Experience Or Language? Choosing Pragmatism's Central Motive” David L
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Language Is a Form of Experience: Reconciling Classical Pragmatism
Abstract The revival of philosophical pragmatism has generated a wealth of intramural debates between neopragmatists like Richard Rorty and contemporary scholars devoted to expli- cating the classical pragmatism of John Dewey and William James. Of all these Language is a internecine conflicts, the most divisive con- cerns the status of language and experience Form of in pragmatist philosophy. Contemporary scholars of classical pragmatism defend expe- Experience: rience as the heart of pragmatism while neo- pragmatists drop the concept of experience Reconciling in favor of a thoroughly linguistic pragma- tism. I argue that both positions engender Classical formidable risks. After discussing the present impasse, I describe a third version of prag- Pragmatism matism which involves a reconstruction of the classical pragmatist concept of experience and in light of the criticisms of foundationalism crucial to the neopragmatist linguistic turn. Neopragmatism This third version of pragmatism does justice to both Rorty and Dewey by focusing on colin koopman experience as a temporal field. Keywords: Richard Rorty, John Dewey, William James, Classical Pragmatism, Neopragmatism, Foundationalism, Myth of the Given, Linguistic Turn Experience and Language in Contemporary Pragmatism The revival of pragmatism by contempo- rary philosophers such as Richard Rorty, Hilary Putnam, and Robert Brandom has generated a wealth of intramural debates between these upstart neopragmatists and contemporary scholars of classical pragma- tism devoted to the work of Charles Peirce, William James, and John Dewey. Of all the internecine conflicts which continue to rage, perhaps the most ink has been spilled TRANSACTIONS OF THE CHARLES S. PEIRCE SOCIETY Vol. 43, No. 4 ©2007 694 over issues concerning the relative priority of language and experience of Experience Language is a Form in pragmatism. -
Curriculum Vitae 2
Dr. Steven M. Levine Curriculum Vitae Academic Employment: Full Professor, University of Massachusetts, Boston, 2019 – present Associate Professor of Philosophy, University of Massachusetts, Boston, 2014 – 2019 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, University of Massachusetts, Boston, 2008 – 2014 Visiting Assistant Professor, University of Arkansas, 2005 - 2007 Education: The New School for Social Research, Ph.D., Philosophy, 2005 University of Colorado, Boulder, B.A., Philosophy, 1995 Areas of Specialty: Pragmatism (Classical and Contemporary) Areas of Competence: Philosophy of Mind, Critical Theory, German Idealism Publications: Books: • Pragmatism, Objectivity, and Experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, March 2019. Papers: • “Experimentalism, Naturalism, and the Grounds of Social Critique,” in Naturalism and Social Philosophy: Contemporary Perspectives, ed. M. Hartman and A. Sarkela, Rowman and Littlefield, forthcoming. • “Pragmatism and Liberal Naturalism,” in Handbook of Liberal Naturalism, Routledge Press, Forthcoming. • “Neopragmatism (Putnam and Habermas),” in A Companion to Rorty, ed. Martin Müller, Springer Press, forthcoming. • “The Speculative Identity of Self and Act: Chapter 15 of the 1932 Ethics,” in John Dewey’s Ethical Theory: The 1932 Ethics, ed. R. Frega and S. Levine, Routledge Press, 2020. • “Rorty, Davidson, and Representation,” in The Wiley-Blackwell Companion to Rorty, ed. A. Malachowski, Wiley-Blackwell Press, 2020. • “Rethinking Sellars’ Naturalism,” in Responses to Naturalism: Critical Perspectives from Idealism and Pragmatism, ed. P. Giladi, Routledge Press, 2019. • “James and Phenomenology,” in The Oxford Handbook of William James, ed. A. Klein, Oxford University Press, published on-line October 2018. 1 • “Sellars and Non-Conceptual Content,” European Journal of Philosophy, 24 (4), Dec. 2016, pp. 855-878. • “Intentionality: Bifurcated or Intertwined?,” International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 24 (4), Oct. -
William James on Risk, Efficacy, and Evidentialism
William James on risk, efficacy, and evidentialism∗ P.D. Magnus March 26, 2020 Forthcoming in Episteme. e-mail: pmagnus(at)fecundity.com ORCID iD: 0000-0002-2446-3494 web: https://www.fecundity.com/job Abstract William James' argument against William Clifford in `The Will to Believe' is often understood in terms of doxastic efficacy, the power of belief to influence an outcome. Although that is one strand of James' argument, there is another which is driven by ampliative risk. The second strand of James' argument, when applied to scientific cases, is tantamount to what is now called the Argument from Inductive Risk. Either strand of James' argument is sufficient to rebut Clifford’s strong evidentialism and show that it is sometimes permissible to believe in the absence of compelling evidence. However, the two considerations have different scope and force. Doxastic efficacy applies in only some cases but allows any values to play a role in determining belief; risk applies in all cases by only allows particular conditional values to play a role. Keywords: William James, evidentialism, doxastic efficacy, inductive risk, ampliative risk In `The Will to Believe' [10, pp. 14-33], William James defends \our right to adopt a believing attitude. in spite of the fact that our merely logical intellect may not have been coerced" [10, p. 14]. The words I've elided with an ellipsis are \in religious matters", and religion is the framing device for his lecture. Nevertheless, philosophers for more than a century have recognized that most of James' arguments face broader epistemic vistas. The issue is whether it is ever permissible to believe a claim in the absence of compelling evidence for it.