<<

The Social and Technological Dimensions of and Related Theoretical Concepts for Learning, Education, and Human Activity Author(s): Roy D. Pea Source: The Journal of the Learning Sciences, Vol. 13, No. 3, Scaffolding (2004), pp. 423-451 Published by: Taylor & Francis, Ltd. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1466943 . Accessed: 14/07/2013 15:12

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

.

Taylor & Francis, Ltd. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of the Learning Sciences.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions THE JOURNALOF THE LEARNING SCIENCES, 13(3), 423-451 Copyright? 2004, LawrenceErlbaum Associates, Inc.

COMMENTARY

The Social and Technological Dimensions of Scaffolding and Related TheoreticalConcepts for Learning, Education,and HumanActivity

Roy D. Pea School of Education StanfordUniversity

I amperhaps not the only one who feels thatthe conceptof scaffoldinghas become so broadin its meanings in the field of educationalresearch and the learningsciences thatit has become unclearin its significance.Perhaps the field has put too much of a burdenon the term, and we need a more differentiatedontology to make progress. Perhapsscaffolding has become a proxy for any culturalpractices associated with advancingperformance, knowledge, and skills whethersocial, material,or repro- ducible patternsof interactivity(as in softwaresystems) are involved.This is surely too much complexity to take on at once. Given these burdensat the level of a scien- tific accountof learningby the individual,I feel it is prematureto be extendingscaf- folding considerationsby metaphoricalextension to the level of a whole classroom of learnersor even to a culturallevel, as Davis andMiyake (this issue) suggestin their introductoryessay. I first see whetherI can garer some clarificationsand leverage fromuses of the termscaffolding for specific instancesand classes of its uses by indi- vidual learners(where the articles in this issue focus their attention). As with many such concepts thatare felt to have useful power in theoreticaland practicalschemes, it will be worthwhileto do some historicalexcavation, identify and circumscribe the early uses and roots of the concept, and then determine

Correspondenceand requestsfor reprintsshould be sent to Roy D. Pea, School of Education,Stan- ford University,Cubberly Hall, Stanford,CA 94305. E-mail: [email protected]

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 424 PEA whether in the rich body of work that has developed since its origins roughly 30 years ago one can craft a conceptualmap relating scaffolding and its many affili- ated concepts such that the vitality of the issues raised in its initial conceptualiza- tion can be preservedand even extended. My goals for this article were to first provide a personalview on the history of scaffolding and relatedconcepts in its semiotic field and to then develop a frame- work for what I believe to be its definitionalcore and contrastiveterms and the pri- mary issues and opportunitiesthey presentfor us as learningscientists and educa- tors. I then consider the contributionsmade and the issues raised in this issue's collection of articles in terms of this framework.Reading the articles themselves will be importantfor the reader,as my goal is not to review them here but to refer- ence them. Collectively, the four articles by Reiser, Quintanaet al., Tabak,and Sherin, Reiser, and Edelson (this issue) provide illuminating conceptualizations that help advance the theory of scaffolding for instructionalsupport, primarily with a focus on learninghow to do scientific inquiry in the middle to high school grades. They offer a distinction between "structuring"and "problematizing" mechanisms of scaffolding for studentwork (Reiser, this issue), a scaffolding de- sign frameworkencompassing an impressive arrayof categories arounddifferent componentsof scientific inquiryillustrated with many softwaresystems (Quintana et al., this issue), the concepts of "distributedscaffolding" and "synergy"between differentcomponents of distributedscaffolding (Tabak,this issue), and an analyti- cal frameworkarguing that scaffolding should be conceived of as a comparative analysis to be performedon learning interactions(Sherin et al., this issue) rather than software features or situations.There is much to be learned from these arti- cles, as they provide a synoptic view of scaffolding researchin science learning. I recall firstbecoming awareof the concept of scaffolding when I was a doctoral studentin Jerome Bruner'slaboratory on South ParksRoad in the Departmentof ExperimentalPsychology at OxfordUniversity around 1975. The context was one in which a numberof graduatestudents, postdocs, and visiting fellows (including CatherineUrwin, Michael Scaife, John Churcher,Alan Leslie, Chris Pratt,Alison Garton,Renira Huxley, KathySylva, andlater visiting studentsAlison Gopnikand Susan Sugarman)were studying the ontogenesis of language and thought and es- pecially the emergenceof syntaxfrom the early protolanguageand single word pe- riod of child language. Yet others were studying imitation, perception,play, and other developmentalphenomena. We regularlyread papers together,had a lively weekly seminar series, and reviewed and analyzed video data and its interpreta- tions together. The termscaffolding was one introducedby David with JerryBruner and Gail Ross in an articlepublished in 1976 and the relatedidea "in the air"among our Oxfordgroup was one thatJerry called "formats."The notion was thatone of the po- tential explanationsfor how it is thatbabies acquiremeaning in early parent-child interactionis that there are regularly structuredsituations in which the range of

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions SOCIAL DIMENSIONS 425 meanings is actually quite limited and that these simple formatsprovide a highly constrainedsituation in which the child can bootstrapsome of the conventions of turn taking and meaning making with words that are requiredof a language user (e.g., Bruner,1975a, 1975b, 1977). Brunerand Sherwood (1976) illustratedthis line of argumentusing data from peekaboo interactionsbetween a motherand child. In Wood et al.'s (1976) article, the term scaffolding was first used, and it de- scribes how an interactionbetween a tutorand a child concerninghow to construct a wooden pyramidalpuzzle employs "a 'scaffolding' process that enables a child or novice to solve a problem,carry out a task or achieve a goal which would be be- yond his unassistedefforts" (p. 90). Formatsfor early language thus provided a form of scaffolding for learning to use words and the acquisitionof meaning. In bothof these conceptualizations,whether mother-infant interaction in the ser- vice of languagedevelopment or for the developmentof the puzzle-solving behav- iors describedin the Woodet al. (1976) article,the firstthing to notice is thatthe situ- ations of learningare neitherformal educationalnor "designed"in the traditional sense ofthe term(even ifthe puzzles were designed,as Tabak,this issue, notes). Such interactionsas we were studyingwere ones we conceivedto be naturallyoccurring in an informalcontext and an expressionof one of the socioculturallygrounded activi- ties typical of at least some families in Westernsocieties. Needless to say, the scaf- folding achieved in these mother-infantencounters was not computermediated. The work that the concept scaffolding is intendedto do in these psychologists' ac- counts of humandevelopment is to bringto one's attentionthe functionthat particu- lar behaviorson the mother'spart appear to play in enabling the performanceof a more complicatedact thanwould have otherwisebeen possible. In this sense, scaf- folding appearsto be an aptturn of phraseas bothnoun and verb-noun because it is a structure,guided in specific formby tacitassessment of a child's independentcapa- bilities andneeds, andmounted temporarily on thelearner's behalf until the child can self-sufficientlyproduce the behavioron his or herown-and verbbecause scaffold- ing is also a processbecause different aspects of an activitywill need to be scaffolded in the conduct of performance over time unless independent performance is achieved.If the parentcontinued to do such structuringonce the child becomes capa- ble of autonomousactivities, one would find it strange. It was also currentat the time for our Oxford Groupand others such as Wood's group at Nottinghamto be readingand thinkingabout the philosophy of language and accounts more broadly of the psychology and developmentof language. We were reading attemptsby Patricia Greenfield (Greenfield & Smith, 1976), John Dore (1972), ElizabethBates (1976), and othersto make sense of how it is that in- fants come to speak not only single words but also eventually sentences. So ac- counts of how to do things with words (J. L. Austin), of speech acts (J. Searle), of word meaning-as-use(L. Wittgenstein),and of functionalaccounts of language in the developmentof thinking(Vygotsky, G. de Laguna) were of vibrantinterest to

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 426 PEA us. We wantedto know how the baby crackedthe linguistic code and became able to do productivethings with words in interaction,and we were unsatisfied with Chomsky's (1966) nativist account of language acquisition. It is in this vein that the role of Vygotsky's (1978) concept of the zone of proxi- mal development (ZPD) in conceptualizationsof scaffolding is noteworthy.De- fined as the zone of activity in which a person can produce with assistance what they cannot producealone (or can only producewith difficulty), the ZPD concept depended on a view of human developmentthat had a numberof importantand distinctiveproperties. The first central propertyis Vygotsky's (1962) sociohistorical conceptualiza- tion of the developmentof language and concepts. Unlike Piaget, who was a ge- netic Kantianarguing for the child's constructionof the necessarycategories of ex- perience (time, space, causality) from largely individualisticinteractions with the physical and representationalworlds (Toulmin, 1972), Vygotsky as a Marxistwas quite appositeto the view thathuman nature is a given. As MarxWartofsky (1983) famously pointed out, there is solid historicalevidence of the world's of the child as much as the child's constructionof the world: "Childrenare, or be- come, what they are taken to be by others, and what they come to take themselves to be, in the course of their social communicationand interactionwith others"(p. 190). I took this argumentto provide a vital issue for humanlearning augmented with informationtechnologies:

Accordingto thistheory, human nature is nota productof environmentalforces, but is of ourown makingas a societyand is continuallyin the processof "becoming." Humankindis reshapedthrough a dialectic,or "conversation"of reciprocalinflu- ences: Our productive activities change the world, thereby changing the ways in whichthe world can changeus. By shapingnature and how ourinteractions with it aremediated, we changeourselves. (Pea, 1987, p. 93)

Second, as Vygotsky would have it, psychological development progresses from an interpsychological to an intrapsychological plane-it is through the child's experiencesof participatingin activitiesthat are initially externallyaccessi- ble that the structuresand content of mental life that can be played out internally become possible, an account reminiscentof Wittgenstein's(1958) conception of learningas participationin "formsof life":

Thevery essence of culturaldevelopment is in thecollision of maturecultural forms of behaviorwith the primitiveforms that characterizethe child's behavior. (Vygotsky,1981, p. 151)

It was perhapsnot until Michael Cole, John-Steiner,Scribner, and Souberman's translationand publicationof selected Vygotsky essays in the landmark1978 vol-

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions SOCIALDIMENSIONS 427 ume, Mind in Society: The Developmentof Higher Mental Processes, prompting the philosopherStephen Toulmin (1978) to call Vygotsky "theMozart of Psychol- ogy," that the fertility of the ZPD concept was made broadly evident to Western psychologists and educational theorists. Michael Cole collaboratorJoe Glick's (1983) chapteron "Piaget,Vygotsky andWerner" helps set a context for the arrival of this work on the Americanscene and why it took root so quickly in an intellec- tual environmentin which "fixedcapacity" conceptions of intelligence were losing favor. Glick distinguished "Vygotsky I" of Thought and Language (Vygotsky, 1962), a book thatVygotsky assembledhimself duringhis lifetime, and "Vygotsky II" of Mind in Society (1978), an editorialconstruction selected for its contempo- raryrelevance to Americanpsychology. (I cannotexplore this distinctionhere, but I recommendit to interestedreaders, especially those not enamoredby the "inter- nalization"metaphor with which Vygotsky has come to be identifiedwhereby cul- turalinfluences are interpersonallyinculcated and subsequently"internalized.")

InMind in Society(Vygotsky II), the underlying conceptual object appears to be the mannerin whichsign systemstransform organism-environment relations and the meansby whichmind becomes socialized (Glick, 1983, p. 43).

Glick (1983) noted that the editors depicted these concepts by making several observationsafter first quoting Vygotsky:

"The specializationof the hand-this implies the tool, and the tool implies specific humanactivity, the transforming reaction of manon nature...theanimal merely uses externalnature, and brings about changes in it simplyby his presence;man, by his changes,makes it servehis ends,masters it. Thisis thefinal, essential distinction be- tweenman and other animals." Vygotsky brilliantly extended this concept of media- tionin human-environmentinteraction to theuse of signsas well as tools.Like tool systems,sign systems(language, writing, number systems) are created by societies over the course of humanhistory and change with the form of society and the level of its culturaldevelopment. Vygotsky believed thatthe interalization of culturallypro- duced sign systems brings about behaviortransformations and forms the bridge be- tween early and laterforms of individualdevelopment. Thus for Vygotsky, in the tra- dition of Marx and Engels, the mechanism of individual development is rooted in society and culture. (Vygotsky, 1978, Introduction,p. 7)

Glick (1983) also highlighted the importance to American psychology of Vygotsky's process-orientedapproach to evaluatingmental capacity in Vygotsky's conceptionof ZPD testing. Vygotsky's (1978) focus on the social foundationsof in- dividualhigher mental functioning is exemplifiedin the ZPD concept, which he de- fined as the distancebetween a child's "actualdevelopmental level as determinedby independentproblem solving" and the higher level revealedin "potentialdevelop- ment as determinedthrough problem solving underadult guidance or in collabora-

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 428 PEA tion with more able peers" (p. 86). Vygotsky providedexamples of children with equivalentindependent problem solving who, when dynamicallyassessed, havedif- ferentZPDs, and he considersthe level of potentialdevelopment more relevantfor instructionthan the actual independentdevelopmental level. By the time of a widely read Rogoff and Wertsch(1984) volume on Children's Learning in the "Zone of Proximal Development" (also see Wertsch, 1978, who cited Wood et al., 1976), the ZPD was becoming a fundamentalcomponent of the learning and education research literature.1Inspired not only by Vygotsky but work in a similarvein by the clinical psychologist ReuvenFeuerstein,2 Ann Brown and colleagues (e.g., Brown & Ferrara, 1985; Campione, 1989; Campione & Brown, 1984, 1990; Campione,Brown, Ferrara,& Bryant, 1984; for theirconnec- tions with Michael Cole's "Laboratoryfor ComparativeHuman Cognition,"see Cole & Griffin, 1983) were workingon what they called "dynamicassessment" in which a cascading sequence of hints was providedto enable a dynamic assessment of how much supporta learnerneeded to complete various benchmarktasks. A preeminent example of work in this era was Scardamaliaand Bereiter's (1983, 1985) researchusing what they have called "proceduralfacilitation" as a pedagogicaltechnique to supportthe use of more advancedwriting strategies(also see Applebee & Langer, 1983, on "instructionalscaffolding" for readingand writ- ing). Proceduralfacilitators were at first physical note cards with lead-in compo- nents to sentences thatwere designed to provide structuringdevices to scaffold the young writer's writing activities and as such were explicit models of more ad- vanced forms of writing.There was no questionin this work thatthe proceduralfa- cilitators were intendedto be but a temporaryadjunct in the writing process. Pea and Kurland(1987) reviewed the state of the art at this period in bringingtogether developmentalunderstanding of the writing process with the new computerwrit- ing tools of adults and industrytoward what they called "developmentalwriting environments"that would directly facilitate the developmentof writing skills and

1Asreported in Gindis (1997), EducationalResource InformationCenter (managed by the U.S. De- partmentof Education)records revealed three times more referencesto Vygotskian researchin educa- tion than Piagetianresearch. 2ReuvenFeuerstein is a clinical psychologistwho studiedwith JeanPiaget and has for yearsbeen Ed- ucation Professorat Israel's Bar Ian University.Feuerstein's inspiring work on the social and cultural conditionsfor modifiableintelligence was rootedin his experiencesin the 1940s as codirectorand teacher in the School for Disadvantagedand Disturbed Children in Bucharestand his workwith child survivorsof concentrationcamps. Feuerstein's theory of structuralcognitive modifiability and the Feuersteinmethod, which he calls "instrumentalenrichment" involves emergent practices of dynamicassessment in which he places so called retardedchildren and adults(many with Down's syndrome)with often dramaticlearning resultsin whathe calls "shapingenvironments" that provide structured mediation to enrichthe qualityof theirinteractions with otherssuch as parents,teachers, caregivers, and peers so thattheir experiences can be graspedand integratedmeaningfully (e.g., Feuerstein,Hoffman, Rand, & Miller, 1980; Feuerstein, Rand,& Hoffman, 1979; also see Kozulin& Rand,2000; Lidz, 1987). For morerecent work on dynamic assessment,see Pellegrino,Chudowsky, and Glaser (2001).

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions SOCIAL DIMENSIONS 429 not only be useful for text production(see Pea, 1987, for a relatedanalysis of cog- nitive for mathematicslearning). Inspiredby these efforts, Hawkins and Pea (1987) developed the INQUIREsoftware system for inquiryprocess sup- ports in bridgingchildren's everyday and scientific thinkingwith modules such as Questions, Notes, Schemes, and Patterns. I believe thatthe seeds for the diffusion of the concept of scaffolding are already latent in Vygotsky's (1962) influentialwritings, for unlike the child language and play work from Bruner,Wood, and othersin which the concept was developed as a prospective mechanism of human development in naturallyoccurring activities and not designed or technologically mediatedones, Vygotsky's conceptions of hu- man developmentbrought together the informaland the formal,the naturaland the designed, to achieve his theoretical ends. For in Vygotsky's (1962, 1978) view, even the naturallyoccurring interactions in which the mother scaffolds the baby were culturallyconstituted productions with a history thatmade them akin in kind to the more historically recent instructionalinterventions in formal education by which we seek to teach a scientific view of concepts. So scaffolding was destined to become a concept, fueled with a Vygotskian (1978) sociohistoricalview of de- velopment,which is applied so broadlyas to encompass featuresof computersoft- ware (e.g., Tikhomirov,1981; Pea, 1985a, 1985b), curriculumstructures, conver- sational devices such questions, and physically literal examples of scaffolding the learningof a complex motor activity like tennis (in which one may physically as- sist the novice tennis player,helping position the body, arm,and racketto facilitate a sense of making a first racket stroke). Nonetheless, there are noteworthydiffer- ences between the ongoing culturalpractices of a community in which informal scaffolding takes place in adult-child interactionpatterns and the scaffolding in- corporatedin formalized activities within systems of designed books, software, materialsfor learning and other artifactscrafted specifically to promote learning activities. I believe that we have two primaryaxes for organizingthe theoreticalcontribu- tions to supportsfor the processes of learning. One axis is social and most con- cerned with interactive responsiveness that is contingent on the needs of the learner,providing resources that enable the learnerto do more thanhe or she would alone. The other axis is technological and about designed artifacts,written about so articulatelyin HerbertSimon's (1969) The Sciences of the Artificial. For many of the contributionsto the theory and research on human develop- ment, learning, and education, these two axes may be more or less dominantin their conceptualizations.For early language and conceptualdevelopment, I argue that the social conception of between-people scaffolding and supportfor learning is not primarilyabout the uses of technological artifactsbut about social practices that have arisen over millennia in parentingand other forms of caring. More recently,as computertools have become increasinglyused for supporting learningand educationalprocesses in school and beyond, the concept of scaffold-

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 430 PEA ing has been more commonly employed to describe what features of computer tools and the processes employing them are doing for learning. The theoreticalchallenge is thatfor humankind, tools andsymbolizing technolo- gies (such as writtenlanguage and number systems) areamong our most significant culturalachievements and, as such, they have become partof the culturalresources that we utilize to propagate society across generations, providing significant value-addedto the social processes of between-people supportand caring in the learningprocess. Also, in online learningenvironments that are mediatedby com- puter technologies and computer-basedversions of symbolizing technologies for representinglinguistic, mathematical,scientific, and other concepts and relation- ships-but nonetheless incorporatingbetween-people supportcomponents-the ways in which scaffolding is made possible are extraordinarilydiverse. These two threadsof social process and tool/mediatingprocess in the scaffold- ing concept came together most noticeably for Western conceptualizations of learningand education through the translatedwritings of Vygotsky in Thoughtand Language (1962) and Mind in Society (1978). Perhapsas Brunerwrote the Intro- ductionto Thoughtand Languagefor publicationin 1962, his first encounterswith Vygotsky's considerationsin these newly translatedwritings came to play a semi- nal role in his later work with Wood and Ross and in language development as well. Vygotsky's concerns were also carriedforward in the work of his students Luria(Cole, 1978) and Leon'tiev (1981) and in activity theorysince thattime (e.g., Engestr6m, 1987; Engestr6m,Miettinen, & Punamaki, 1999) as well as cultural psychology more broadly (Cole, 1996).

FRAMEWORKFOR THE DEFINITIONOF SCAFFOLDING

Like several of the authorsin this special issue, I find it productiveto returnto the discussions of scaffolding in Wood et al. (1976) and to consider currentwork on scaffolding in this light. There are several components to this definition, which I call here the what, why, and how of scaffolding. The what and why of scaffolding may be consideredtogether, and the how of scaffolding can be taken separately. First, as to the WHAT and the WHY of scaffolding: Scaffolding situationsare those in which the learnergets assistanceor supportto performa taskbeyond his or her own reach if pursuedindependently when "unassisted"(Wood et al., 1976, p. 90). Right away,one can see how fundamentalaspects of this founding sense of the term differ from the work reportedin the four articlesin this issue. In the scaffold- ing activities of the adult when working with the child in the Wood et al. study, thereis a diagnosis of the learner'sproficiency and an adaptivelevel of supportthat is providedby the adult,with the temporaldynamics of the scaffoldingprocess im- plying cycles of comparisonbetween the assessed level of performancethe learner is exemplifying at any moment in time and the level of scaffolding that is respon-

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions SOCIAL DIMENSIONS 431 sively provided and with the dynamic of the process proceedingthrough such dy- namic assessment cycles toward the learner's autonomous performance. Stone (1993, 1998a, 1998b) has also highlighted the dynamic natureof the scaffolding process dependenton cycles of assessment and adaptivesupport. A fundamental aspect of the scaffoldingprocess was thus consideredto be what only latercame to be called "fading"of the scaffold, to use the term that I believe was introducedin Collins, Brown, and Newman (1989) and used by many others since:

Oncethe learner has a graspof thetarget skill, the master reduces (or fades) his partici- pation, providing only limited hints, refinements, and feedback to the learner,who practicessuccessively approximating smooth execution of thewhole skill. (p. 456)

Such fading, I argue, is an intrinsic component of the scaffolding framework: Withoutsuch a dismantlingmechanism, the kinds of behaviorsand supportsthat have been more recently described as scaffolding actually reflect the much more pervasiveform of cognitive supportthat enables what some call "distributedcog- nition" (e.g., Hutchins, 1995) and what I have called "distributedintelligence" (Pea, 1993, 2002). From this perspective,the main sense of distributedintelligence emerges from the image of people in action whose activity is enabled by the configuringof dis- tributedintelligence. However,that intelligence is distributedacross people, envi- ronmentsincluding designed artifacts,and situations.This is in contrastto intelli- gence viewed as a possession of the individual embodied mind. I thus describe intelligence as accomplishedrather than possessed. As I (Pea, 1993) noted in my chapteron distributedintelligence and education

Thereare both social and material dimensions of thisdistribution. The socialdistri- butionof intelligencecomes from its constructionin activitiessuch as theguided par- ticipationin joint actioncommon to parent-childinteraction or apprenticeship,or throughpeople's collaborativeefforts to achieve sharedaims. The materialdistribu- tion of intelligence originatesin the situatedinvention of uses of aspects of the envi- ronmentor the exploitationof the affordancesof designedartifacts, either of which may contributeto supportingthe achievementof an activity's purpose. (p. 50)

I believe that clearly delineating the boundariesbetween scaffolding with fad- ing and more general distributedintelligence without fading is a centralproblem for the learning sciences and for education, and the argumentstructures and war- rants used in marking these boundarieswill be informative-as well as conten- tious. So many new forms of humanactivity thatinvolve computingwould be sim- ply unachievablewithout the computing supportsenabling the acts of distributed intelligence. Fading is simply out of the question. People cannot do the activities withoutthe technologies, or it becomes meaninglessto ask whetherthey can do so.

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 432 PEA

If the supportdoes not fade, then one should consider the activity to be distributed intelligence, not scaffolded achievement.I returnto this core issue later on. Second, as to the HOW of scaffolding, the Wood et al. (1976) article was espe- cially useful in defining several of the propertiesfor how such assistance func- tioned for the learner.These propertiesfell into two primarygroups, with short- hand names I use for them (not used by Wood et al.):

1. Channelingand focusing: Reducing the degrees of freedom for the task at handby providingconstraints that increase the likelihood of the learner'seffective action; recruitingand focusing attentionof the learnerby marking relevanttask features (in what is otherwise a complex stimulus field), with the result of main- taining directednessof the learner'sactivity towardtask achievement. 2. Modeling: Modeling more advancedsolutions to the task.

Although channeling and focusing appearto be closely related, they may be distinguishedin the following way: Whereasthe scaffoldingprocess of channeling reducesthe degrees of freedomfor the task at hand, there is nonetheless the poten- tial for the learnernot to be focusing on the desiredtask componentor propertyin a temporalsequence of task-relatedbehaviors. So the scaffolding process of focus- ing is a more restrictive,limiting aspect of scaffolding.

CRITICALCONSIDERATION OF THE ARTICLES IN THIS SPECIAL ISSUE

In the remainderof my commentary,I reflect on the issues raised in the four arti- cles in terms of the scaffolding concept and its relation to distributedintelligence and raise questionsthat I feel warrantcontinued attention toward making advances concerningthis centralconcept in the learning sciences and instructionaltheory.

The WHATand WHY of Scaffolding It is significantthat the dynamic assessmentintrinsic to the scaffoldingframework thatI have outlined,which was integralto the originalWood et al. (1976) definition of the term, is absent in the software systems that are described in the articles in this issue as is acknowledgedby the authors,for example, Reiser (this issue): "The sense in which tools can scaffold learnersunder such conditions are clearly quite differentthan expert teachers who can tailortheir advice to an assessmentof the in- dividual learnerstate" (p. 298). Thus, the microgenesis of scaffolding processes evident in the problem-solvingsupport by the adultas the child works on the pyra- mid puzzle or in the peekaboo games characterizedby Bruner and Sherwood

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions SOCIAL DIMENSIONS 433

(1976) or Cazden (1979) is not an ingredientto the presumedscaffolding of these software systems. The reasons for this absence are apparentand noted by authorssuch as Reiser (this issue): Ourfield simply does not have the design knowledge as yet for how to providediagnostic assessmentthat is responsiveto what the learnerneeds for such complex cognitive tasks as the conduct of scientific inquiry. Intelligent tutoring systems for proceduraldomains such as algebra problem solving or geometric proof, by contrast,do seek to reasonabout the states of individuallearners and pro- vide next-step, responsive support.Reiser (this issue) thus observes how "the ap- proachin the scaffolded cognitive tools has been to embed supportwithin the sys- tem as promptsor representedin the structureof the tool itself,"leaving adaptation "underthe controlof the learnerswho can explore additionalprompts or assistance available [or] attemptto follow or work aroundthe system's advice" (p. 298). The scaffolding need in this case might even be called metascaffolding:If the learner does not know how to structuretheir problem-solving process for productivein- quiry,how is it that they are expected to know how to decide among nonadaptive choices for scaffolding?They need scaffolds for the scaffolds. This may be a use- ful locus of teachersupport in what Tabak(this issue) in her articlecalls "synergis- tic scaffolding"when studentsare using such software. Nonetheless, Reiser's (this issue) effort to distinguishwhat he calls the "struc- turing"and "problematizing"aspects of scaffoldingbears closer scrutinyon the is- sue of adaptivesupport vital to the scaffolding definition. Reiser seeks to explain by what "mechanisms"a softwaretool provides scaffolding for learnersand what model will account for how the tool has benefited learners.Reiser (this issue) dif- ferentiatestwo such mechanisms:task structuring("guiding learners through key componentsand supportingtheir planning and performance"[p. 273]) and content problematizing("tools can shape students'performance and understandingof the task in terms of key disciplinarycontent and strategiesand thus problematizethis importantcontent" [p. 273]). Reiser's (this issue) goal is to make the problematizingmechanism of scaffold- ing a more centralissue for our attentionin scaffolding theory and design, and this is quite significant,as it could lead to productiveuses for the scaffolding concept in instructionalactivity design. Reiser distinguishes structuringtasks to make them more tractablefrom shapingtasks for learnersto make theirproblem solving more productive.I found this distinctionhard to maintainas I workedthrough reviewing eitherthe softwaresystems he describesor those of the otherarticles. For example, the same tool featuresmay both simplify and problematizeby focusing learnerson task componentsthat they have not yet accomplished.Reiser (this issue) defines a broadarray of characteristicsthat he believes createproblematizing conditions for scaffolding includingdirecting attention of the studenttoward an issue that "needs resolution,"a triggeringof affective components such as "creatinginterest" in ad- vancingunderstanding, establishing a sense of "dissonanceor curiosity,"and more

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 434 PEA generally,"engaging students." In the end, I startedto see that I could identify ex- amples of task simplificationwithout problematization, and so I grantthat any ex- istence proof for the value of the distinctionReiser wants to makeprovides warrant for his distinction. Yet it remains an open empirical question under what condi- tions it is that a specific scaffoldingfeature and affiliatedscaffolding process work to problematizetasks for any given learnerdepending on the natureof the tasks; the learner'sbackground knowledge, capabilities,and interests; and the social con- text. As Reiser (this issue) notes, "thesocial context of collaborativeproblem solv- ing is often integralto the problematizingnature of the tool" (p. 289), which sug- gests that the problematizingbrought about by scaffolding is less a mechanismin the tool thana social functionof its interpretationin the particularsof the discourse of a learning situation. I also was not sure what Reiser (this issue) meant by mechanism.For physical tools, a mechanismis a method, procedure,or process involved in how something works.For learning, one is familiarwith proposedmechanisms of learning,such as assimilation-accommodation(Piaget, 1952) or knowledge compilation (Ander- son, 1983). However, I found the hybrid use of the term confusing, as it is used interpretivelyto markwhat Reiser as theoristbelieves to be what is happeningfor the learneras the software scaffolding features are used in the conduct of a com- plex task of inquiry.So it is neither about a descriptivefeature for a physical tool nor a proposalabout an internalmechanism for learningbut a hypotheticalcharac- terizationconcerning how (external)scaffolds work for (internal)learning. When mechanismis used in this way, it is importantto ask what will count as evidence for claims concerninghow scaffolds work. Reiser (this issue) provides illustrative examples of problematizing student work in characterizinghow, as studentsinteract with high school biology scaffold- ing tools andcreate artifacts, they are constrainedto using importantepistemic fea- tures of the discipline embodied in softwaremenu choices: "Ratherthan just writ- ing down their explanation,the tool forces them to consider how to express their hypothesis and its supportwithin a disciplinaryframework such as naturalselec- tion"(p. 291). Even with examples of studentdiscourse when using this software,I could still not determinewhat datacounts as evidence in supportof a claim for any given instance that a particularfeature of a scaffolded cognitive tool functionedto scaffold learningin terms of one, the other,or both of these two proposedmecha- nisms. However,the distinctionhas promise and can be developed in its empirical groundingin futurework. The Sherin et al. article in this issue also usefully foregroundsthe need for the comparativeanalysis intrinsicto the scaffolding process definition in Wood et al. (1976). Perhapsbecause the call for papersrequested conceptual work ratherthan empiricalstudies, Sherinet al. (this issue) do not provideany empiricaldata on this count except for theiroccasional referenceto comparisonsof the "hypotheticalbe- havior of learnerswith and without the innovation"(p. 398). A challenge for the

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions SOCIAL DIMENSIONS 435 learningsciences to work on what kinds of dataand analyses will help us betterun- derstandthe role of scaffolding processes using softwaretools towardthe targeted autonomousperformances.

The HOW of Scaffolding: Channeling and Focusing, Modeling Channeling and focusing in the articles. The articles offer many exam- ples that illustratethe channelingfunction of scaffolding learneractivities includ- ing systems dynamics model-buildingtask decomposition in Model-ItT, inquiry process scaffoldingusing Knowledge IntegrationEnvironment or ProgressPortfo- lio, planning notations, progress maps, and constrainedepistemic forms such as "what I know" and "high level question" in Computer-SupportedIntentional Learning Environments.Reducing task complexity is a function of many of the categories of scaffolding defined by Quintanaet al. (this issue) such as process managementguides for mapping complex stages in an inquiry process with re- minders and guidance toward progress and task completion. Reiser (this issue) also describes how some tool components automatethe execution of some of the task components.Many of the softwarefeatures described in the articlesalso focus a learner'sattention by markingrelevant task featuresto maintaindirectedness of their activity towardtask achievement. I found the category system comprising seven scaffolding guidelines and 20 scaffolding strategiesin Quintanaet al.'s (this issue) articlequite interestingand an impressiveformulation of an exceptionallycomplex field of softwaresystems and theiruses for science instructionand otherareas of learning.As one point of meth- odology, it would seem importantto develop interraterreliability data on classify- ing softwaresystems or specific instructionalpractices in termsof these guidelines and strategies.As with any classification,even one done with the merits of a com- bination of top-down and bottom-upanalysis such as this one, only time will tell whetherthese categories (forms of scaffolding) merit distinctionas their uses are put to the test in design, analytic, and empiricalwork. What looks good as a theo- retical distinctionmay be moot-or not-for the learningthat results from its de- ployment in specific subject matterdomains and implementationsituations (e.g., depending on the teacher'sroles, learning in groups ratherthan individually,stu- dent backgroundsand interests,etc.). Reiser (this issue) describeshow both featuresof the softwaretools and the arti- facts producedby studentsin using them reveal the problematizingmechanism of scaffolding insofaras the tools studentsuse to access, analyze, andmanipulate data are structuredso thatthe implicit strategiesof the discipline are visible to students and in that the work productscreated by students are designed so as to represent importantconceptual properties of explanationsin the discipline (these featuresre- flect scaffolding Strategy2b and scaffolding Guideline 2 in Quintanaet al., this is-

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 436 PEA sue). Reiser (this issue) characterizes these issues in terms of the Galapagos Finches software,which enables learners"to investigatechanges in populationsof plantsand animalsin an ecosystem and serves as a platformfor learningprinciples of ecosystems and naturalselection" (p. 286). The softwarescaffolds embody two differentstrategies for examining ecosystem data:through time longitudinallyor cross-sectionally (by some dimension such as male-female, young-adult). The empiricalquestion one may ask is whetherthe forced choice of strategiesin using such templatesto producethe students'artifacts yields continueduses of the strate- gies and expressions of the discipline's strategiesin artifactsonce the studentis no longer using the tool. Thus, the general issue with which I am concernedis whether studentsusing a constrainedset of forms for producingthe work artifactsof scaffoldedscientific in- quiries are "parroting"back disciplinaryforms of thinkingrather than performing with understandingof whatthey have created(like the horse CleverHans was doing when he seemed to be counting and doing arithmeticbut was being scaffolded by subtle cues from his owner; Pfungst, 1911). It remainsan empiricalissue whether Reiser's (this issue) having "tools force them into decisions or commitmentsre- quiredto use the vocabularyand machinery of the interface"results in learnerswho attendto such structuralfeatures of knowledge and inquirystrategies in the science domain without such scaffolding around.Another software system called Animal Landlorddistinguishes "observations" from "interpretations" (a preferredscientific practiceand epistemic distinction)as studentslook at animalbehavior videos, and the artifactsthat they produce require use of this distinction.Once theyhave used this system, what is known aboutwhether students are more likely offline to spontane- ously differentiateobservations from interpretationsin their uses of scientific in- quiry strategiesand distinctions?

Modeling in the articles. Thereare numerousscaffolds describedby the au- thorsin this issue thatseek to establishin both inquiryprocess andproduct artifacts a model for more developmentallymature scientific inquiryforms of activity.I see two issues of concern here. My first issue is where is the data in supportof the model attributionfor expertise? The second issue is the difference between a "model-without-a-person"and a scaffolding "person-as-a-model." On the first issue, all of the articles but perhapsmost clearly Quintanaet al.'s (this issue) talk about the "targetpractices" of "expertknowledge" toward which they hope their scaffolding software features and processes will guide the student as learner(also see Sherinet al.'s, this issue, "idealizedtarget performance"). In the characterizationsof the science inquirygoal states for learners,where do these at- tributionsof expertknowledge come from?From what I can tell, much of it is built from rational reconstructions and prototypical idealizations of inquiry (e.g., Krajcik,Berger, & Czeriak, 2002) and laboratorystudies (e.g., Klahr,2000), not social practicestudies or cognitive ethnographicstudies of actualmature scientific

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions SOCIAL DIMENSIONS 437 practices. Such empirical work in this vein, identified with work in the field of "science studies"(e.g., Bowker & Star, 1999; Galison, 1987, 1997; Knorr-Cetina, 1999; Latour & Woolgar, 1979/1986; Nersessian, 2004; Ochs & Jacoby, 1997; Rheinberger,1997; Star, 1989), both challenge existing idealizations of science practice on which the scaffolding models are based and introducenew forms of scientific expertise that such idealizationsrarely include (e.g., distributedreason- ing; see Dunbar,1999). These issues of empirically groundingthe targetstate for learningin empiricalstudies of scientists are significantones and warrantone's at- tention to the science studies literatureand the increasingfocus on technology-me- diated practices in scientific inquiry.To take but one case in point, extensive re- search defining "novice-expert differences" reasoning and task performancein science was used to informpedagogy (Chi, Glaser,& Farr,1988), but it did not suf- ficiently heed the adaptiveexpertise of the maturepractitioner in contrastto rou- tine expertise (Hatano& Oura,2003). On the second issue concerning modeling, note that because the scaffolding provided in the software systems characterizedin these articles lacks human agency for the learnerto interactwith, they may be missing what could come to be a key property of such modeling-a socially interactive other. One should consider the likely importancein scaffolding processes of a model in the sense of a role model, someone whose performancesand knowledge one could person- ally aspire to as a cultural issue and involving at its core a sense of identity, an affiliation with that person and their values, language, and activity components as a part of a community of practice (e.g., Holland, Lachicotte, Skinner,& Cain, 1998; Holland & Lave, 2001, Lave & Wenger, 1991). Having such a model may have very different consequences for learning than working within a nonhuman model structureof a task model that has been developed as a generic pattern prompter for scientific inquiry. Reiser (this issue) acknowledges as importantbut does not treat empirically in his article how the teachers' interpretiveand discourse practices, among other propertiesof the classroom system, are essential to achieving the desired educa- tional results from uses of the scaffolded cognitive tools. It would be good to see references to such empirical work on such practices and how they contributeto the benefits that software scaffolding may provide. Tabak (this issue) provides fertile examples of what she calls "synergisticscaffolding," an organizationthat brings together software features designed for scaffolding and teacher's scaffold- ing activities. However, this concept is not developed in terms of what properties of their interactions make such synergies work-or not. Such analyses would comparativelyexamine whether both software and teacher scaffolding functions could be achieved by software alone, by teacher alone, and what this says about whether it is importantthat the teacher's supportis human and socially interac- tive or simply that it needs to be interactiveand adaptive in nature (as software may eventually enable).

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 438 PEA

Fading in the articles. I am struckwith the absence of referenceto empiri- cal accounts of fading or transferin any of the articles in this issue, including the Quintanaet al. article, which seeks to be synoptic in its scope, covering dozens of systems in use in the field. Are thereknown results from measureddiagnosis of un- aided performanceand differentforms of scaffolding provided(as requiredin the comparativedefinition of scaffolding and in its original formulations)?Are there theory-informedefforts to fade such presumedscaffolds duringthe course of their uses for the learners?What are the known empiricalresults from learners'uses of scaffolds and their fading over time as unaidedperformance becomes possible? I am concernedthat the reasonfor such silence is that many of the softwarefea- turesin the systems describedappear to functionnot as scaffolds-with-fadingbut as scaffolds-for-performancein a way thatwill requirethem to continueto be used by the learnersto be able to have them deliverthe performancesthat are desired.Thus, thereis distributedintelligence, not scaffold-with-fading.Some of these scaffolding designs, such as the Quintanaet al. (this issue) category of "processmanagement supports,"look like they could be useful for the adultpracticing scientist, too; others in sense makingmay ormay notbe useful to the scientist,but where there is overtem- beddingof scientific disciplinarystrategies in the tool menusit certainlycalls out for learningdata from scaffold-with-fadingto avoid the Clever Hans interpretationof studentperformances in using these tools. Of course,scaffolding-with-fading can be useful for adultlearning, too, butI thinkthat many of the supportsdescribed in these categorieswould functionusefully as aides to the distributedintelligence achieved in the activities of adults or childrenwithout such fading. However,the surpriseis in the Sherinet al. article(this issue) on this point:Sherin et al. arguewith the assumptionin the originalWood et al. (1976) articleon scaffold- ing thatfading is a requiredcomponent of the definition.Yet understandingthe dy- namicsof scaffoldingprocesses, includingthe selection andcalibration of scaffold- ing structuresduring interactions, lies at the heartof developmentaltheory and the science of learningand roles that scaffolding plays in them. Although Sherinet al. havemade good progressin helpingus analyzescaffolding, they mustnow move for- wardto make headwayon the issue of change over time. To not take on this issue is self-defeating and only a statementof the currentlimited state of the art that, as Sherinet al. (this issue) note, "inthe case of technologicalartifacts, there is less of an opportunityfor interactivetuning of scaffolding"(p. 403). In fact, it is not at all obvi- ous thatSherin et al.'s frameworkcannot be appliedto changes over time, andin the closing sections of their article,they even suggest that it can be so extended.

Relation of Scaffolding With Fading to Distributed Intelligence More Generally In this section, I considerhow scaffolding with fading as one of its integralcompo- nents relates to distributedintelligence more generally. As Stone (1998b) high-

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions SOCIAL DIMENSIONS 439 lighted and Tabak(this issue) highlights, scaffolding is not at all a theoretically neutralterm. It is rooted in ZPD conceptions of learningand developmentand ac- tivity theoretic conceptualizationsof the relations among people, tools, and envi- ronment. It is activity and performance centered (e.g., Engestrom, 1987; Leont'iev, 1981; Vygotsky, 1978; Wertsch, 1991), not cognitive structureor task analysis centeredto point to a very differenttheoretical tradition in cognitive sci- ence (e.g., Anderson, 1983; Newell, 1990). Tabak'sarticle (this issue) provides a rich discussion of how scaffolding relates more broadlyto mediationof activity with culturaltools such as mathematicalrep- resentational systems for place value multiplication and how this helps problematize,in interestingways, the boundariesbetween (a) scaffolding consid- ered in the context of instructionaldesign and learningsupport and (b) distributed cognition more generally,which is commonly mediatedby culturaltools and scaf- folds createdby others or by oneself as designs for achieving activities that would be errorprone, challenging, or impossible otherwise. If one considered scaffolding activity to be assisting performancegenerally, it would problematically span an exceptional range of human behaviors that in- cludes adults, not only children, and many activities that people do not consider learning such as walking up stairs, sitting in chairs, flying in planes-each of which is assisted performancethat would not be possible if unaided (stairs pro- vide a physical scaffold for achieving greaterheight in a , chairs provide a scaffold for activity in an intermediatestate between standing and lying down, planes provide a scaffold for rapid travel avoiding those pesky mountains, etc.). Learning to scale heights without stairs, compose a sitting position without a chair, and unaided fast motion in the air are not goals of these scaffolds, and no one expects fading to be an integralpart of the use of stairs, chairs, and planes as scaffolds. Closer to the examples of these articles on inquiry are the com- puter-supportedactivities of adult scientists using advanced scientific visualiza- tions for reasoning about qualitative and quantitativerelations about physical variables as in global warming, or making inferences about statistical relations in census data (without the revolutionaryadvances in exploratorystatistical data analysis methods and software pioneered by Tukey, 1977), or longitudinal data modeling (using computationallyintensive analytic methods;e.g., Singer & Wil- let, 2003). Insofar as I am aware, we are not asking adults using these methods to function autonomously without such tools. Although certainly not the first,3 one of the most significant formulationsof the uses of computing to enable people to do what they could not do at all or could only do poorly without computing is in the seminal technical report on "augmentingthe human intellect" written by Douglas Engelbart (1962, 1963) shortly before he and his group developed the first personal computer at Stan- ford Research Institute (SRI; Bardini, 2000; Hafner & Lyon, 1996; Waldrop, 2002). Engelbart (1962) wrote the following:

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 440 PEA

It has been jokingly suggested several times during the course of this study that what we are seeking is an "intelligence amplifier."... At first this term was re- jected on the groundsthat in our view one's only hope was to make a better match between existing human intelligence and the problems to be tackled, ratherthan in making man more intelligent. But ... this term does seem applicable to our objec- tive. Accepting the term "intelligence amplification"does not imply any attemptto increase native human intelligence. The term "intelligence amplification" seems applicable to our goal of augmenting the human intellect in that the entity to be produced will exhibit more of what can be called intelligence than an unaided hu- man could [italics added]; we will have amplified the intelligence of the human by organizing his intellectual capabilities into higher levels of synergistic structuring. What possesses the amplified intelligence is the resulting H-LAM/T system [Hu- man using Language, Artefacts, and Methodology in which he is Trained;italics added], in which the LAM/T augmentationmeans represent the amplifier of the human's intelligence. In amplifying our intelligence, we are applying the principle of synergistic structuringthat was followed by naturalevolution in developing the basic humancapabilities. What we have done in the developmentof our augmenta- tion means is to constructa superstructurethat is a synthetic extension of the natu- ral structureupon which it is built. In a very real sense, as representedby the steady evolution of our augmentationmeans, the developmentof "artificialintelli- gence" has been going on for centuries. (p. 19)

3SeeVannevar Bush's astounding 1945 essay "As We May Think"(Bush, 1945a), imagining the fu- tureof computersas "memex" that would support human activities from scientific discovery to businessdecision making using associative indexing [which came to be calledhypertext]: For exam- ple

Considera futuredevice for individual use, whichis a sortof mechanizedprivate file andli- brary.It needsa name... "memex"will do. A memexis a devicein whichan individual stores all his books,records, and , and which is mechanizedso thatit maybe con- sultedwith exceeding speed and flexibility. It is anenlarged intimate supplement to his memory. ... Whollynew forms of encyclopediaswill appear, ready made with a meshof associativetrails runningthrough them, ready to be droppedinto the memex and there amplified. The lawyer has at his touchthe associatedopinions and decisions of his wholeexperience, and of the experi- ence of friendsand authorities. The patent attorney has on call the millionsof issuedpatents, withfamiliar trails to everypoint of his client'sinterest. The physician, puzzled by a patient's reactions,strikes the trailestablished in studyingan earliersimilar case, and runsrapidly throughanalogous case histories, with side references to theclassics for the pertinent anatomy andhistology. The chemist, struggling with the synthesisof an organiccompound, has all the chemicalliterature before him in his laboratory,with trails following the analogiesof com- pounds,and side trails to theirphysical and chemical behavior. (p. 106)

Bush was the first PresidentialScience Advisor whose strategicand futuristicthinking also directlyled to Congressionalauthorization for the NationalScience Foundation(Bush, 1945b). Engelbartwas very inspiredby Bush's vision in his inventions.

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions SOCIALDIMENSIONS 441

In Doug Engelbart's(1962) remarkablereport creating a new frameworkfor thinkingnot only aboutcomputing but its relationto the history of humanthinking and activity,he conjecturedthat computers represent a fourthstage in the evolution of humanintellectual capabilities building on (a) the biologically based conceptma- nipulationstage, (b) the speech and writing-basedstage of symbol manipulation, and(c) theprinting-based stage of manualexternal symbol manipulation,and now

Inthis stage, symbols with which the human represents the concepts he is manipulat- ing canbe arrangedbefore his eyes, moved,stored, recalled, operated upon accord- ing to extremelycomplex rules-all in veryrapid response to a minimumamount of informationsupplied by the human,by meansof specialcooperative technological devices. In the limit of what we might now imagine, this could be a computer,with whichwe could communicaterapidly and easily,coupled to a three-dimensional colordisplay within which it couldconstruct extremely sophisticated images with thecomputer being able to executea widevariety of processeson partsor all of these imagesin automaticresponse to humandirection. The displays and processes could providehelpful services and could involve concepts not hithertoimagined (as the pregraphicthinker of stage2 wouldbe unableto predictthe bar graph, the process of long division,or a cardfile system).(p. 25)

This traditionof using computersas what came to be called "cognitivetechnol- ogies" at Xerox Palo Alto Research Center (PARC) in the 1970s and 1980s (see history in Rheingold, 1985/2000) was fueled significantly when the new center hired almost all of Engelbart'sSRI group whose talents were then turnedto creat- ing the first commercially available personal computer,the Xerox Alto (Hiltzik, 2000). The interestingwrinkle in this history that then begins to connect up with developmentalpsychology and learningis thatAlan Kay, the PARCimpresario of portable personal computing with his vision of a Dynabook, brought the neo-Piagetian ideas and child-centered sensibilities of MIT professor Seymour Papertinto the design of the PARC'scognitive technologies with his leadershipof PARC's Learning Research Group. The development of bit-mapped computer screens, the SmallTalk object-orientedand message-passing programminglan- guage, constantpilot testing of PARCprogram user interfaceswith childrento see if they found them compelling and useful as "fantasyengines," and point-and-click interactivitywere all partof the emergence of the art of humaninterface design at PARCin the early 1970s (Kay & Goldberg, 1977), and laterthe Macintoshteam at Apple Computertook on this legacy (and significantly,some of its key staff). Now consider-with tongue in cheek-a differentspin on today'spersonal com- puterand its accessible user interfaceswith this design history:Imagine an account of personalcomputing that was developed not by the likes of Kay but by educators who insisted on scaffolding-with-fadingof the kinds of supportsprovided by the cognitive technologiesthat the computerafforded instead of integraluse of comput-

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 442 PEA ers in a coevolved patternof activity in which the humanand the roles in conducting complex inquiries and performingadvanced scientific modeling and simulationsneeded to transferto the learner,alone, workingwithout the computer. Withdistributed intelligence, the point is often not aboutfading at all, but being able to act in a context of assumptionsof availabilityof tools-representational, material, and other people-for achieving ends. Educators, policymakers, and learnersneed to weigh the perceived risks affiliated with the loss of such support with the value of the incrementaleffort of learninghow to do the task or activity unaided should such tools and supportsever become inaccessible, and the answer has to do with the social and technological assumptionshumans make. As we ap- proach a world in the coming years with pervasive computing with always-on Internetaccess, reliable quality of service networks,and sufficient levels of tech- nological fluency, the context assumptionsthat help shape culturalvalues for dis- tributedintelligence versus scaffolding with fading are changing. So that is one of my concerns here. I believe the authorsin these articles have been making significantprogress in providingtechnological and pedagogical sup- portsto the conductof scientific inquiryin its bootstrappingphases. I see two large vistas of questions for the work ahead. First is the fascinating and challenging question of sorting out empirically which of the sense making, process manage- ment, and articulationand reflection supportsthat they and others have created should be conceived of as scaffolds-with-fadingto be pulled down and whisked away once the learneris able to performas expected withouttheir use-and which of these supportsdeserve to serve in an ongoing way as partof a distributedintelli- gence scientific workbench and as fundamentalaides to the doing of science whose fading is unnecessaryand unproductive. The second vista is engaged more with culturalvalues than with empiricism. For the most part (except Tabakand briefly, Reiser, this issue), the articles in this issue do not take on developmentsof any specific social practicein science inquiry whose performancesare scaffolded (for contrast,see Hutchins, 1995, on naviga- tion in relationto its instrumentsand social practices).Yet the issue looms large. If one can assume regular access to the scaffolding supports by the person using them, and if theiruse may acceleratebroader access to the forms of reasoningthat employ them (such as science inquiry),the question is pressing:Why fade? Tabak provides a historical considerationof scaffolding and its relation to distributed cognition, and Reiser hints at it. Sherin et al. (this issue) note that "it is not even clear thatit makes intuitivesense to call the calculatora scaffold,"as it has become so common that "if a calculator is a fixed component of mathematics prob- lem-solving activity,can it still be called a scaffold?"(p. 390). Sherinet al. (this is- sue) go on to correctlyobserve how "themore that our learningartifacts transform the task, the harderit will be to understandhow the learnermight be 'doing the same thing"' (p. 395). So these value considerationsin relation to issues of scaf- folding as an educationalconcept are a vital need, particularlyin terms of the his-

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions SOCIAL DIMENSIONS 443 torically changing relationbetween scaffolding-with-fadingand distributedintel- ligence.

What Does It Mean to Test Scaffolding Theory? It is importantto begin testing the claims of scaffolding theory in which scaffold- ing theory involves specific formulationsof what distinctive forms and processes of focusing, channeling,and modeling are integralto the developmentof expertise. It also appearsthat embodied within a theory of scaffolding needs to be a theoryof transferof learningfor autonomousperformance as well, or, more likely I would argue,a theoryof scaffoldingneeds to be situatedwith respectto a theoryof the de- velopment of the distributedintelligence, as learning to "worksmart" (Bransford & Schwartz,1999; Bransfordet al., 1998) will often involve, as adaptiveexpertise, learning to establish one's own scaffolds for performance,4and fading these may be beside the point-fading of supportsas a somewhatPuritanical concept that is inappropriatefor modem times. Among the considerationsin such a formulation,it seems to me, would be the following:

1. A theoryof scaffolding should successfully predictfor any given learnerand any given task what forms of supportprovided by what agent(s) and designed arti- facts would suffice for enablingthat learner to performat a desirablelevel of profi- ciency on that task, which is known to be unachievablewithout such scaffolding. Thus, one needs independentevidence that the learnercannot do the task or goal unaided. One would imagine as a primaryconcern the need to take on issues of over what range of situationsthis determinationwould be made or inferred.This concern is also implied in the comparativeformulation of scaffolding by Sherinet al. (this issue). Such a theory of scaffolding would also need to account for recognition pro- cesses by which a learnerrecognizes a situationas an appropriateone for deploy-

4Teachingfor the design of distributedintelligence ... would encourageand refine the natu- ral tendency for people to continuallyre-create their own world as a scaffold to their activities. ... In mathematics and science education, one might develop a metacurriculumoriented to learningabout the role of distributedintelligence in enabling complex thought ... They would come to see throughtheir activities where the bottlenecks of complex mentationreside. They would recognize how physical, symbolic, and social technologies may provide the supportsto allow for reachingconceptual heights less attainableif attemptedunaided. This goal might be achievedthrough examination of living, everydayexamples (buildingfrom cases where they al- ready do distributedintelligence in the world), and, perhaps,through case studies of the roles of informationstructures (e.g., matrices,flowcharts, templates) and social structures(work teams; apprenticeships)in mediating learningand reasoning as activity systems of distributedintelli- gence. (Pea, 1993, pp. 81-82)

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 444 PEA ing the knowledge or skills in an autonomousmanner that was developed through scaffolding. 2. In readingthe articles, I was astonishedto find that they do not distinguish learners at different developmentallevels of knowledge or of distinctive beliefs about knowledge and learning(e.g., Hofer & Pintrich, 1997), even within science tasks or in terms of epistemological views on the natureof science-although ex- tensive literatureis available in science education that uses such developmental levels (e.g., Carey,Evans, Honda, Jay, & Unger, 1989; Halloun, 1997; Hammer, 1994; Kuhn, Amsel, & O'Loughlin, 1988; Linn & Songer, 1993; Redish, Steinberg,& Saul, 1998; Roth & Roychoudhury,1994; Smith, Maclin, Houghton, & Hennessey, 2000; Songer & Linn, 1991). It would seem that scaffolding theory by its very natureneeds to characterizea developmentaltrajectory for levels of per- formance on the tasks that it is designed to dynamically scaffold. The diagnoses and adaptivesupport that scaffolding as a process provides would move stepwise with the learnerup the developmentallevel sequence until such masteryhas been achieved that the fading has been accomplished.5 It seems possible to imagine "mixed initiative"6designs of scaffolding pro- cesses in which people and machinesjoin togetherin helping someone learn some- thing in the sense that certainscaffolding activities can be the responsibilityof the teacher(or peers) and otherscaffolding activitiesprovided by the software.Even if the softwarecannot do an assessmentof the learnerand then provideadaptive scaf- folding on its own, it seems entirely possible that the teachercould do such an as- sessment and then be in chargeof switching levels of scaffolding that are provided by the software.In this way, a scaffolding partnership,or synergy,as Tabakwould call it, could be achievedin supportof the learner'sadvances. How these "divisions of labor"should be achieved is a theoreticallyfertile areafor learning sciences re- search (e.g., Stevens, 2000). 3. Testing scaffoldingtheory for the purposesof informinginstructional design has some distinctively different issues affiliated with it. The designer needs to know how to scaffold what facets of the scientific inquiryprocess when, and with what expected results, along a learning trajectoryin which new answers will be given to what is needed. The complexity of the scientific inquiryprocess is such thatit cannotall be scaffoldedat once. (Thereare stronganalogs here to the writing process and forms of scaffolding that have been providedfor learningto write in-

5Davis (2003a, 2003b) has provided an example of work that can inform the making of such con- nections in her studies of how studentswith differentbeliefs about science learningused and benefited from differenttypes of scaffolding. 6Carbonell(1970) is most identifiedwith the concept of mixed initiative systems for learningsup- port.Carbonell created the first intelligenttutoring system, and its design was such thateither a human teacher or the computerprogram could ask questions. Today, such mixed initiative systems are com- monly providedin customer-relationshipmanagement and call centers,in complex planning,and more recently to aid information-seekingbehavior.

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions SOCIAL DIMENSIONS 445 eluding writer'sworkshops and varioussoftware tools.) Yet from readingthese ar- ticles, the instructionaldesigner does not have at hand any rules for making deci- sions about what kinds of scaffolds (among seven scaffolding guidelines and 20 scaffolding strategiesin Quintanaet al., this issue) to providein what kind of adap- tively relevantsequencing for advancinga learner'scapabilities. 4. In the activities of scaffoldingfor learning,what specifically requiresthe so- cial face-to-face of scaffolding versus the interactivitythat might be providedby a software artifact?Is contingency of responding all that matters (e.g., Reeves & Nass, 1996; implied in most of these articles as well), or is it humanagency that is crucial in the scaffolding process? It is entirely possible that issues of identity de- velopment, community or culturalvalues, a sense of belonging/affiliation,faith, trust,individual caring, and responsibilityweigh into these mattersand that with- out the "humantouch" of scaffolding and fading from agents that truly represent these dimensionsof experience,scaffolding and fading for learningmay be less ef- fective (or unhelpful altogether).Reminding a child of a rule to be followed in a game may provide both a metacognitivescaffolding promptbut also be emblem- atic of a caring response that motivates its consideration (e.g., Lepper & Woolverton,2002). In this respect, it is somewhat worrisomethat what is valued by people in the uses of these scaffolds is too distantand relativelyinvisible in the scaffoldingartifacts that are developedand used by Reiser (this issue) and othersin these articles.A learnercannot have a dialog with the scaffolding supportsin an in- quiry system such as the BGuILEExplanationConstructor-like one could a per- son doing BGuILE-likeinterpersonal scaffolding in a classroom-about why one needs to answer a question in a certainway. Conveyingthe rationalesfor perform- ing different scientific practices by means of a prescriptionbuilt into a software scaffold, as recommendedby scaffolding Strategy 5b in Quintinaet al.'s article, may not have enough of a humantouch.

CONCLUSION

Like the term communityin learningtheory and educationaluses of phrases such as "community of practice," "community of learners" "online community of learning,"it is importantto note that theoretical issues are not settled by defini- tions per se (Barab,Kling, & Gray, 2004; Renninger& Shumar,2002). Yet defi- nitional issues and category systems of kinds of scaffolds and scaffolding oc- cupy a large proportion of the pages in these articles. The vital question, ontologies aside, is this: What work does the concept of scaffolding do in theo- ries of learning and instruction?How does the scaffolding concept, however ar- ticulated, stand in relation to the specific goals of explanation, prediction, and the coherence of theoreticalclaims for a theory of learning, encompassing learn- ing in everyday cognition, work practices, and in formal education? How does

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 446 PEA the scaffolding concept stand in relation to its effective use in what Bruner (1966, 1996) has called a "theory of instruction"to guide the structureand se- quencing of its instructionaldesigns, its situated practices, and its outcomes? Reflecting on these questions, I recommend several new emphases (a) on estab- lishing systematic empirical investigationsof how the scaffolding process relates to learning and not only to performanceand (b) in designing and researching uses of mixed-initiative systems that combine human help from teachers and peers with software system features that aid scaffolding processes. One thing for sure: Scaffolds are not found in software but are functions of processes that relate people to performancesin activity systems over time. The goals of scaffolding research going forward should be to study how scaffolding processes-whether achieved in part by the use of software features, human as- sistance, or other material supports-are best conceived in ways that illuminate the natureof learning as it is spontaneously structuredoutside formal education and as it can most richly inform instructionaldesign and educational practices. In either case, to advancethe prospects of learners,thickly texturedempirical ac- counts are now needed of how scaffolding processes in such activity systems work in comparisonto their independentperformances, even when (and perhaps especially when) the results deviate from the best intentions of their designers. We need to see best practices (when scaffolding systems work as planned) but also the troubles that arise when learnersturn out not to act in the ways that de- signers hoped and when addressingtheir needs can stretchour imaginations,the- ories, and designs. These articles have focused more on properties of software and curriculum for science inquiry than they have learner performances and transfer of learning considerations. When software designed to scaffold complex learning is used, the burden of proof is on the researcherto (a) document how it is that it serves to advance a learner'sperformance beyond what they would have done working alone (i.e., the ZPD comparisonneeds to be warranted)and (2) what processes of fading need to be employed to sustainthe learner'sautonomous performance of the capabilitiesin question across transfersituations that matter.Such proof needs to be providedfor each learner,not only selected learnersor groups that serve to illustratethe best practicesof scaffolding processes. Finally, these articles provocativelycall one's attentionto the boundaryissue between scaffolding defined with fading as a necessary condition and distributed intelligence in which scaffolded support enables more advanced performances than would be possible without such supportbut in which fading is not a cultural goal. Such boundaryissues are at once empirical and normativeas we debate val- ues for what learners should be able to do with and without such designed scaf- folds-debates nonetheless informed by empirical accounts of learners' perfor- mances in the diversity of situations in which their knowledge and adaptive expertise should come to play.

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions SOCIAL DIMENSIONS 447

REFERENCES

Anderson,J. R. (1983). The architectureof cognition. Cambridge,MA: HarvardUniversity Press. Applebee, A. N., & Langer,J. A. (1983). Instructionalscaffolding: Reading and writingas naturallan- guage activities. LanguageArts, 60, 168-175. Bardini,T. (2000). Bootstrapping:Douglas Engelbart,co-evolution, and the origins of personal com- puting. Stanford:Stanford University Press. Barab,S. A., Kling, R., & Gray,J. (Eds.). (2004). Designingfor virtual communitiesin the service of learning. New York:Cambridge University Press. Bates, E. (1976). Language and context: The acquisition of pragmatics. New York:Academic. Bowker, G. C., & Star, S. L. (1999). Sorting things out: Classification and its consequences. Cam- bridge, MA: MIT Press. Bransford,J. D. & Schwartz,D. (1999). Rethinkingtransfer: A simple proposalwith multipleimplica- tions. In A. Iran-Nejad& P.D. Pearson(Eds.), Reviewof researchin education(Vol. 24, pp. 61-100). Washington,DC: AmericanEducational Research Association. Bransford,J. D., Zech, L., Schwartz,D., Barron,B., Vye, N. J., & Cognition and Technology Groupat Vanderbilt.(1998). Designs for environmentsthat invite and sustain mathematicalthinking. In P. Cobb (Ed.), Symbolizing,communicating, and mathematizing:Perspectives on discourse, tools, and instructionaldesign (pp. 275-324). Mahwah,NJ: LawrenceErlbaum Associates, Inc. Brown, A., & Ferrara,R. (1985). Diagnosing zones of proximal development.In J. Wertsch(Ed.), Cul- ture, ,and cognition: Vygotskianperspectives (pp. 273-305). Cambridge,England: CambridgeUniversity Press. Bruner,J. (1966). Towarda theory of instruction.Cambridge, MA: HarvardUniversity Press. Bruner, J. (1975a). From communication to language: A psychological perspective. Cognition, 3, 255-289. Bruner,J. (1975b). The ontogenesis of speech acts. Journal of Child Language, 2, 1-19. Bruner,J. (1977). Early social interactionand language acquisition. In R. Schaffer (Ed.), Studies in mother-infantinteraction (pp. 271-289). New York:Academic. Bruner,J. (1996). The cultureof education. Cambridge,MA: HarvardUniversity Press. Bruner,J. S., & Sherwood V. (1976). Peekaboo and the learningof rule structures.In J. S. Bruner,A. Jolly, & K. Sylva (Eds.), Play: Its role in developmentand evolution (pp. 277-285). New York:Pen- guin. Bush, V. (1945a). As we may think. TheAtlantic Monthly,176(1), 101-108. Bush, V. (1945b). Science-The endless frontier: A report to the president on a programfor postwar scientific research.Washington, DC: GovernmentPrinting Office. Campione, J. C. (1989). Assisted assessment:A taxonomy of approachesand an outline of strengths and weaknesses. Journal of Learning Disabilities, 22, 151-165. Campione,J. C., & Brown, A. L. (1984). Learningability and transferpropensity as sources of individ- ual differencesin intelligence. In P. H. Brooks, R. Sperber,& C. McCauley(Eds.), Learningand cog- nition in the mentally retarded(pp. 265-293). Hillsdale, NJ: LawrenceErlbaum Associates, Inc. Campione, J. C., & Brown, A. L. (1990). Guided learning and transfer:Implications for approaches to assessment. In N. Frederiksen,R. Glaser, A. Lesgold, & M. Shafto (Eds.), Diagnostic monitor- ing of skill and knowledge acquisition (pp. 141-172). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence ErlbaumAssoci- ates, Inc. Campione,J. C., Brown,A. L. Ferrara,R. A., & Bryant,N. R. (1984). The zone of proximaldevelopment: Implicationsfor individualdifferences in learning.In B. Rogoff & J. V. Wertsch(Eds.), New directions for child development:No. 23: "Children'slearning in the zone ofproximaldevelopment" (pp. 77-91). San Francisco,CA: Jossey Bass. Carbonell,J. R. (1970). AI in CAI: An artificialintelligence approachto computer-assistedinstruction. IEEE Transactionson Man-Machine Systems, 11(4), 190-202.

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 448 PEA

Carey,S., Evans, R., Honda,M., Jay,E., & Unger,C. (1989). "Anexperiment is when you try it and see if it works":A study of grade 7 students'understanding of the constructionof scientific knowledge. InternationalJournal of Science Education, 11, 514-529. Cazden, C. (1979). Peekabooas an instructionalmodel: Discourse developmentat home and at school. StanfordPapers and Reports in Child Language Development, 17, 1-19. Chi, M. T. H., Glaser, R., & Farr, M. J. (1988). The nature of expertise. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence ErlbaumAssociates, Inc. Chomsky,N. (1966). Cartesian linguistics: A chapter in the history of rationalist thought.New York: Harper& Row. Cole, M. (Ed.). (1978). The selected writings of Alexander R. Luria. White Plains, NY: Sharpe. Cole, M. (1996). Culturalpsychology: A once andfuturediscipline. Cambridge,MA: HarvardUniver- sity Press. Cole, M., & Griffin, P. (1983, October). A socio-historical approachto re-mediation.The Quarterly Newsletterof the Laboratoryof ComparativeHuman Cognition,5(4), 69-74. Collins, A., Brown, J. S., & Newman, S. E. (1989). Cognitive apprenticeship:Teaching the craft of reading,writing, and mathematics.In L. B. Resnick (Ed.), Knowing,learning, and instruction:Es- says in honor of Robert Glaser (pp, 453-494). Hillsdale, NJ: LawrenceErlbaum Associates, Inc. Davis, E. A. (2003a). Promptingmiddle school science studentsfor productivereflection: Generic and directedprompts. The Journal of the LearningSciences, 12, 91-142. Davis, E. A. (2003b). Untanglingdimensions of students'beliefs about scientific knowledge and sci- ence learning.International Journal of Science Education,25, 439-468. Dore, J. (1972). The developmentof speech acts. Unpublisheddoctoral dissertation, Graduate Center, City University of New York. Dunbar, K. (1999). The scientist in vivo: How scientists think and reason in the laboratory.In L. Magnani, N. Nersessian, & P. Thagard(Eds.), Model-based reasoning in scientific discovery (pp. 89-98). New York.Plenum. Engelbart,D. (1962). A conceptualframework for the augmentationof man's intellect. Menlo Park, CA: Stanford Research Institute. Retrieved May 16, 2004, from http://www.bootstrap.org/augdocs/friedewald030402/augmentinghumanintellect/ahi62.index.html Engelbart, D. (1963). A conceptual framework for the augmentationof man's intellect. In P. W. Howerton& D. C. Weeks (Eds.), Vistasin informationhandling (pp. 1-29). Washington,DC: Spar- tan Books. Republishedin I. Greif (Ed.). (1988). Computersupported cooperative work: a book of readings (pp. 35-65). San Mateo, CA: MorganKaufmann. Engestr6m,Y. (1987). Learning by expanding:An activity-theoreticalapproach to developmentalre- search. Helsinki, Finland:Orienta-Konsultit. Engestrom, Y., Miettinen, R., & Punamaki,R. (Eds.). (1999). Perspectives on activity theory. New York:Cambridge University Press. Feuerstein,R., Hoffman, M. B., Rand, Y., & Miller, R. (1980). Instrumentalenrichment. Baltimore: University ParkPress. Feuerstein,R., Rand, Y., & Hoffman, M. B. (1979). The dynamicassessment of retardedperformers: The learning potential assessment device, theory, instruments,and techniques. Baltimore:Univer- sity ParkPress. Galison, P. (1987). How experimentsend. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Galison, P. (1997). Image and logic: A material culture of microphysics.Chicago: University of Chi- cago Press. Gindis, B. (1997). Psychology appliedto education:Lev S. Vygotsky's approach.NASP Communique, 25, 2, 12-13. Glick. J. A. (1983). Piaget, Vygotsky and Werner.In S. Wapner& B. Kaplan(Eds.), Towarda holistic developmentalpsychology (pp. 35-52). Hillsdale, NJ: LawrenceErlbaum Associates, Inc.

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions SOCIAL DIMENSIONS 449

Greenfield,P. M., & Smith, J. H. (1976). The structureof communicationin early language develop- ment. New York:Academic. Halloun,I. (1997). Views about science and physics achievement:The VASS Story.In E. F. Redish & J. S. Rigden (Eds.), Proceedings of the InternationalConference on UndergraduatePhysics Education (pp. 605-613). Washington,DC: AmericanInstitute of Physics. Hammer,D. (1994). Epistemological beliefs in introductoryphysics. Cognition and Instruction, 12, 151-183. Hatano,G., & Oura,Y. (2003). Commentary:Reconceptualizing school learningusing insight from ex- pertise research.Educational Researcher, 32(8), 26-29. Hawkins, J., & Pea, R. D. (1987). Tools for bridgingeveryday and scientific thinking.Journalfor Re- search in Science Teaching,24, 291-307. Hiltzik, M. (2000). Dealers of lightning: Xerox PARCand the dawn of the computerage. New York: HarperCollins. Hofer, B. K., & Pintrich, P. R. (1997). The development of epistemological theories: Beliefs about knowledge andknowing and theirrelation to learning.Review of EducationalResearch, 67, 88-140. Holland, D., Lachicotte, W., Skinner,D., & Cain, C. (1998). Identityand agency in cultural worlds. Cambridge,MA: HarvardUniversity Press. Holland,D., & Lave, J. (2001). (Eds.). History in person: Enduringstruggles, contentiouspractice, in- timate identities. Santa Fe, NM: The School of AmericanResearch Press. Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cambridge,MA: MIT Press. Kay, A., & Goldberg,A. (1977, March).Personal dynamic media. IEEE Computer,10(3), 31-42. (Re- printedin A. Goldberg (Ed.). (1988). A history of personal workstations(pp. 254-263). Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.) Klahr, D. (2000). Exploring science: the cognition and development of discovery processes. Cam- bridge, MA: MIT Press. Knorr-Cetina,K. (1999). Epistemiccultures: How the sciences makeknowledge. Cambridge, MA: Har- vardUniversity Press. Kozulin, A., & Rand, B.Y. (Eds.). (2000). Experienceof mediatedlearning: An impactof Feuerstein's theory in education and psychology. Oxford, England:Pergamon. Krajcik,J., Berger,C. E, & Czemiak, C. M. (2002). Teachingscience in elementaryand middle school classrooms: A project-basedapproach (2nd ed.). New York:McGraw-Hill. Kuhn, D., Amsel, E., & O'Loughlin, M. (1988). The developmentof scientific reasoning skills. Or- lando, CA: Academic. Latour,B., & Woolgar,S. (1986). Laboratorylife: The constructionof scientificfacts (2nd ed.). Lon- don: Sage. (Originalwork published 1979) Lave, J., & Wenger, E. (1991). Situated learning: Legitimateperipheral participation. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press. Leont'iev, A. A. (1981). The problemof activity in psychology. In J. V. Wertsch(Ed.), The concept of activity in Sovietpsychology (pp. 37-71). New York:Sharpe. Lepper,M. R., & Woolverton,M. (2002). The wisdom of practice:Lessons learned from the study of highly effective tutors.In J. Aronson (Ed.), Improvingacademic achievement:Impact ofpsychologi- calfactors on education (pp. 135-158). San Diego, CA: Academic. Lidz, C. S. (Ed.). (1987). Dynamic assessment: An interactionalapproach to evaluating learning po- tential. New York:Guilford. Linn, M.C., & Songer, N. B. (1993). How do studentsmake sense of science? Merrill-PalmerQuar- terly, 39, 47-73. Nersessian,N. J. (2004). Interpretingscientific and engineeringpractices: Integrating the cognitive,social, andcultural dimensions. In M. Gorman,R. Tweney,D. Gooding,& A. Kincannon(Eds.), New directions in science and technicalthinking (pp. 17-56). Mahwah,NJ: LawrenceErlbaum Associates, Inc. Newell, A. (1990). Unified theories of cognition. Cambridge,MA: HarvardUniversity Press.

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 450 PEA

Ochs, E., & Jacoby,S. (1997). Down to the wire: The culturalclock of physicists and the discourse of consensus. Language in Society, 26, 479-505. Pea, R. D. (1985a). Beyond amplification:Using computersto reorganizehuman mental functioning. EducationalPsychologist, 20, 167-182. Pea, R. D. (1985b). Integratinghuman and computerintelligence. In E. L. Klein (Ed.), New directions for child development:No. 28, Childrenand computers(pp. 75-96). San Francisco:Jossey-Bass. Pea, R. D. (1987). Cognitivetechnologies for mathematicseducation. In A. Schoenfeld(Ed.), Cognitive science and mathematicseducation (pp. 89-122). Hillsdale,NJ: LawrenceErlbaum Associates, Inc. Pea, R. D. (1993). Practicesof distributedintelligence and designs for education.In G. Salomon (Ed.), Distributedcognitions (pp. 47-87). New York:Cambridge University Press. Pea, R. D. (2002). Learningscience throughcollaborative visualization over the Internet.In N. Ringertz (Ed.), Nobel symposium: Virtualmuseums and public understandingof science and culture. Re- trieved May 17, 2004, from http://www.nobel.se/nobel/nobel-foundation/symposia/interdisciplin- ary/ns120/about.html Pea, R. D., & Kurland,D. M. (1987). Cognitivetechnologies for writingdevelopment. In L. Frase (Ed.), Review of researchin education (Vol. 14, pp. 71-120). Washington,DC: AmericanEducational Re- search Association. Pellegrino, J., Chudowsky,N., & Glaser, R. (2001). Knowing what students know. Washington,DC: National Academy Press. Pfungst, 0. (1911). Clever Hans (The horse of Mr VonOsten): A contributionto experimentalanimal and humanpsychology. New York:Holt. Piaget, J. (1952). The origins of intelligence in children (M. Cook, Trans.). New York:International Universities Press. Redish, E. F., Steinberg,R. N., & Saul, J. M. (1998). Student expectations in introductoryphysics. AmericanJournal of Physics, 66, 212-224. Reeves, B., & Nass, C. (1996). The media equation: How people treat computers,television, and new media like people and places. New York:Cambridge University Press. Renninger,K. A., & Shumar,W. (2002). (Eds.). Building virtual communities:learning and change in cyberspace. New York:Cambridge University Press. Rheinberger,H.-J. (1997). Towarda history of epistemic things: Synthesizingproteins in the test tube. Stanford:Stanford University Press. Rheingold, H. (2000). Toolsfor thought: The history and future of mind-expandingtechnology (2nd ed.). Cambridge,MA: MIT Press. (Originalwork published 1985) Rogoff, B., & Wertsch,J. V. (Eds.). (1984). New directionsfor child development:No. 23: Children's learning in the "zone ofproximal development."San Francisco,CA: Jossey Bass. Roth, W. M., & Roychoudhury,A. (1994). Physics students'epistemologies and views aboutknowing and learning.Journal of Research in Science Teaching,31, 5-30. Scardamalia,M., & Bereiter,C. (1983). The developmentof evaluative,diagnostic, and remedialcapa- bilities in children'scomposing. In M. Martlew(Ed.), Thepsychology of writtenlanguage: Develop- mental and educationalperspectives (pp. 67-95). London:Wiley. Scardamalia,M., & Bereiter, C. (1985). Research on written composition. In M. C. Wittrock (Ed.), Handbookof researchon teaching (3rd ed., pp. 778-803). New York:MacMillan. Simon, H. (1969). The sciences of the artificial. Cambridge,MA: MIT Press. Singer,J. D., & Willet, J. B. (2003). Applied longitudinaldata analysis: Modeling change and event oc- currence.New York:Oxford University Press. Smith, C. L., Maclin, D., Houghton, C., & Hennessey, M. G. (2000). Sixth-grade students' epistemologies of science: The impact of school science experiences on epistemological develop- ment. Cognition & Instruction,18, 349-22. Songer, N. B., & Linn, M. C. (1991). How do students'views of science influence knowledge integra- tion? Journal of Research in Science Teaching,28, 761-784.

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions SOCIAL DIMENSIONS 451

Star, L. (1989). Regions of the mind: Brain research and the questfor scientific certainty. Stanford: StanfordUniversity Press. Stevens, R. R. (2000). Divisions of labor in school and in the workplace:Comparing computer and pa- per-supportedactivities across settings. The Journal of the Learning Sciences, 9, 373-401. Stone, C. A. (1993). What is missing in the metaphorof scaffolding? In E. Forman,N. Minick, & C. Stone (Eds.), Contexts for learning: Sociocultural dynamics in children's development (pp. 169-183). New York:Oxford University Press. Stone, C. A. (1998a). The metaphorof scaffolding:Its utility for the field of learningdisabilities. Jour- nal of LearningDisabilities, 31, 344-364. Stone, C. A. (1998b). Should we salvage the scaffolding metaphor?Journal of Learning Disabilities, 31, 409-413. Tikhomirov,O. K. (1981). The psychological consequences of computerization.In J. V. Wertsch(Ed.), The concept of activity in Soviet psychology (pp. 256-278). Armonk,NY: Sharpe. Toulmin,S. (1972). Human understanding.Princeton, NJ: PrincetonUniversity Press. Toulmin, S. (1978, September 28). The Mozart of psychology. New YorkReview of Books, 25(14), 51-57. Tukey,J. W. (1977). Exploratorydata analysis. Boston: Addison-Wesley. Vygotsky, L. S. (1962). Thoughtand language. Cambridge,MA: MIT Press. Vygotsky, L. S. (1978). Mind in society: The developmentof higher mental processes (M. Cole, V. John-Steiner,S. Scribner,& E. Souberman,Eds.). Cambridge,MA: HarvardUniversity Press. Vygotsky, L. S. (1981) The genesis of higher mental functions. In J. V. Wertsch(Ed.), The concept of activity in Soviet psychology (pp. 148-188). Armonk,NY: Sharpe. Waldrop,M. M. (2002). The dreammachine: J.C.R. Lickliderand the revolutionthat made computing personal. New York:Penguin. Wartofsky,M. (1983). The child's constructionof the world and the world's constructionof the child: From historical epistemology to historical psychology. In F. S. Kessel & A. W. Siegel (Eds.), The child and other cultural inventions(pp. 188-215). New York:Praeger. Wertsch,J. V. (1978, January).Adult-child interactionand the roots of metacognition.Quarterly News- letter of the Institutefor ComparativeHuman Cognition, 1(1), 15-18. Wertsch,J. (1991). Voicesof the mind. Cambridge,MA: HarvardUniversity Press. Wittgenstein,L. (1958). Philosophical investigations.Oxford, England:Blackwell. Wood, D., Bruner,J., & Ross, G. (1976). The role of tutoringin problemsolving. Journal of Child Psy- chology and Psychiatryand Allied Disciplines, 17, 89-100. Wood, D., & Middleton,D. (1975). A study of assisted problemsolving. BritishJournal of Psychology, 66, 181-191.

This content downloaded from 129.79.193.7 on Sun, 14 Jul 2013 15:12:39 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions