historical Perspective’, Physis 32 (1995), Pp
CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by SAS-SPACE Published: Louis Caruana, ‘John von Neumann's “Impossibility Proof” in a Historical Perspective’, Physis 32 (1995), pp. 109-124. JOHN VON NEUMANN'S ‘IMPOSSIBILITY PROOF’ IN A HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE ABSTRACT John von Neumann's proof that quantum mechanics is logically incompatible with hidden varibales has been the object of extensive study both by physicists and by historians. The latter have concentrated mainly on the way the proof was interpreted, accepted and rejected between 1932, when it was published, and 1966, when J.S. Bell published the first explicit identification of the mistake it involved. What is proposed in this paper is an investigation into the origins of the proof rather than the aftermath. In the first section, a brief overview of the his personal life and his proof is given to set the scene. There follows a discussion on the merits of using here the historical method employed elsewhere by Andrew Warwick. It will be argued that a study of the origins of von Neumann's proof shows how there is an interaction between the following factors: the broad issues within a specific culture, the learning process of the theoretical physicist concerned, and the conceptual techniques available. In our case, the ‘conceptual technology’ employed by von Neumann is identified as the method of axiomatisation. 1. INTRODUCTION A full biography of John von Neumann is not yet available. Moreover, it seems that there is a lack of extended historical work on the origin of his contributions to quantum mechanics. -
Consciousness and the Collapse of the Wave Function∗
Consciousness and the Collapse of the Wave Function∗ David J. Chalmers† and Kelvin J. McQueen‡ †New York University ‡Chapman University May 7, 2021 Abstract Does consciousness collapse the quantum wave function? This idea was taken seriously by John von Neumann and Eugene Wigner but is now widely dismissed. We develop the idea by combining a mathematical theory of consciousness (integrated information theory) with an account of quantum collapse dynamics (continuous spontaneous localization). Simple versions of the theory are falsified by the quantum Zeno effect, but more complex versions remain compatible with empirical evidence. In principle, versions of the theory can be tested by experiments with quantum com- puters. The upshot is not that consciousness-collapse interpretations are clearly correct, but that there is a research program here worth exploring. Keywords: wave function collapse, consciousness, integrated information theory, continuous spontaneous localization ∗Forthcoming in (S. Gao, ed.) Consciousness and Quantum Mechanics (Oxford University arXiv:2105.02314v1 [quant-ph] 5 May 2021 Press). Authors are listed in alphabetical order and contributed equally. We owe thanks to audiences starting in 2013 at Amsterdam, ANU, Cambridge, Chapman, CUNY, Geneva, G¨ottingen,Helsinki, Mississippi, Monash, NYU, Oslo, Oxford, Rio, Tucson, and Utrecht. These earlier presentations have occasionally been cited, so we have made some of them available at consc.net/qm. For feedback on earlier versions, thanks to Jim Holt, Adrian Kent, Kobi Kremnizer, Oystein Linnebo, and Trevor Teitel. We are grateful to Maaneli Derakhshani and Philip Pearle for their help with the mathematics of collapse models, and especially to Johannes Kleiner, who coauthored section 5 on quantum integrated information theory. -
Arxiv:1806.01736V3 [Quant-Ph] 17 Dec 2018 State Originally Received
Unconstrained Summoning for relativistic quantum information processing Adrian Kent Centre for Quantum Information and Foundations, DAMTP, Centre for Mathematical Sciences, University of Cambridge, Wilberforce Road, Cambridge, CB3 0WA, U.K. and Perimeter Institute for Theoretical Physics, 31 Caroline Street North, Waterloo, ON N2L 2Y5, Canada. (Dated: December 18, 2018) We define a summoning task to require propagating an unknown quantum state to a point in space-time belonging to a set determined by classical inputs at points in space-time. We consider the classical analogue, in which a known classical state must be returned at precisely one allowed point. We show that, when the inputs are unconstrained, any summoning task that is possible in the classical case is also possible in the quantum case. INTRODUCTION In the not necessarily distant future, many or most significant economic decisions may depend on algorithms that process information arriving around the world as efficiently and quickly as possible, given light speed signalling constraints. Such algorithms will need to decide not only whether to make a trade, but also when and where. Quantum money enables efficient transactions, by allowing a delocalized quantum money token effectively to be “summoned” to a given space-time point as a result of information distributed through space-time. There are also alternative technological solutions [1] in the form of token schemes that do not require long term quantum state storage and in some embodiments are based entirely on classical communication. This paper defines types of summoning task that naturally arise in relativistic economies, and shows that for an important and natural class of these tasks the two technologies have the same functionality. -
David Bohm's Theory of the Implicate Order: Implications for Holistic Thought Processes*
ISSUES IN INTEGRATVE STUDIES No. 13, pp. 1-23 (1995) David Bohm's Theory of the Implicate Order: Implications for Holistic Thought Processes* by Irene J. Dabrowski, Ph.D. Division of Social Services, St. John's University, New York Abstract: David Bohm's theory of quantum physics, which focuses on the schism between matter and consciousness, is discussed in terms of positivist knowledge and the interdisciplinary holistic paradigm. This paper examines how scientific and educational holism, predicated on the relationship between knowledge and reality, fosters innovative approaches such as evolutionary learning, a pedagogical application of general systems theory. In pursuit of right- brain thought and a unified knowledge base, diverse modes of inquiry are presented in the context of Bohm's thesis of an implicate order. Given that holistic thought processes generate a reality-based knowledge, problem-solving styles are examined, which reveal the holistic orientation of proactive problem-solving. Interdisciplinary dialogue is identified as an essential way for moving toward holistic expressions and networks of thought. NEW VERSIONS of the sciences as well as other academic disciplines are being formulated in terms of a naturalistic mode of inquiry (Lincoln, 1989; Palm, 1979). The emergent post-positivist paradigm is directed toward a holistic conception of reality, replacing the Cartesian, mechanistic mode of conceptualization (Capra, 1982; Guba, 1981; Lincoln, 1989; Turner, 1990), In fact, characteristics of the "whole paradigm" are being identified in a variety of disciplines (Lincoln, 1989, p. 69). New dimensions include a refocusing from simple to complex realities, the movement from the mechanical to the holographic, and the emphasis from linear to mutual causality (Lincoln & Guba, 1985; Macy, 1991; Schwartz & Ogilvy, 1979). -
Testing Causal Quantum Theory
Testing Causal Quantum Theory Adrian Kent∗ Centre for Quantum Information and Foundations, DAMTP, Centre for Mathematical Sciences, University of Cambridge, Wilberforce Road, Cambridge, CB3 0WA, United Kingdom and Perimeter Institute for Theoretical Physics, 31 Caroline Street North, Waterloo, ON N2L 2Y5, Canada. Causal quantum theory assumes that measurements or collapses are well-defined physical pro- cesses, localised in space-time, and never give perfectly reliable outcomes and that the outcome of one measurement only influences the outcomes of others within its future light cone. Although the theory has unusual properties, it is not immediately evident that it is inconsistent with experiment to date. I discuss its implications and experimental tests. INTRODUCTION There are fairly compelling theoretical and experimental reasons [1{17] to believe that nature violates local causality and that local hidden variable theories are incorrect. However, while loopholes remain, the case is not quite conclusive. In particular, the collapse locality loophole [18] remains largely untested. Moreover, causal quantum theory [18] is a theoretically interesting example of a local hidden variable theory that remains consistent with Bell experiments to date by exploiting this loophole. Causal quantum theory assumes that measurements or collapses are well-defined physical processes, localised in space-time, and never give perfectly reliable outcomes. Unlike standard quantum theory, it also assumes that mea- surement outcomes respect a strong form of Minkowski or Einstein causality, in that the outcome of one measurement only affects the probability distributions for the outcomes of other measurements within its future light cone. This gives it very peculiar properties, which evoke the suspicion that it must already be excluded by experiments other than Bell experiments and/or cosmological observations. -
The Hidden- Variables Controversy in Quantum Physics
Phys Educ Vol 14, 1979 Prlnted in Great Brltaln CONTROVERSIESIN PHYSICS aggressiveness which resembles more the defence of orthodoxy of one ideology than a spirit of scientific objectivity’ (Jauch 1973, introduction). The hidden- ‘The entirely reasonable question, Are there hidden- variable theories consistent with quantum theory and variables if so whatare their characteristics?,has been unfortunately clouded by emotionalism’ (Ballentine controversy in 1970, p374). Perhaps some of the acrimonv which has surrounded this debate can be seen in the following quantum physics comment on the workof hidden-variable theorists made by Leon Rosenfeld, an eminent physicist and TREVOR J PINCH defender of the orthodoxview of quantum theory: Science Studies Centre, Universityof Bath ‘That suchirrational dogmatists shouldhurl the very accusation of irrationality and dogmatism at the defenders of the common-sense, uncommitted attitude of other scientists is the crowning paradox which gives Recent studies of controversies in science have shown a touch of comedy to a controversy so distressingly that they are not always settled by appeals to Nature pointless and untimely’ (Rosenfeld 1958, p658). alone. Social and political factors as well as scientific These are hardly the sorts of comments we would factors often combine to produce the outcome(see for expect to follow from unproblematicreadings of example Forman 1971, Collins 1975, Frankel 1976 Nature’s secrets. So what was at stake in this dispute? and Wynne 1976). The ‘truth’, it seems, emerges from To answer this question we need to go back to the whatcan be asurprisingly volatile struggle, very revolution in physics brought about by the develop- unlike the rarified atmosphere of noblesse within ment of quantum theoryin the 1920s. -
Or, How to Share a Quantum Secret in Spacetime
Localizing and excluding quantum informa- tion; or, how to share a quantum secret in spacetime Patrick Hayden1 and Alex May2 1Stanford University 2The University of British Columbia October 15, 2019 When can quantum information be localized to each of a collection of spacetime regions, while also excluded from another collection of regions? We answer this question by defining and analyzing the localize-exclude task, in which a quantum system must be localized to a collection of authorized regions while also being excluded from a set of unauthorized regions. This task is a spacetime analogue of quantum secret sharing, with authorized and unauthorized regions replacing authorized and unauthorized sets of parties. Our analysis yields the first quantum secret sharing scheme for arbitrary ac- cess structures for which the number of qubits required scales polynomially with the number of authorized sets. We also study a second related task called state-assembly, in which shares of a quantum system are requested at sets of spacetime points. We fully characterize the conditions under which both the localize-exclude and state-assembly tasks can be achieved, and give explicit protocols. Finally, we propose a cryptographic application of these tasks which we call party-independent transfer. Patrick Hayden: [email protected] arXiv:1806.04154v4 [quant-ph] 14 Oct 2019 Alex May: [email protected] Accepted in Quantum 2019-07-02, click title to verify 1 Contents 1 Introduction2 2 Localizing and excluding quantum information4 2.1 Localizing quantum information to many regions . 4 2.2 Localizing and excluding quantum information . 10 3 State-assembly 19 3.1 State-assembly with authorized regions . -
Depictions of Quantum Reality in Kent's Interpretation of Quantum
Depictions of Quantum Reality in Kent's Interpretation of Quantum Theory Brendan Marsh∗ Department of Applied Mathematics and Theoretical Physics, University of Cambridge, Wilberforce Road, Cambridge, CB3 0WA, U.K. At present, quantum theory leaves unsettled which quantities ontologically, physically exist in a quantum system. Do observables such as energy and position have meaningful values only at the precise moment of measurement, as in the Copenhagen interpretation? Or is position always definite and guided by the wave function, as in de Broglie-Bohm pilot wave theory? In the language of Bell, what are the \beables" of quantum theory and what values may they take in space and time? This is the quantum reality problem. A definitive answer requires not just describing which physical quantities exist in a quantum system, but describing what configurations of those quantities in space and time are allowed, and with what probability those configurations occur. Adrian Kent sets out a new vision of quantum theory along these lines. His interpretation supplements quantum theory to infer the value of physical quantities in spacetime from the asymptotic late-time behavior of the quantum system. In doing so, a Lorentz-covariant and single-world solution to the quantum reality problem is achieved. In this paper, the framework of Kent's interpretation is presented from the ground up. After a broad overview, a derivation of the generalized Aharonov-Bergmann- Lebowitz (ABL) rule is provided before applying Kent's interpretation to toy model systems, in both relativistic and non-relativistic settings. By adding figures and discussion, a broad introduction is provided to Kent's proposed interpretation of quantum theory. -
Mistrustful Quantum Cryptography
Mistrustful Quantum Cryptography Adrian Kent Centre for Quantum Computation DAMTP, University of Cambridge Two lectures for MIT Independent Activities Period. 2pm on 28.01.03 and 29.01.0; Sponsored by the CMI Beyond key distribution: mistrustful cryptography • Life requires controlled information exchange between not necessarily trusting parties. (Some cynics might say life is controlled information exchange between not necessarily trusting parties.) • For example: trustable electoral systems that allow secret ballot, secure auctions, tax collection that preserves privacy, remote authentication to a computer, decisions on joint corporate (or other) ventures, job interviews, “helping the police with their enquiries”, … • Cryptography can help, at least with some of these, by regulating the information flow – instead of trusting the other party, you need only trust the cryptosystem, which if well designed is provably secure modulo reasonable assumptions. Mistrustful cryptography: often referred to as “Post Cold War” cryptography • Cold War cryptography: your aim is to communicate with your agents behind enemy lines. • You (let’s hope) trust your agents, or at any rate trust them enough to want the message to get to them: the worry is about enemy eavesdroppers. • Whereas in the post Cold War world… Mistrustful cryptography and physics • Classical cryptographers have identified key “primitives” – elementary tasks that can be used as building blocks for many mistrustful cryptographic purposes (and are often very useful in their own right). • Given the example of key distribution, where quantum information allows classically unattainable security, we naturally want to understand which mistrustful tasks quantum information can be useful for. We don’t! (Mostly. Yet.) • More generally, we want to know what physics can do for cryptography. -
Oppenheimer: a Life April 22, 1904-February 18, 1967
Oppenheimer: A Life April 22, 1904-February 18, 1967 an online centennial exhibit of J. Robert Oppenheimer http://ohst.berkeley.edu/oppenheimer/exhibit/ This print edition of the online exhibit is free for use, reproduction, and distribution for educational purposes as long as this cover page and the acknowlegments page are included. It may not be altered or sold. For other usage questions, please contact the Office for History of Science and Technology, Univer- sity of California, Berkeley, at http://ohst.berkeley.edu. All image copyrights are retained by their hold- ers. © 2004 by The Regents of the University of California. 1 Oppenheimer: A Life April 22, 1904-February 18, 1967 Introduction As Alice Kimball Smith and Charles Weiner have noted, “Part of Oppenheimer’s attraction, at first for his friends and later for the public, was that he did not project the popularly held image of the scientist as cold, objective, rational and therefore above human frailty, an image that scientists themselves fostered by underplaying their per- sonal histories and the disorder that precedes the neat scientific conclusion.” There is a cacophony of conflicting descriptions of Oppenheimer – as friends have remembered him, as historians have analyzed him. He has been labeled both warm and cold, friendly and condescending, affable as well as hurtful. Learning Sanskrit and cultivating the air of an aesthete, as a young professor he stretched the bounds of the scientist’s persona. Yet in the space of a decade, the otherworldly theorist was transformed into a political insider par excellence. His fellow scientists remembered him as a visionary and capable leader at Los Alamos, while his security hearing brought to light foolish mistakes in judgment and human relationships.