arXiv:1911.01696v1 [physics.hist-ph] 5 Nov 2019 n hlspyo cec,e-mail: Science, of Philosophy and Science Math./Natural of Faculty Wuppertal, of University Abstract Scholz Erhard later century back a looking forth and – metric spacetime the Gauging rpslo i ai emtia tutr.I nsnwint new finds phi and It cosmology, physics, century structure. particle a geometrical elementary of extended basic studies been his has g of and to proposal on linked lives success, field methods immediate scalar by geometrical crowned new not Although a physics. hypothesizing energy d by among often interest others), new E attracted Dirac/Canuto/Maeder, geometry (Omote/Utiyama/Kugo, Weyl physicists context (Jo this theory gravitation In in and/ independently, conformal and, al.) of hi et question in Wess, authors the different physic by century reconsidered as were last transformation gauge the scale of original middle the the considered field spinor longer and no functions wave Weyl of alternat phase convincing the a to of it rise translating getting the After after gravity. and program and star research electromagnetism the of was theory It field considerations. physical and philosophical oa cl ag ltrcalled (later gauge scale local .Wy’ rpslo 98frgnrlzn imningeom Riemannian generalizing for 1918 of proposal Weyl’s H. [email protected] elgeometry Weyl eso 01/11/2019 version a oiae ymathematical, by motivated was ) ,adItricpiayCnr o History for Centre Interdisciplinary and s, dn ir,Bas Dicke). Brans, Fierz, rdan, heeg hsc (Bopp, physics energy gh ooh fphysics. of losophy igpito i unified his of point ting nqatmmechanics, quantum in s v o h ag daby idea gauge the for ive lr/iaiShl and hlers/Pirani/Schild iilsoe ihthis with disillusioned hs“eae fWeyl of “retake” this rs npeetday present in erest rlclsaegauge scale local or lyrlvn.About relevant. ally aiyado high and/or ravity ffrn rusof groups ifferent fe elsfirst Weyl’s after tyby etry 1

Contents

Gauging the spacetime metric – looking back and forth a century later version 01/11/2019 ...... 1 Erhard Scholz 1 Introduction...... 4 2 Weyl’sscalegaugegeometry1918–1930...... 6 2.1 Purelyinfinitesimalgeometry,1918-1923 ...... 6 2.2 WithdrawelofscalegaugebyWeylafter1927/29...... 13 3 AnewstartforWeylgeometricgravityinthe1970s ...... 16 3.1 Newinterestsin localscaleand conformaltransformations 16 3.2 Weyl geometric gravity with a scalar field and dynamical scale connection: Omote, Utiyama, Dirac . . . . 20 3.3 Foundationsofgeneralrelativity:EPS ...... 24 3.4 Geometrizingquantummechanicalconfigurationspaces 27 4 Interlude...... 29 4.1 Basicconcepts,notationandIWG...... 29 4.2 Weylgeometricgravity,inparticularinIWG ...... 32 5 Interesttoday...... 35 5.1 Philosophicalreflectionsongravity ...... 35 5.2 Matveev/TrautmanonEPS...... 37 5.3 Howdoesthestandardmodelrelatetogravity?...... 39 5.4 Openquestionsincosmologyanddarkmatter...... 43 6 Anextremelyshortglancebackandforth ...... 48 References...... 49

3 1 Introduction

In 1918 Hermann Weyl proposeda generalizationof Riemannian geometry,which he consideredas betteradaptedto the field theoreticcontextof generalrelativity than the latter. His declared intention was to base geometry on purely “local” concepts which at the outset would not allow to compare field quantities X p and X p at distant ( ) ( ′) points p and p′ of the spacetime manifold, but only for infinitesimally close ones. The possibility of comparing directly two quantities at distant points appearedto him a remnant of Euclidean geometry, which Riemannian geometry had inherited via the Gaussian theory of surfaces. In Weyl’s view Riemann had generalized the latter without putting the comparability of quantities at different locations into question. He demanded in contrast that . . . only segments at the same place can be measured against each other. The gauging of segments is to be carried out at each single place of the world (Weltstelle), this task cannot be delegated to a central office of standards (zentrales Eichamt). (Weyl, 1919, p. 56f., emph. ES)1 Hethereforeconsideredageometryformalizedbyaconformal (pseudo-Riemannian) structureas more fundamentalthan Riemannian geometryitself (Weyl, 1918c,p.13). But it has to be supplemented by a principle which allows for comparing metrical quantities at infinitesimally close points (p , p′), realized by a principle of metrical transfer. A conformal manifold could be qualified as “metrically connected” only if a comparison of metrical quantities at different points is possible: A metrical connection from point to point is only being introduced into it [the manifold, ES], if a principle of transfer for the unit of length from one point P to an infinitesimally close one is given. (Weyl, 1918c, 14)2 Weyl formulated this principle of transfer by introducing what today would be called a connection in the local scaling group R+, i.e., by a real differential 1-form. The new type of “purely infinitesimal geometry” (Weyl’s terminology), later called Weyl geometry, was builtupon thetwo interrelated basic conceptsofa conformal structure and a scale connection as the principle of transfer. Weyl called the latter a length connection. Both were united by the possibility of changing the metrical scale by gauge transformations in the literal sense (see sec. 2.1). For a few years Weyl tried to build a unified field theory of electromagnetism and gravity upon such a geometrical structure, and to extend it to a field theory of matter.3 But in the second half of the 1920s he accepted and even contributed actively to reformulating the gauge idea in the context of the rising new quantum mechanics. Several decades later this idea was generalized to non-abelian groupsand became a fundamental conceptual ingredient even for the lager development of high energy

1 “. . . nur Strecken, die sich an der gleichen Stelle befinden, lassen sich aneinander messen. An jeder einzelnen Weltstelle muß die Streckeneichung vorgenommen werden, diese Aufgabe kann nicht einem zentralen Eichamt übertragen werden” (Weyl, 1919, p. 56f.). (Translation here and in the following by ES, if no reference to a published English translation is given.) 2 Emphasis in the original, here and in other places, where not explicitly stated that it is by ES. 3 Cf. (Vizgin, 1994; Goenner, 2004).

4 physics.4 In the meantime (during the 1940s) Weyl had recanted the importance of scaling transformations (localized “similarities” as he used to call them) for the search of what he called the “physical automorphisms of the world” (see sec. 2.2). The basic idea underlying Weyl’s “purely infinitesimal geometry” of 1918 reap- peared independently at several occasions during the second half of the 20th century. In the early 1960s Carl Brans and Robert Dicke developed their program of a modi- fied general relativistic theory of gravity with a non-minimally coupled scalar field. Dicke stated as an “evident” principle (which it was not, at least not for everyone):

It is evident that the particular values of the units of mass, length, and time employed are arbitrary and that the laws of physics must be invariant under a general coordinate dependent change of units. (Dicke, 1962, p. 2163, emph. ES)

This was very close to Weyl’s view in 1918, but Dicke postulated local scale in- variance without the complementary structure of a scale connection. As a result Brans, Dicke’s PhD student, and Dicke himself developed a theory of gravity which had an implicit relationship to the special type of Weyl geometry with an integrable scale connection, in short integrable Weyl geometry (IWG). Other authors made this relationship explicit and generalized it to the non-integrable case. This was part of a classical field theory program of gravity research, but the importance of conformal transformations got also new input from high energy physics. And even the original form of Weyl geometry had some kind of re- vival from the 1960s onward in scalar field theories of gravity or nuclear struc- tures, initiated by authors in Japan (Omote/Utiyama/Kugo) and, independently Eu- rope/USA (Dirac/Canuto/Maeder), and also in the foundational studies of gravity (Ehlers/Pirani/Schild). This restart in the last third of the 20th century of research building on, and extending, Weyl geometric methods in physics has lasted until today and shows that Weyl’s disassociation from his scale gauge idea is not at all to be considered a final verdict on his geometrical ideas developed between 1918 and the early 1920s. The following paper tries to give an account of the century long development from Weyl’s original scale gauge geometry of 1918 (and the reasons why he thought it an important improvement on the earlier field theories building upon Riemannian geometry), through its temporary disregard induced by the migration of the gauge idea frommetrical scale to quantumphase (ca. 1930–1960,section 2), and the revival in the early 1970s indicated above (section 3), to a report on selected research in physics, which uses Weyl geometric methods in a crucial way (section 5). Basic concepts and notations of Weyl geometric gravity (in the moderately modernized form in which they are used in section 5) are explained in an interlude between the historical account and the survey of present studies (sec. 4). Short reflections on this glance back and forth are given at the end of the paper (section 6).

4 See N. Straumann’s contribution to this volume.

5 2 Weyl’s scale gauge geometry 1918–1930

2.1 Purely infinitesimal geometry, 1918-1923

Parallel to finalizing his book Raum - Zeit - Materie (RZM) (Weyl, 1918b) Weyl developed a generalization of Riemannian geometry, in which an inbuilt concept for a direct metrical comparison of quantities at distant points was no longer foreseen. It was substituted by a comparison in “purely local” regions, in the infinitesimal sense (Weyl, 1918a,c). Weyl introduced this generalization into the third and fourth editions of the book, and added a discussion of what might be the consequences for relativistic field theory and the description of matter. In this way his proposal entered the English translation Space - Time - Matter (STM) of the fourth edition of the book (Weyl, 1922b). It became more widely known than his separate articles on the topic. In a letter dated 1 March 1918 to Albert Einstein, before RZM was publicly available, Weyl announced that the publisher (Springer) would soon send the cor- rected page proofs of the book to Einstein.5 In March the two men met in Berlin, and Weyl used the occasion for presenting his ideas on the generalized theory to Einstein. This started a friendly, but controversial discussion on Weyl’s proposals which would extend through the whole year 1918 and continued to have some reper- cussions in the years to come.6 Weyl submitted his first publication on the topic to the Berlin Academy of Science through Einstein who appended a famous criti- cal note to it (Weyl, 1918a). As Einstein queried, atomic clocks (spectral lines of atoms/molecules) would become dependent on their history, if one assumes that their internal time is subject to Weyl’s local length transfer. Weyl did not share this assumption; he considered the length connection as a part of the general field theoretic structure, which is reflected only indirectly in the behaviour of measuring instruments. This was one difference among others which the two scientists debated in the next few years.7 Other physicists, among them Arthur Eddington and the young Wolfgang Pauli, reacted differently. For a period of a few years they contributed to the dissemination and an elaboration of Weyl’s theory. The latter might have been of particular interest to physicists at the time, because it seemed to open a geometrical road towards a unification of the then known fundamental interactions, electromagnetism and gravity, and was related to the even more ambitious goal of a fundamental theory of matter based on a unified classical field theory along the lines of G. Mie and D. Hilbert. A few years later this early program of a geometrical unification became consid- ered obsolete, when the gauge idea was transformed from geometrical scale to the quantum mechanical phase degree of freedom. In this form it was the starting point for the gauge field theories of the second half of the last century, which became

5 (Einstein, 1987ff., vol. 8, doc 472) 6 (Straumann, 1987; Lehmkuhl, 20yy), all the letters in (Einstein, 1987ff., vol. 8B). 7 The debate between Einstein and Weyl after 1918 is being dealt with in (Lehmkuhl, 20yy).

6 central for the standard model of particle physics. The early parts of this interesting storyhas beentold fromdifferentangles;8 itwillnotberepeatedhere.Thelaterpart– the rise of the standard model – would probablystill deserve more detailed historical investigations.9 Here we concentrate on Weyl’s basic conceptual ideas for gauging the metric of spacetime, which lay at the basis of his new geometry. Not unlike the more general idea of gauge structures (with groups operating on dynamical spaces of field variables) it proved of a wider range and impact than Weyl’s first approach for a physical application in unified field and matter theory. Weyl considered the orthogonality relation specified by a symmetric, non- degenerate (but not necessarily definite) bilinear form in the coordinate differentials as an objective element for introducing a metric (“Maßbestimmung”) in a differen- tiable manifold M. It is given independentlyof any further choice of the description; for a Lorentzian signature it corresponds to the causal structure of spacetime. On the other hand, the scale factor (“Proportionalitätsfaktor”) of the bilinear form is part of the choice of a reference frame (“Bezugssystem”) and defines a metrical gauge (“Eichung”) in the literal sense (Weyl, 1919, p. 58).10 In this sense it is a subjective element of the descriptionlike the choiceof a coordinatesystem and complementary to it (Weyl, 1918c, p. 13). Thus far M carries a conformal structure, or in Weyl’s words a “conformal geometry” (ibid.).11 But this is insufficient for establishing a full-fledged metrical concept in the manifold. Without further stipulations the different points of the manifold would “be completely isolated from each other from the metrical point of view”. Weyl concluded:

A metrical connection between points is being introduced only if a principle of transfer for the unit of length measurement from a point P to an infinitesimally close one is given. (Weyl, 1918c, p.14)12

He specified such a principle of transfer by adding a differential 1-form ϕ = k ϕk dx to the metrical coefficients gik of the chosen reference frame.13 For him the differential form codified the change of squared length quantities l2 = l2 p measured at a point p M to the respective squared lengths l 2 = l2 p measured( ) ∈ ′ ( ′) at a infinitesimally close point p′ expressed by the relation

8 See, among others, (Vizgin, 1994; Sigurdsson, 1991; Goenner, 2004; Scholz, 2006; Ryckman, 2005; Afriat, 2013, 2019). 9 See (Kragh, 1999, chap. 22) (Pickering, 1988; Galison, 1997; Borrelli, 2017, 2015a,b) 10 Page references here and in the following refer to Weyl’s Gesammelte Abhandlungen. 11 The terminology of different structures on a manifold appeared only in the 1940s, essentially due to protagonists of the French community (C. Ehresmann et al.). 12 “Machen wir keine weiteren Voraussetzugen, so bleiben die einzelnen Punkte der Mannig- faltigkeit in metrischer Hinsicht vollständig gegeneinander isoliert. Ein metrischer Zusammenhang wird erst dann in sie hineingetragen, wenn ein Prinzip der Übertragung der Längeneinheit von einem Punkt P zu einem unendlich benachbarten vorliegt. (Weyl, 1918c, p. 14)

13 In fact, Weyl wrote “dϕ = ϕi dxi ” for the differential form, e.g. (Weyl, 1918c, p. 15). In order to avoid confusion with the present notational conventions influenced by Cartan’s symbolism of differential forms, we denote it by ϕ because in general it is not an exact form.

7 2 2 l′ = 1 + ϕ ξ l . (1) ( ( )) Here the infinitesimal displacement of the points isdenoted in terms of a tangent vector ξ Tp M. But then,of course, one has to gain clarity about the transformation ∈ ϕ undergoesif the local scale is changed,i.e. if the metric gµν is conformally changed tog ˜µν = λ x gµν. Weyl realized that consistency of the length transfer idea demands to transform( ) the scale connection ϕ as follows: 1 If g g˜ = λg , then ϕ ϕ˜ = ϕ d log λ, (2) 7−→ 7−→ − 2 = 1 1 i.e.,ϕ ˜µ ϕµ 2 λ− ∂µλ. Weyl called it a “modification of the gauge (Abänderung der Eichung)”(Weyl,− 1919, p. 59); this was the first gauge transformation considered explicitly in the history of mathematics/physics. He showed that a genuine geometry on a manifold M can be built upon such a generalized concept of a gauge metric (later Weylian metric). Slightly reformulated, Weyl characterized his metric by an equivalence class g, ϕ of pairs g, ϕ con- sisting of of a (pseudo-) Riemannian metric g on M and[( a real)] valued differential( ) form ϕ on M, equivalences being given by gauge transformations (2). Gauging the metric boils down to choosing a representative g, ϕ ; its first component g will be called the Riemannian component of the respective( gauge,) the second one ϕ its scale connection form. A clue to this geometry was Weyl’s finding that g, ϕ possesses a uniquely de- termined (in particular gauge independent), metric[( compatible,)] affine connection Γ (in the sense of a symmetric linear connection) like in Riemannian geometry (Weyl, 1918a, p. 33).14 Metric “compatibility” is here understood as the consistency of the length change of vectors under parallel transport by Γ with the length change de- manded by the length transfer ϕ. Γ is gauge independent,although in any gauge g, ϕ it can be decomposed into two gauge dependent terms, the Levi-Civita connection( ) Γ g of g and a scale connection term Γ = Γ ϕ , ( ) ( ) µ 1 µ µ µ Γ = Γ g + Γ ϕ where Γ ϕ = δ ϕλ + δ ϕν gνλ ϕ . (3) ( ) ( ) νλ( ) 2( ν λ − ) Γ induces a gauge independent covariant derivative and has geodesics which are no longer extremal lines of the (gauged) metric but are autoparallels of the invariant affine connection. Weyl derived the curvature tensors for the connections Γ and ϕ. With regard to the affine connection he formed the Weyl geometric curvature tensor analogous to the Riemann tensor in the classical case. Because of this analogyit will be denotedin the following by Riem (with components Rµ ) although it (more precisely its 0, 4 νλκ ( ) type version Rµνλκ ) is not antisymmetric in the first pair of indices. Its contraction Ric is the Weyl geometric Ricci tensor, and R its scalar curvature. Like Γ, the Weyl geometric curvatures can be decomposed, in any gauge g, ϕ , into contributions ( ) derived from the Riemannian part of the metric gµν alone, the Riemannian part of

14 In (Weyl, 1918c, p. 17) Weyl referred also to (Hessenberg, 1917) in this regard.

8 the curvature Riem g = Riem Γ g , and the scale connection part of the curvature Riem ϕ , which is( formally) built( ( like)) the usual Riemann tensor expression from ( ) Γ ϕ , but with covariant derivatives g κ of g in place of the partial derivatives ∂κ.15 ( The) curvature formed with regard∇ to the scale (length) connection is f = dϕ, written in Cartan notation of outer derivatives (which Weyl did not use). It is called the length (scale) curvature. Weyl decomposed the curvature tensor Riem into a con- µ tribution R νλκ with the same symmetry properties as the classical Riemann tensor and a contribution derived from the length curvature, which is not antisymmetric in the first two indices: µ µ 1 µ R = R δ fλκ (4) νλκ νλκ − 2 ν Also this decomposition is gauge independent. Weyl called the first term the direc- tional curvature (“Richtungskrümmung”) (Weyl, 1918c, p. 20). From the directional curvature he constructed a tensor C of type 1, 3 like Riem, ( ) which “depends only on the gjk ”. It is conformally invariant and vanishes in the dimensions n = 2, 3. For n 4, so Weyl announced, it vanishes if the manifold is conformally flat (Weyl, 1918≥c, p. 21). Later it would be called conformal curvature or the Weyl tensor.16 For vanishing length curvature, f = dϕ = 0, the scale connection can be inte- grated locally. Then the corresponding gauge reduces to a Riemannian metric; it will therefore be called the Riemann gauge of the Weylian metric. In this case the curvature tensor reduces to the directional curvature and is identical to the Riemann curvature of the Riemann gauge. Weyl therefore considered Riemannian geometry as a special case of his scale gauge geometry.This was his perspective in RZM from the third edition onward and also in its English version STM (Weyl, 1922b, chap. 2). The generalization of the metrical structure demanded an extension of tensor (of course also of vector and scalar) fields with regard to their scaling properties under a change of metrical gauge. In the third edition of RZM Weyl wrote In a generalised sense we shall, however, also call a linear form which depends on the co-ordinate system and the calibration a tensor, if it is transformed in the usual way when the co-ordinate system is changed, but becomes multiplied by the factor λe (where λ = the calibration ratio) when the calibration is changed; we say that it is of weight e. (Weyl, 1922b, p. 127)17 Weyl considered these fields “merely as an auxiliary conception, which is intro- duced to simplify calculations” (ibid.); but physicists among his readers realized that it would becomeof physicalimportanceif Weyl geometryis accepted as a framework for field theory. Einstein called them “Weyl tensors” (Einstein, 1921, p. 200), Ed- dington introduced the terminology of “co-tensors” or “co-invariants” (Eddington, 1923, p. 202), which is still in use in parts of the physical literature. Here they will be called scale covariant quantities (tensor, vector, scalar fields).

15 Cf. footnote 48; more details in (Yuan, 2013) or in (Eddington, 1923, p. 218f.), (Perlick, 1989, p. 150ff.) etc. 16 That C = 0 is also sufficient for conformal flatness was not clear to Weyl in 1918; he even seemed to exclude it in a side remark. It was proven by Schouten (1921) and later by himself (Weyl, 1921b). 17 In the 5th edition (Weyl, 1923b, p. 127)

9 Weyl’s conjectural unification of gravity and electromagnetism built essentially on the idea of using the length connection ϕ as a symbolic representative of the νλ electromagnetic potential. Then the Maxwell action density fνλ f g for the | | electromagneticfield was of weight 0, if and only if the dimension is n =p4. This was an intriguing argument for the necessary specification of the spacetime dimension 4 in Weyl geometric field theory (Weyl, 1918a, p. 31), (Weyl, 1918/1997, p. 37). In an early response to Weyl’s theory it was praised by Einstein also.18 In order to get a scale invariant gravitational action density, Weyl replaced the Hilbert term R g | | by quadratic expressions in the Weyl geometric curvature, essentially R2 g ,p also | | of weight 0. p In such an approach the Weylian metric seemed to establish a unified description of gravity (gµν and affine connection Γ) and electromagnetism (ϕ and its curvature f = dϕ). But the question of the physical interpretation of the scale invariant geodesics and its relation to the free fall trajectories of neutral and of charged particles had to be answered.This was part of the discussion betweenWeyl and Einstein, aside from Einstein’s spectral line objection to Weyl’s geometrical generalization. For Weyl the latter was no compelling (knock-out) argument. He answered that one has to distinguish between the field theoretic metric and the measure indicated by clocks and rods. The latter would be realized by a specific gauge and ought to depend on the physical behaviour of atomic systems in the local (infinitesimal) neighbourhood of the atom, not on their history. For the time being he proposed to consider the hypothesis that atoms adapt to the local field constellation of the gravitational field in such a manner that the Weyl geometric scalar curvature becomes constant, R = const (Weyl, 1923b, p. 298f.).19 At the time of the fifth edition of RZM (1923) he still kept to the position that the final judgement on his theory would depend on a theory of measurement. Three years later he gave up this idea and joined the interpretation of the electromagnetic potential as a phase connection in the new quantum mechanics. In the two years before the fifth edition, on the other hand, Weyl looked for a deeper philosophical-conceptual underpinning of his geometry in a new analysis of the problem of space (PoS). Half a century earlier Helmholtz had analysed the principles which the motions of a rigid body have to satisfy in order for being able to establish empirical measuring rules. The evaluation of these principles led to classical Euclidean or non-Euclideangeometry.Soon Helmholtz’s principles for free

18 “Ihr Gedankengang ist von wunderbarer Geschlossenheit. Auch der Schluss auf die Dimensions- zahl 4 hat mir sehr imponiert.” (Einstein, 1987ff., vol. 8B, Doc 499, 8 Apr. 1918). Weyl could not keep up this argument after 1927; for his later deliberations see (De Bianchi, 2019). 19 Weyl mentioned this argument already in his letter of 18 Sep. 1918 to Einstein (Einstein, 1987ff., vol. 8B, Doc. 619, p. 877), but introduced it into RZM only in the 5th edition; it is thus not contained in the English translation (Weyl, 1922b). The Weyl geometric scalar curvature R scales with the inverse metric gµν . If it is different from zero it can thus be scaled to a constant like any other non vanishing scalar field of the same scale weight.

10 mobility of rigid rods were rephrased in terms of conditions for the automorphism group of space.20 This analysis became known as the classical PoS. The fusion of space and time in a unified spacetime in special relativity and the loss ofthe conceptofrigidbodyin thegeneraltheorylet Helmholtz’s analysis appear obsolete in the light of relativity. At the end of 1920 Weyl set out for formulating conceptual principles for any type of geometry in a smooth manifold, which builds upon congruenceand similarity operations in the infinitesimal neighbourhoodsonly. As a unifying (“synthetical”) principle he included the postulate of a uniquely deter- mined affine connection and formulated the result of his conceptual analysis in the form of axioms for those subgroups of the general linear group, which may serve as candidates for defining the local similarity and congruence relations in the manifold in the mentioned sense (Weyl, 1921a, 1922a). In 1922 and early 1923 he was able to show that the only groups satisfying his axioms in a manifold of dimension n are the special pseudo-orthogonal groups SO p, q; R as “congruence” groups (p + q = n), with similarities SO p, g; R R+ (Weyl,( 1923)a). If one accepts his characterization of the principles for( infinitesimal)× congruence and similarity relations this can be read as a strong conceptual underpinning for the structure of Weylian manifolds.21 Another conceptual insight of long range was gained by Weyl in a paper which arose as a by-product to a report he wrote for F. Klein on a manuscript by J.A. Schouten (Weyl, 1921b). The manuscripthad been rejected by L.E.J Brouwer for the Mathematische Annalen, but was published a little later in Mathematische Zeitschrift (Schouten, 1921).22 Schouten showed that in dimension n > 3 the vanishing of the conformal tensor C of a Riemannian metric gµν implies local conformalflatness. For Weyl this was new and gave him an incentive to study the projective and conformal viewpoint which he had “touched upon only marginally” in his previous discussions of infinitesimal geometry (Weyl, 1921b,p.201).Hestartedthepaperwiththeremark:

The construction of pure infinitesimal geometry, which I have described most consequentially in the 3rd and 4th edition of my book Raum, Zeit, Materie, is naturally implemented in the three levels which are characterized by the catchwords continuous connection, affine connection, metric. Projective and conformal geometry originate by means of abstraction from the affine respectively the metric one. (Weyl, 1921b, p. 195)23

20 Cf. (Merker, 2010; Bernard, 2018). At first Helmholtz believed to have derived Euclidean geometry alone, but soon learned that non-Euclidean geometry satisfies his principles too. 21 More details in (Bernard, 2015; Bernard/Lobo, 2019; Scholz, 2016). A short version of the argument can also be found in the fifth edition of RZM (Weyl, 1923b), a provisional sketch already in the 4th edition and in (Weyl, 1922b). 22 Klein to Weyl 6.10.1920, Weyl to Klein 28.12.1920, University Library Göttingen, Codex Ms Klein 296, 297. 23 “Der Aufbau der reinen Infinitesimalgeometrie, wie ich ihm am folgerichtigsten in der 3. und 4. Auflage meine Buches Raum, Zeit, Materie geschildert habe, vollzieht sich natürlicherweise in drei Stockwerken, welche durch die Schlagworte stetiger Zusammenhang, affiner Zusammenhang, Metrik gekennzeichnet sind. Die projektive und konforme Geometrie enspringen durch Abstraktion aus der affinen bzw. der metrischen.” (Weyl, 1921b, p. 195)

11 Under “continuous connection (stetiger Zusammenhang)” Weyl understood the pos- sibility to consider infinitesimal neighbourhoods; in present terms it is usually ex- pressed as a smooth structure on the underlying manifold.24 Weyl defined the “projective property (projektive Beschaffenheit)”, in our terms the projective structure of a smooth manifold M, by means of an equivalence class Γ p of affine connections Γ which have “geodesics” (autoparallels) with identical [ ] traces. Γ and Γ are projectively equivalent, if µ = µ + µ + µ Γνλ Γνλ δν ψλ δλ ψν (5)

ν for some differential form ψ = ψν dx . He characterized the conformal structure (“konforme Beschaffenheit”) of M analogously by an equivalence class of affine connections Γ c. Here he considered two affine connections Γ and Γ as belonging [ ] to the same conformal class Γ c, if both are scale invariant affine connections of Weylian metrics g, ϕ and [g˜,]ϕ˜ with conformalRiemannian components,e g g˜. Because of (3) this[( boils)] down[( to)] the condition (Weyl, 1921b, p. 196) ∼

µ µ 1 µ µ µ Γ Γ = δ ϕ + δ ϕ gνλ ϕ (6) νλ − νλ 2( ν λ λ ν − ) e for some differential form ϕ. It is important to realize that this differential form need not be exact (locally integrable), as one would expect if the characterization is read in the context of Riemannian geometry and their Levi-Civita connections.25 On this basis Weyl easily proved the following Theorem 1 (Weyl 1921). A Weylian metric is uniquely determined by its projective and its conformal structures.26

The theorem deals with the comparison of two different classes Γ p, Γ c of affine connections with non-empty intersection (because both arise by[ ] abstraction[ ] from the same presupposed Weylian metric). If Γ and Γ′ are now any two in Γ p Γ c, both arising as affine connections of Weylian metrics g, ϕ , g˜, ϕ˜ ,[ it] has∩[ to] be shown that the latter are identical. In any case the Riemanni[( an)] components[( )] of such two Weylian metrics are conformally equivalent, and the Γ, Γ′ are related by (6). Both Weylian metrics can be gauged to identical Riemannian components, i.e. be given in gauges of the form g, ϕ , resp. g, ϕ . The differential form ϕ in (6) is then ( ) ( ′) ϕ = ϕ ϕ′. As Γ and Γ′ are also projectively equivalent, their difference ∆ = Γ Γ′ − µ ν λ µ − changes a vector ξ such that ∆νλ ξ ξ ξ (here stands for proportionality). ν λ∼ µ ∼ µ Plugging in (6) for ∆ shows that gνλξ ξ ϕ is proportional to ξ for all vectors ξ. This implies ϕ = 0.

24 For a philosophical analysis of this idea see (Bernard, 2013). A modern reconstruction which may even be closer to Weyl’s intentions than their reformulation in terms of standard differential topology, may be possible by differential geometry with infinitesimals; see (Kock, 2006). 25 Matveev/Trautman (2014, 833) makes this restriction, see sec. 5.2. 26 “Satz 1. Projektive und konforme Beschaffenheit eines metrischen Raums bestimmen dessen Metrik eindeutig” (Weyl, 1921b, p. 196).

12 Weyl emphasized the physical importance of this theorem: The conformal struc- ture characterizes the causality relations in spacetime. The projective properties of space are an expression of, in later terminology, the gravito-inertial structure of spacetime. Weyl described it in the following way:

. . . the tendency of persistence of the direction for a moving material particle, which im- presses a certain ‘natural’ motion on it, once it has been set free in a specified world-direction, is the very unity of inertia and gravity, which Einstein put in the place of both, although a suggestive name for it is still lacking (Weyl, 1921b, p.196).27

At the time of the 5th edition of RZM Weyl could claim to have a well-rounded generalized concept of infinitesimal gauge geometry. This geometry was mathemat- ically well developed (uniquely determined affine connection, curvature properties), had a convincing conceptual underpinning in terms of basic physical structures (causality, inertio-gravitational persistence), and could even be given a transcenden- tal philosophical backing (PoS). On the other hand, Weyl’s early enthusiasm for the capacity of his theory for leading to a unified theory of fields and matter had become cracks because of internal technical difficulties of the program (extremely complicated differential equations). Even stronger doubts arose from the growing impression of physicists in the environment of Sommerfeld that quantum physics might make the attempts for a classical field theory of matter obsolete anyhow. Weyl was well aware of such doubts and tended to share them.

2.2 Withdrawel of scale gauge by Weyl after 1927/29

Already in the early 1920s E. Schrödinger had the idea that Weyl’s gauge principle might be useful in a modified form for dealing with the phase of complex wave functions in quantum mechanics, rather than for scale in gravity. This idea was taken up and elaborated by F. London and independently by V. Fock after the turn towards the “new” quantum mechanics. Weyl endorsed it in the first edition of his book on Gruppentheorie und Quantenmechanik (Weyl, 1928, 1st ed., p. 87). A year later Weyl extended this to a general relativistic approach to spinor fields. This led to the now well known representation of the electromagnetic potential by a connection with values in the Liealgebra of the phase group U 1 .28 At the end of the decade Weyl was quite fond of this migration of the gauge( idea) from scale to phase and considered it as a definitive answer to the question how electromagnetism ought to be understood as a gauge theory.

27 “. . . die Beharrungstendenz der Weltrichtung eines sich bewegenden materiellen Teilchens, welche ihm, wenn es in bestimmter Weltrichtung losgelassen ist, eine bestimmte ‘natürliche’ Be- wegung aufnötigt, ist jene Einheit von Trägheit und Gravitation, welche Einstein an Stelle beider setzte, für die es aber bislang an einem suggestiven Namen mangelt” (Weyl, 1921b, p.196). 28 See (Vizgin, 1994, p. 274ff.), (Straumann, 2001; Scholz, 2005; Afriat, 2013) and N. Straumann’s contribution to this volume.

13 The 1930 Rouse Ball lecture at Cambridge university gave him an opportunity for explaining his view of the program of geometrical unification to a wider scientific audience. He explained his own theory of 1918 and summarized its critical reception by physicists. He reviewed Eddington’s approach to unification by affine connections and Einstein’s later suppport for that program, always in comparison with his own “metrical” unification of 1918. He concluded that in hindsight one could consider both theory types merely as “geometrical dressings (geometrische Einkleidungen) rather than proper geometrical theories of electricity”. He added with irony that the struggle between the metrical and affine unified field theories (UFT), i.e. his own 1918 theory versus Eddington/Einstein’s, had lost importance. In 1930 it could no longer be the question which of the theories would “prevail in life”,but only “whether the two twin brothers had to be buried in the same grave or in two different graves” (Weyl, 1931, 343). All in all Weyl perceived a scientific devaluation of the UFT’s of the 1920s, resulting from developments in the second part of the decade:

In my opinion the whole situation has changed during the last 4 or 5 years by the detec- tion of the matter field. All these geometrical leaps (geometrische Luftsprünge) have been premature, we now return to the solid ground of physical facts. (Weyl, 1931, 343) He continued to sketch the theory of spinor fields, their phase gauge and its inclusion into the framework of general relativity along the lines of his 1929 articles. Weyl emphasized that, in contrast to the principles on which the classical unified field theories had been built, the new principle of phase gauge “has grown from experience and resumes a huge treasury of experimental facts from spectroscopy” (ibid. 344). He still longed for safety, just as much as at the time after the First World War, when he had designed his first gauge unification. Now he no longer expected to achieve it by geometric speculation, but tried to anchor it in more solid grounds:

By the new gauge invariance the electromagnetic field now becomes a necessary appendix of the matter field, as it had been attached to gravitation in the old theory. (Weyl, 1931, 345, emphasis in original) In this way Weyl made it clear that he had changed his perspective. He no longer saw a chance in attempts to derive matter in highly speculative approaches from mathematical structures devised to geometrize force fields; he now set out searching for mathematical representations of matter which was based on the “huge treasury” of experimental knowledge. For him, this was reason enough to prefer the view that the electrical field ”follows the ship of matter as a wake, rather than gravitation” (ibid.). This paper indicates a re-evaluation of Weyl’s view of geometry with regard to those of the early 1920s. This change of mind took place at the turn to the 1930s and is not yet present in the first German edition of his book Philosophie der Mathematik und Naturwissenschaften (Weyl, 1927), but it is in the English translation for which the author formulated text amendments and changes during 1948/49 (Weyl, 1949a). These changes were taken over into the German third edition (after Weyl’s death). In a talk with the title Similarity and congruence given during the time when he worked on the changes for Philosophy of Mathematics and Natural Science Weyl discussed the topic of automorphism groups as a clue for establishing objectivity

14 of symbolic knowledge in mathematics and in physics.29 Weyl hoped to be able to clearly distinguish between physical and mathematical automorphisms. The latter were characterized by him as the normalizer of the former – leaving open the ques- tion in which larger group the normalizer was to be taken. For classical physics this was relatively simple: the physical automorphisms of classical physics are given by the Galilei group(including Euclideancongruences),and the mathematical automor- phisms are the similarity transformationsextending the Galilei group. Weyl therefore used the pair similarities/congruences also in the general case as synonymous with the dichotomy mathematical/physical automorphisms. Of course it is a difficult question to decide what the physical automorphisms are; but Weyl was sure that this is a central task of physics:

The physicist will question Nature to reveal him her true group of automorphisms (Weyl, 2017/1949b, p. 156).

For relativistic physics, so Weyl argued in 1949, the physical automorphisms were given by the diffeomorphisms Diff M of the spacetime manifold M, extended by point dependent operations of G =( SO) 1, 3 U 1 . In hindsight Weyl’s physical automorphisms of relativistic physics may( be)× considered( ) as an informal characteri- zation of a gauge group G P ante letteram with respect to a principal bundle P over M with the group G. In his( ) view the mathematical automorphisms were then the corresponding “similarities” given by the extension from G to G = G R+.30 In the view of the mature Weyl, the contemporary knowledge of the 1930/40s× in quantum physics clearly spoke for reducing the physical automorphismse to the group G.

The atomic constants of charge and mass of the electron atomic constants and Planck’s quantum of action ~, which enter the universal field laws of nature, fix an absolute standard of length, that through the wave lengths of spectral lines is made available for practical measurements (Weyl, 2017/1949b, p. 161).31

In the 1940s Weyl no longer considered the local scale extension from G to G as part of physics, but of mathematics only. Taking up his language of 1919 in the discussion with Einstein, the laws of quantum mechanics and the universal constantse ~, e, me had now taken over the role of the central office of standards. For Weyl, this( was) a definitive good bye to the idea of localized standards of length/time due to an adaptation of atomic oscillators to local field constellations and from the view that his scale gauge geometry is an adequate conceptual framework for gravity and field theory. He did not care about an interesting observationmade by Jan A. Schouten and Jan Haantjes inthe 1930s,whoarguedthatnotonlythe(vacuum)Maxwellequations, but also the equations of motion of test mass particles (with or without Lorentz forces) can be written in a scale covariant form, if only the mass parameter m is being 1 transformed scale covariantly with quadratic Weyl weight 2 (Schouten/Haantjes, 1934, 1936; Haantjes, 1941). At the time, this was an unusual− point of view. Pauli

29 This talk is published in (Weyl, 2017/1949b) 30 For more details see (Scholz, 2018b). 31 Similarly in PMN.

15 argued that only the massless Dirac equation could be considered as scale invariant (Pauli,1940); asimilar pointof viewhad beenexpressedbyWeyl in the context of the general relativistic Dirac equation (Weyl, 1929). Schouten’s and Haantjes’ common proposal to consider mass parameters as scaling quantities indicated a path toward including massive spinor fields into a basically conformal – or correspondingly a Weyl geometric – framework; but at the time it was not widely noted.

3 A new start for Weyl geometric gravity in the 1970s

3.1 New interests in local scale and conformal transformations

In the early 1950s and 1960s Pascual Jordan, later Robert Dicke and Carl Brans (JBD) proposed a widely discussed modification of Einstein gravity (Jordan, 1952; Brans/Dicke, 1961; Dicke, 1962). Essential for their approach was a (real valued) scalar field χ, coupled to the Hilbert action term. Its Lagrangian density was

ω µ JBD = χR ∂ χ∂µ χ det g , (7) L ( − χ ) | | p where ω isafreeparameterofthetheoryand Rthescalar curvatureof theRiemannian metric g. Jordan had started from a projective version of a 5-dimensional Kaluza- Klein approach. He arrived at a Lagrangian of form (7) only after several steps of simplifications and interpreted the scalar field as a varying gravitational parameter (replacing the gravitational constant).32For ω the theory has Einstein gravity as limiting case. All three authors allowed for conformal→∞ transformations of the metric, g˜ = λg; but only Brans and Dicke understood them as an expression for a local scale transformation under which also the scalar field χ transforms with (quadratic length) = 1 weight 1 (matter fields and energy tensors T with weight w T 2 etc.). Jordan− started considering conformal transformations onl(y after) − Pauli had made him aware of such a possibility; he discussed them in the second edition of his book (Jordan, 1952). Pauli must have been aware of the closeness of this principle to Weyl’s scale geometry; in his youth he had been one of the experts for it. But neither he nor Jordan, looked at the new scalar tensor theory from this point of view. The migration of the gauge idea from scale to phase geometry seems to have been considered by them, like by Weyl himself, as definitive. The US-American authors nearly a decade later were probably not even aware of the parallel.33

32 For technical details see (Goenner, 2012, pp. 31ff.), for the physical interpretation and the historical context (Kragh, 2016, pp. 45ff, 65ff.); a conceptual analysis will be given in (Lehmkuhl, 202x). 33 In retrospect C. Brans wrote regarding this question:“I believe (but am not sure) that I knew of other UFT’s, especially Kaluza-Klein, but do not know if I was aware of Weyl’s conformal work. I wish I could be more definite, but the best answer I can give to your question of whether Bob or I was aware of Weyl’s conformal scalar field is ‘probably not’.” (e-mail of C. Brans to the author, 19 June, 2012)

16 Maybe this ignorance was an advantage. Dicke did not hesitate when advocating conformal rescaling. He frankly declared it as an obvious postulate that the “laws of physics must be invariant under a general coordinate dependent change of units” (see quote in the introduction, p. 5). He did not mention that this would demand a basic restructuring, or at least reformulation of fundamental theories, although he must have been aware of it. The postulate itself agreed with Weyl’s intentions of 1918. In a long appendix to his letter of 16 Nov. 1918 to Einstein, published in extended form during the next year, Weyl had stated

Einstein’s present theory of relativity (. . . ) only deals with the arbitrariness of the coordinate system; but it is important to gain a comparable foundational stance with regard to (. . . ) the arbitrariness of the measurement of units (Weyl, 1919, p. 55).34

Knowing more about Weyl’s trajectory, who had recanted this viewpoint in the 1940s, might only have been a hindrance for developing the new scalar tensor theory, or at least the inclusion of the conformal transformations viewpoint into it. By “coordinate dependent change of units” Dicke and Brans indicated a point dependent rescaling of basic units. In the light of the relations established by the fundamental constants (velocity of light c, Planck constant ~, elementary charge e and Boltzmann constant k) all units can be expressed in terms of one independent fundamental unit, e.g. time, and the fundamental constants (which, in principle can be given any constantnumericalvalue, which then fixes the system).35 Thus only one essential scaling degree of units remains, and Dicke’s principle of an arbitrary point dependent unit choice comes down to a “passive” formulation of Weyl’s localized similarities in his scale gauge geometry, where dimensional constants are to be treated as scale covariant scalar fields with the respective Weyl weights. A closer look shows that Dicke’s boastful postulate that the “laws of physics must be invariant” under point dependent rescaling was not fully realized in JBD theory. The modified Hilbert term of (7) is formulated in terms of the Riemannian scalar curvature and is not scale invariant. The practitioners of JBD theory understand it as defined in a specific scale (the Jordan frame) and apply well known correction terms under conformal rescaling. This defect can easily be cured if one reformulates the theory in terms of a simple version, i.e. integrable, Weyl geometry (see sec. 5.1).

34 “Die bisherige Einsteinsche Relativitätstheorie bezieht sich nur auf (. . . ) die Willkürlichkeit des Koordinatensystems; doch gilt es eine ebenso prinzipielle Stellungnahme zu (. . . ) der Willkür- lichkeit der Maßeinheiten zu gewinnen” (Weyl, 1919, p. 55). 35 For the recent revision of the international standard system SI see (Hehl/Lämmerzahl, 2019). It has implemented measurement definitions with time as only fundamental unit, uT = 1 s such that 133 “the ground state hyperfine splitting frequency of the caesium 133 atom ∆ν Cs hfs is exactly 9 192 631 770 hertz” (Bureau International, 2011, 24f.). In the New SI, four( of the) SI base units, namely the kilogram, the ampere, the kelvin and the mole, will be redefined in terms of invariants of nature (www.bipm.org/en/si/new si/). The redefinition of the meter in terms of the basic time unit by means of the fundamental constant− c was implemented already in 1983. Point dependence of the time unit because of the locally varying gravitational potential on the surface of the earth is inbuilt in this system. For practical purposes it can be outlevelled by reference to the SI second on the geoid (standardized by the International Earth Rotation and Reference Systems Service IERS). Some, only seemingly paradoxical, consequences in the description of astronomical distances are being discussed by T. Schücker, this volume.

17 In spite of such a (minor) formal deficiency, the three proponents of JBD theory unknowingly brought their approach quite close to Weyl geometry by fixing a unique affine connection rather than changing it with the conformal transformation. They postulated the Levi-Civita connection Γ := Γ g of the Riemannian metric g in (7), called the Jordan frame, as unchanging under( ) conformal transformations. In a different scale gauge, or frame,g ˜ = λg they just had to express Γ in terms of the Levi-Civita connection Γ g˜ plus correction terms in derivatives of λ (equivalent to (5)). Let us summarily denote( ) these additional terms by by ∆ ∂λ , then ( )

Γ = g˜Γ + ∆ ∂Ω . ( ) Roger Penrose noticed that the additional terms of the (Riemannian) scalar curvature are exactly cancelled by the partial derivative terms of the kinematical term of χ if = 3 and only if ω 2 . In this case, and in JBD theory only in this case, the Lagrangian (7) is conformally− invariant (Penrose, 1965). Probably the protagonists considered the invariance of the affine connection Γ as a consequence of the principle that the “laws of nature” have to be considered as invariant under conformal rescaling. If the trajectories of test bodies are governed by the gravito-inertial “laws of physics” they should not be subject to change under a transformation of units. The same must then hold for the affine connection which can be considered a mathematical concentrate of these laws. Thus passive conformal rescaling, in addition to fixing an affine connection, have become basic tools of JBD theory.36 JBD theory originated at a time when symmetry aspects attracted more and more attention by high energy particle physics. Here symmetries were often not considered as exactly realized, but as somehow “hidden” or even “broken”.37 Also conformal transformations were now being reconsidered in field physics. Werner Heisenberg took up the idea of Haantjes and Schouten and proposed to consider rescaling of mass parameters as a legitimate symbolic procedure (Heisenberg, 1957); and so did other elementary particle physicists.38 In this context it became a standard procedure to associate scale weights to physical fields. For a detailed historical report see (Kastrup, 2008). Of course, elementary particle physicists were not interested in conformal trans- formations of general Lorentzian manifolds; they dealt exclusively with the group Conf M of conformal transformations of the (conformal) compactification M, of Minkowski( ) space. The group can be expressed as the subgroup of projective trans- e 5 e formations in real projective space P R with projective coordinates u0,... u5 , which leaves the hyperbolic quadric Q 2(, 4) [ ] ( )

36 For an outline of conformal transformation as used in JBD see (Wald, 1984, app. D); surveys on the actual state of JBD theory and its applications to cosmology are given in (Fujii/Maeda, 2003; Faraoni, 2004). 37 See (Borrelli, 2015a, 2017). 38 Among them J. Wess (1959, 1960) and H. Kastrup (1962a,b).

18 4 u2 + u2 u2 = 0 0 5 − j Õj=1 invariant. The embedding of Minkowski space M ֒ Q 2, 4 P5 R is given by → ( )⊂ ( )

1 2 1 2 x0,... x3 u0,..., u3, x + 1 , x 1 , ( ) 7−→ [ 2(| | ) 2(| | − )]

2 2 3 2 with x = x = x . This was well known at the time.39 But the understanding | | o − j 1 j of the reciprocal transformations(inversions)Í with regard to Lorentzian hyperboloids rather than to euclidean spheres was hampered for some time because of confused attempts to interpret them as an expression for transformations of relatively acceler- ated observersystems. Such proposals had been made in the 1930/40s, among others by Haantjes (1941). They lived until the mid 1960s, although it was clear to a part of the community that this was misleading.40 Hans Kastrup for example, developed an interpretation with point dependent measuring standards for describing the effects of hyperboloidal inversions and studied the representations of the full conformal group on scalar and spinor fields with the hope that the inversions would, at least, turn out to be approximative symmetries of a conformal field theory (Kastrup, 1966), . In the discussion of the point dependent standards he explicitly referred back to Weyl’s scale gauge method of 1918 (Kastrup, 1966, p. 150), although the wider scope of Weyl geometry was of no importance for his investigations. The questions regarding the inversions posed in the GR community were dif- ferent. Penrose gave a detailed geometrical analysis of the light cone at infinity in Minkowski space (Penrose, 1964). From such a point of view it became clear that the reciprocal transformations are mappings between conformal infinity and finite light cones, which induce a conformally deformed metric (with regard to the Minkowski metric) in the neighbourhoodof the latter. In general relativity such transformations were useful for studying fields in asymptotic flat spacetimes. They even became a step towards better understanding the asymptotic behaviour of general relativistic spacetimes also in more general cases.41 In this sense, hyperboloid inversions, or their relatives in more general spacetimes, remained at best “mathematical automor- phisms” in the language of Weyl, useful for technical reasons rather than for physical ones. In the high energy context, on the other hand, reciprocal transformations had a different appeal, in particular if applied to the energy-momentumspace (in a physical sense dual to Minkowski spacetime). If everything went well, they seemed to allow conformal field theory searching for relationships between field states in extremely high energies/momenta and extremely small energy/momentum states close to a finite light cone, even though such inversion symmetries might perhaps be “hidden” or “broken” and indicate the relations only in a modified form. In this sense, the

39 Such a representation of Conf M is sketched, e.g., in (Weyl, 1923b, p. 302f.). ( ) 40 (Kastrup, 2008, p. 659ff.) e 41 (Frauendiener, 2000).

19 understanding of conformal symmetries in high energy physics was characterized by an active understanding in the perspective of extending the “physical” automorphisms in Weyl’s description of 1948/49. Such differences of outlook my have contributed to the unhappy constellation that the interchange between general relativity and conformal field theory (in Minkowski space) remained rather weak. As far as I can see, there were mutual methodological challenges between the fields, but no a closer exchange.

3.2 Weyl geometric gravity with a scalar field and dynamical scale connection: Omote, Utiyama, Dirac

In 1971 Minoru Omote, Tokyo, introduced a scale covariant scalar field φ coupling to the Hilbert term and scaling like in JBD theory into the framework of Weyl geometry (Omote, 1971).42 A second paper by Omote followed after the publication of apaperbyP.A.M. Diracwith a similar proposal(Dirac, 1973) andafter R. Utiyama had jumped in (Omote, 1974) (for both authors see below). Alexander Bregman, at that time working at Kyoto, was inspired by Omote’s proposal to separate localized rescaling from Weyl’s geometrical interpretation of the infinitesimal length transport (Bregman, 1973). He argued that the point-dependentscale transformations could be treated “analogous to the introduction of a space-time dependence into the constant parameters of Isospin or Poincaré transformations” (ibid. p. 668). This brought the approach closer to what high energy physicists were doing at the time, although only the scale extended Poincaré group was localized, not the complete conformal group of Minkowski space. The global scale dimensions d of a physical field X could then be taken over as “Weyl weight” of X to the localized theory (Bregman, 1973, p. 668). With such a proposal he followed the lines of the research program for constructing general relativistic theories of gravity by “localizing” the symmetriesof the Poincaré group, which had been opened by D. Sciama and T. Kibble (Kibble, 1961; Sciama, 1962).43 A little later, more or less parallel to Dirac, Ryoyu Utiyama, Toyonaka/Osaka, joined the new start of a Weyl geometric approach to gravity (Utiyama, 1973). Bregman’s approach seemed to have triggered his interest which lay mainly in elementary particle physics.44 Different from Dirac and, of course also from Weyl, he saw in the nontrivial Weylian scale connection ϕ a candidate for a new fundamental field of high energy physics, the Weyl gauge field or, later, the Weyl boson.Ina series of papers (Utiyama, 1973, 1975a,b) he ventured toward a bosonic interpretation of ϕ and presented his results at the Seventh International Conference on Gravitation and Relativity (Tel Aviv, June 1974). Utiyama emphasized that in Weyl geometry

42 This was more than a year before the Trieste symposium at which Dirac talked about the same question (see below), while it seems that Omote’s paper remained unknown to him. 43 See (Blagojević/Hehl, 2013). 44 In his first paper of 1973 Utiyama did not mention Omote. This changed in later papers, see the references of (Utiyama, 1975a).

20 a scalar field φ of weight 1 could serve as a kind of measure field (Utiyama’s terminology). With respect− to it gauge invariant measurable quantities could be defined for physical observable without assuming a breaking of the scale gauge symmetry (Utiyama, 1973, 1975b). Utiyama proposed to explore the ordinary Yang-Mills Lagrangian term for a Weylian scale connection

1 µν ϕ = ε fµν f det g here with ε = 1 (8) L − 4 | | ( ) p (Utiyama, 1975b, eq. (2.4)).45 He studied conditions under which “Weyl’s gauge field” admitted plane wave solutions, and came to the conclusion that they would be tachyonic, allowing superluminal propagation of perturbations. In Utiyama’s view the “boson” had therefore to be confined to the interior of matter particles. Nevertheless he thought that this “unusual field ϕµ might play some role in establishing a model of a stable elementary particle” (Utiyama, 1973, 2089). This view was not accepted by all his readers. Kenji Hayashi and Taichiro Kugo, two younger colleagues from Tokyo resp. Kyoto, reanalysed Utiyama’s calculations and argued that, with slight adaptations of the parameters, the sign ε in (8) could be switched. Then an ordinary, at least non-tachyonic, field would result (Hayashi/Taichiro, 1979, 340f.). Even then the scale connection would still have strange physical properties. After introducing Weyl geometric spinor fields and their Lagrangiansin terms of scale co- variant derivatives, the two physicists showed that the scale connection terms cancel in the spinor action. In their approach neither the scalar φ-field nor the scale connec- tion ϕ coupled directly to spinor field or to the electromagnetic field. The new fields φ, ϕ seemed to characterize an extension of the gravitational sector with no direct interaction with the known elementary particles. At the very moment that a Weylian scale connection ϕ was interpreted as a physical field beyond electromagnetism, it started to puzzle its investigators. It seemed to pose more riddles than it was able to solve. It did not to couple to matter fields (Hayashi/Kugo), looked either tachyonic (Utiyama) or, as we shall see below (Smolin, Nieh, Hung Cheng), appeared to be of Planck mass, far beyond anything observable. Independent of the Japanese physicists, and mor or less at the same time, Paul Adrien Maurice Dirac brought Weyl geometry back into the rising field scalar-tensor theories,althoughwith different interpretationsfromhis Japanese colleaguesin mind (Dirac, 1973, 1974). His motivation had two components which may look strange from today’s point of view. He started from the speculation that some long noticed interrelations of certain large numbers in physics indicated a deep structural law of the universe (the “large number hypothesis”) and the idea of a varying gravity. Both ideas had their origin in the 1930s, and also P. Jordan had taken them up.46 Dirac presented his ideas at the occasion of a symposium at Trieste 1972, honouring his

45 Dirac included a similar scale curvature term in his Lagrangian, but with another interpretation (see below). 46 For Dirac’s and Jordan’s ideas on the large number hypothesis, varying gravity and a surprising link to geophysics in the 1930s see the detailed study in (Kragh, 2016).

21 70th birthday. The talk remained unpublished but participants report that its content was close to publication in the following year (Dirac, 1973).47 Dirac’s paper was important for the transmission of knowledge between genera- tions. He introduced his readers to Weyl geometry which was no longer generally known among younger physicists, following Eddington’s notation and terminology of “co-invariants” for scale covariant fields (Eddington, 1923). He also added the important concept of the scale-covariant derivative D , respectively Dµ (in later terminologyand notation), for scale covariant fields to the methodological arsenal of Weyl geometry (see below, eq. (15)). It is a necessary modification of the covariant derivative of scale covariant fields for arriving again at a scale covariant fields. He called it, virtually stuttering, the “co-covariant” derivative. Similar to Jordan/Brans/Dicke – and like Omote/Bregman/Utiyama, the publica- tions of which he apparently did not know – Dirac introduced a scalar field called β and rescaling with the (non-quadratic) length weight 1 and coupledit to the Hilbert term expressed by the sign-inverted Weyl geometric− scalar curvature R.48 Thus he replaced Weyl’s gravity Ansatz in the Lagrangian, using square curvature terms, by a scale invariant Lagrangian ( Dir = LDir g ) of first order in R, L | | p 2 λ 4 1 µν LDir = β R + kD β Dλ β + cβ + fµν f . (9) − 4 The quartic potential for β was demanded by scale invariance. f = dϕ denoted the Weylian scale curvature. Different from the Japanese physicists, Dirac stuck to the outdated interpretation of the scale connection ϕ as the potential of the electromagnetic (Maxwell) field Fµν

Fµν = fµν . (10)

In the sequel I call this the electromagnetic (em) dogma . For the coupling constant of the kinetic term, k = 6, the contributions of the scale connection to the Lagrangian cancel essentially.49 Dirac knew that for k , 6 a large mass term for the Weyl field ϕ arises, which would destroy the em-dogma interpretation; so he chose k = 6. As a result Dirac could write the Lagrangian in a form using only the (sign inverted)Riemannian component gR of the scalar curvature

2 λ 4 1 µν Dir 1 = β gR + 6∂ β∂λ β + cβ + fµν f , (11) L − 4 It was already known to be conformally invariant (Penrose, 1965), and only the specific Weyl geometric interpretation of the em potential was added.

47 (Charap/Tait, 1974, p. 249 footnote) 48 The qualifications “sign inverted” refers to the sign convention which agrees with the definition = µ = µ µ + α µ α µ Riem Y, Z X Y Z X Z Y X Y, Z X, i.e. R νλκ ∂λΓνκ ∂κ Γνλ Γνκ Γαλ ΓνλΓακ . It is preferred( ) in the∇ mathematical∇ −∇ ∇ literature−∇[ including] (Weyl, 1918b, 5th− ed., 131) and also− used in the majority of recent physics books. 49 They reduce to boundary terms and thus are variationally negligible.

22 If it had notbeen Dirac, suchan approachwouldprobablynothave attracted much interest in the physics community. But he also derived dynamical equations and the Noether identities for diffeomorphisms and scale transformations. For a vanishing em field, fµν = 0, he distinguished the Riemann gauge with ϕ = 0 (called by him “natural gauge”) from the Einstein gauge (with the gravitational parameter constant, β = 1) and a hypothetical atomic gauge characterized as “the metric gauge that is measured by atomic apparatus” (Weyl’s “natural gauge”) and warned that “all three gauges are liable to be different” (Dirac, 1973, 411). At the end of his article Dirac discussed why one should believe in the proposed “drastic revision of our ideas of space and time”. He announced another part of his research agenda, which was independent of the large number hypothesis:

There is one strong reason in support of the theory. It appears as one of the fundamental principles of Nature that the equations expressing basic laws should be invariant under the widest possible group of transformations . . . The passage to Weyl’s geometry is a further step in the direction of widening the group of transformations underlying physical laws. (Dirac, 1973, 418)

So far, Dirac’s explanations were close to the view of Brans and Dicke. He followed a tendency of the time for probing possible extensions of the symmetries (automorphisms) of fundamental physics and saw a new chance for Weyl geometry to play its part in such an endeavour. Dirac’s proposal for reconsidering Weyl geometry in a modified theory of gravity was taken up by field theorists, gravitational physicists and a few astronomers. An immediate and often quoted paper by Vittorio Canuto and coauthors gave a broader and more detailed introduction to Dirac’s view of Weyl geometry in gravity and field theory (Canuto et al., 1977). The opening remark of the paper motivated the renewed interest in Weyl geometry with actual developments in high energy physics:

In recent years, owing to the scaling behavior exhibited in high-energy particle scattering experiments there has been considerable interest in manifestly scale-invariant theories. (Canuto et al., 1977, 1643)

With the remark on “considerable interest in manifestly scale-invariant theories” in high energy physics the authors referred to scaling in high energy physics and, in particular,the seminal paper (Callan et al., 1970). But the authorswere careful not to claim field theoretic reality for Dirac’s scalar function β (Canuto et al., 1977, 1645). They rather developed model consequences for the approach in several directions: cosmology, including the “large number hypothesis as a gauge condition” (ibid. 1651), modification of the Schwarzschild solution in the Dirac framework, conse- quences for planetary motion, and structure. At the end the authors indicated certain heuristic links to gauge fields in high energy physics of the late 1970s. Dirac’s retake of Weyl geometric gravityand field theory had wider repercussions than mightbe expectedif one takes his insistence on the em-dogmainto account. The scope of the approachwas much wider without it, and a lot of authors with different backgrounds and diverging research interests started again to explore the potential of Weyl’s geometry for widening the geometric framework of gravity, most of them without subscribing to the em-dogma. Here I can only hint summarily at a sample

23 from different groups or individual authors who took part in this exploration during the following decades until, roughly, the end of the century. Among them were P. Bouvier and A. Maeder, Geneva, from astronomy (Bouvier/Maeder, 1977, 1979; Maeder, 1980);50 N. Rosen, the former collaborator of Einstein, and his PhD student M. Israelit came from gravitational theory (Rosen, 1982; Israelit/Rosen, 1992, 1995; Israelit, 1999), and from cosmology M. Novello with a growing group of researchers in Brazil (Novello, 1986; Novello et al., 1993). Other authors like L. Smolin, W. Drechsler, his PhD student H. Tann and H. Cheng, working in fundamental or high energy physics, also took up Weyl geomteric methods (Smolin, 1979; Drechsler, 1991; Drechsler/Tann, 1999b; Drechlser, 1999; Cheng, 1988). Most of these authors worked at different places and separated from each other; only in rare cases they knewandcited the respective worksof their colleagues.Inspite ofthe risingnumbers of papers and authors during the last third of the 20th century one cannot speak of the birth of a literary network or even of a scientific subcommunity of Weyl geometrically oriented work in theoretical physics. Once in a while also researchers studying gravitational gauge fields in the Cartan geometric approach considered Weylgeometryasaspecialcaseoftheirwiderprogram,withor without the additional feature of translational curvature; among them notably J. Charap, W. Tait, F.W. Hehl and E. Mielke (Charap/Tait, 1974; Hehl et al., 1988a,b). – This list is, of course, far from exhaustive.51

3.3 Foundations of general relativity: EPS

About the same time at which Dirac and the Japanese physicists were using Weyl geometry in the context of scalar tensor theories new interest in Weyl’s geometry of 1918 arose also in the research on the foundations of gravity. Weyl’s argument of (Weyl, 1921b) that the combination of projective and conformal structures suffice for uniquely characterizing a Weyl geometric structure was taken up, abstracted and extended half a century later by Jürgen Ehlers, Felix Pirani and Alfred Schild (EPS in the sequel) (Ehlers et al., 1972). The EPS paper was written for a Festschrift in the honour of J.L. Synge. Synge was known for his proposal of basing general relativity on the behaviour of standard clocks rather than length measurements (chronometric approach).52 From the foundational point of view, however, clocks are no less unproblematic for defining the metric of spacetime, because they are realized by complicated material systems and would need a validated theory of time measurement for a foundational justification. The question suggested itself, whether the physical metric can be determined on the basis of more elementary signal structures of gravitational theory than material clocks, e.g. by like light rays, particle trajectories etc. Weyl’s paper of 1921 had sketched such a type of approach.

50 In recent publications A. Maeder has taken again up this line of research (Maeder, 2017b,c, 2018), see section 5.4. 51 For a more extended, although still incomplete, survey see (Scholz, 2018a). 52 Compare similar remarks in T. Schücker’s contribution to this volume.

24 EPS analysed Weyl’s idea of 1921 in detail, using the mathematical language of differentiable manifolds and mimicking, at least to a certain degree, Hilbert’s ax- iomatic method.They started from three sets, = p, q,... , = L, N,... , = P, Q,... representing the collections of events,M light{ rays and} Lparticle{ trajectories} P respectively.{ } By postulates close to physical experimental concepts of light signal exchange between particles EPS formulated different groups of axioms, which al- lowed them to conclude that the event set could be given the structure of a (C3-) differentiable manifold M endowed withM a conformal structure c, the null-lines of which agree with , and a projective structure of (C2-) differentiable paths in agree- ment with . TheL latter can equivalently be described by a projective equivalence = P = λ class p Π of affine connections Π Πµν (ibid. p. 77). In an additional axiom C (ibid. p. 78)[ ] they secured the compatibility between the structures c and p, with the upshot (C′) that the null lines of the conformal cones of c are projective geodesics of p (ibid. 78–80).53 In the light of this result the criterion for compatibility of c and p in the sense of EPS can be stated as follows:

A projective structure p and a conformal structure c will be called EPS-compatible, if the null lines of c are projective geodesics (autoparallels) of p.

This criterion was new. For Weyl the compatibility of p and c was no independent problem,because he supposed both to be abstracted from a the affine connection of a Weylian metric (assumed to exist in advance). From the viewpointof the EPS context a modernized definition of Weyl compatibility can be stated as follows (compare sec. 2.1):

Definition. The conformal and projective structures c and p are said to be Weyl compatible, if for some g c a differential 1-form ϕ can be found such that the affine connection Γ g, ϕ of the Weyl metric∈ g, ϕ satisfies Γ g, ϕ p.54 ( ) [( )] ( ) ∈ In distinction to the Riemannian case ϕ need, of course, not be integrable. Using their new concept of compatibility EPS derived their main statement:

A light ray structure and a set of particle trajectories defined on an event set which satisfy the EPS axiomsL endow with the structure ofP a (C3-) differentiable manifoldM M and specify a (C2-) Weylian metricM g, ϕ upon M. The metric is uniquely determined by the condition that its causal and geodesic[( structures)] coincide with and respectively. L P If one accepts the argumentation, this was an important result. The authors were cautious enough, however, to qualify their result by the remark:

A fully rigorous formalization has not yet been achieved, but we nevertheless hope that the main line of reasoning will be intelligible and convincing to the sympathetic reader (Ehlers et al., 1972, p. 69f.).

53 For a more detailed description of the paper, including references to follow up papers and some carefully critical remarks, see (Trautman, 2012). 54 If this holds for some g c, then for any g c (due to Weyl’s rescaling result and the scale invariance of Γ g, ϕ ). ∈ ∈ ( )

25 In his commentary to a recent re-edition of the EPS paper Trautman hinted at the desideratumof a formalproofof the existenceof the affine connection Γ g, ϕ (in our notation) (Trautman, 2012, p. 1584). In a joint paper with Matveev the( two) authors even suggest to give a counter example to EPS’ existence claim (Matveev/Trautman, 2014); but this is due to the quid pro quo of Riemannian metrics and Weyl metrics (see sec. 5.2). EPS gave arguments that assuming some physically plausible axioms, spacetime may be described by a differentiable manifold M. Moreover, acccording to the authors light rays and particle trajectories can be used to establish a metric on M in the sense of Weyl geometry, rather than assuming the latter as a result of rod and clock measurements, chronometric prescriptions, or even only as a structural property like Weyl had done in (Weyl, 1921b). Such a result was important also from the point of view of Einstein gravity; but there remained a gap to the latter, namely how, or whether at all, one can arrive at a (pseudo-) Riemanniang metric from the Weylian one. EPS argued that this gap might be closed by a adding a single additional Riemannian axiom, postulating the vanishing of the scale curvature, dϕ = 0, i.e. the integrability of the Weylian metric (Ehlers et al., 1972, p. 82). Such a postulate would not seem implausible, as Weyl’s interpretation of the scale connection ϕ as electromagnetic potential, the em-dogma, was obsolete anyhow;of course EPS did not adhere to it. But the authors did not exclude the possibility that a scale connection field ϕ of non-vanishing scale curvature might play the role of a “true”, although still unknown, field f = dϕ which would relate “the gravitational field to another universally conserved current” ((Ehlers et al., 1972, p. 83)). The paper of Ehlers, Pirani and Schild triggered a line of investigations in the foundations of general relativity, sometimes called the causal inertial approach (Coleman/Korté), sometimes subsumed under the more general search for a con- structive axiomatics of GRT (Majer/Schmidt, Audretsch, Lämmerzahl, Perlick and others). The debate was opened by (Audretsch, 1983). It was soon continued by a collective paper written by three authors (Audretsch et al., 1984) and had follow up studies, among others (Audretsch/Lämmerzahl, 1988). The authors of the first mentioned paper, Audretsch, Straumann and Gähler, argued that the “gap” between Weylian and Riemannian geometry can “be closed if quantum theory as a theory of matter is made part of the total scheme” (Audretsch, 1983, 2872). By this they referred to an investigation of scalar and spinor fields on a Weylian manifold and the assumption that the flow lines of their WKB-approximation coincide with the geodesics of the underlying metric. In this way these authors could underpin the ad- ditional Riemannian postulate of EPS which was considered as sufficient for closing the gap between Weyl and Riemannian geometry. But the integrability of a Weylian metric is only a necessary condition for locally establishing a Riemannian framework, not a sufficient one. Although the choice of the Riemann gauge is always possible in an integrable Weyl geometry and appears natural from a purely mathematical point of view, the question remains which of the different scale gauges expresses time and other physical quantities directly. If it differs from Riemann gauge, even the conceptually minor difference between the

26 Riemannian structure and an integrable Weylian structure matters for the physics of spacetime. The investigations of the causal inertial approach turned towards a basic con- ceptual analysis from the point of view of foundations of inertial geometry (Coleman/Korté, 1984), some even looking for Desargues type characterization of free fall lines (Pfister, 2004). How a kind of “standard clocks” can be introduced in the Weyl geometric setting without taking refuge to atomic processes, by just using the observation of light rays and inertial trajectories, was studied by (Perlick, 1989, 1987, 1991). Another line of follow up works explored the extension of the foundational argument of the causal inertial approach to quantum physics, where particle trajectories might no longer appear acceptable as a foundational concept.

3.4 Geometrizing quantum mechanical configuration spaces

A completely different perspective on Weyl geometry was taken by Enrico Santam- ato in Naples. In the 1980s he proposed a new approach to quantum mechanics based on studying weak random processes of ensembles of point particles moving in a Weylian modified configuration space (Santamato, 1984a,b, 1985). He compared his approach to that of Madelung-Bohm and to the stochastic program of Feynès- Nelson.55 While the latter dealt with stochastic (Brownian) processes, Santamato’s approach was closer to the view of Madelung and Bohm because it assumed only random initial conditions, with classical trajectories given in Hamilton-Jacobi form (this explains the attribute “weak” above). One can interpret Bohm’s particle trajec- tories as deviating from those expected in Newtonian mechanics by some “quantum force”. Santamato found this an intriguing idea, but he deplored its “mysterious na- ture” which “prevents carrying out a natural and acceptable theory along this line”. He hoped to find a rational explanation for the effects of the “quantum force” by means of a geometry with a modified affine connection of the system’s configuration space. Then the deviation from classical mechanics would appear as the outcome of “fundamental properties of space” (Santamato, 1984a, p. 216), understood in the sense of configuration space. In his first paper paper Santamato started from a configuration space with coor- dinates q1,..., qn endowed with a Euclidean metric. More generally, his approach ( ) allowed for a general positive definite metric gij , and later even a metric of indefinite signature, for dealing with general coordinates of n-particle systems, and perhaps, in a further extension, with spin. The Lagrangian of the system, and the corresponding Hamilton-Jacobi equation, contained the metric, either explicitly or implicitly. This Euclidean, or more generally Riemannian, basic structure was complemented by a Weylian scale connection. Santamato’s central idea was that the modification of the Hamilton-Jacobi equation induced by a properly determined scale connection could be used to express the quantum modification of the classical Hamiltonian, much

55 For E. Nelson’s program to re-derive the quantum dynamics from classical stochastic processes and classical probability see (Bacciagaluppi, 2005).

27 like was done in the Madelung-Bohm approach. Then the quantum aspects of the systems would be geometrized in terms of Weyl geometry, surely a striking and even beautiful idea, if it should work. Santamato thus headed towards a new program of geometrical quantization sui generis. This had nothing to do with the better known geometric quantization pro- gram initiated more than a decade earlier by J.-N. Souriau, B. Kostant and others, which was already well under way in the 1980s (Souriau, 1966; Kostant, 1970; Simms, 1978). In the latter, geometrical methods underlying the canonical quanti- zation were studied. Starting from a symplectic phase space manifold of a classical system, the observables were “pre-quantized” in a Hermitian line bundle, and fi- nally the Hilbert space representation of quantum mechanics was constructed on this basis.56 Santamato’s geometrization was built upon a different structure, Weyl geometry rather than symplectic geometry, and had rather different goals. Like other proposals in the dBMB (de Broglie-Madelung-Bohm) family, San- tamato’s program encountered little positive response. In the following decades he shifted his research to more empirically based studies in nonlinear optics of liquid crystals and quantum optics. Perhaps a critical paper by Carlos Castro Perelman,a younger colleague who knew the program nearly from its beginnings, contributed to what would be an extended period of interruption. Castro discussed “a series of technical points” which seemed important for Santamato’s program from the phys- ical point of view (Castro, 1992, p. 872). This criticism may have contributed to a first interruptionof work on the reearch program.It was taken up again and extended by Santamato, Martini and other researchers in the last decade. After the turn of the century, Santamato came back to foundational questions, working closely together with his colleague Franceso De Martini from the Univer- sity of Rome. Both had cooperatedin their work on quantum optics already for many years. In the 2010s they turned to geometrical quantization in a series of joint publi- cations that continuedthe programSantamato had started three decades earlier. They showed how to deal with spinor fields in this framework, in particular with the Dirac equation (Santamato, 2013), and they discussed the famous Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen (EPR) non-locality question (De Martini/Santamato, 2014a,b). Moreover, they ana- lyzed the helicity of elementary particles and showed that the spin-statistics relation- ship of relativistic quantum mechanics can be derived in their framework without invokingarguments from quantum field theory (De Martini/Santamato, 2015, 2016). In this new series of papers, the authors took Minkowski space as the starting point for their construction of the configuration spaces, which could be extended by inter- nal degrees of freedom. They also enlarged the perspective by making a transition from point dynamical Lagrangians to a dynamically equivalent description in terms

56 See, e.g., (Woodhouse, 1991) or (Hall, 2001, chaps. 22/23). A classical monograph on the symplectic approach to classical mechanics is (Abraham, 1978); but this does not discuss spinning particles. In the 1980s the symplectic approach was already used as a starting platform for (pre- )quantization to which proper quantization procedures could then hook up, see e.g. (Śniarycki, 1980). Souriau was an early advocate of this program. In his book he discussed relativistic particles with spin (Souriau, 1970, §14).

28 of scale invariant field theoretic Lagrangians in two scalar fields. For more details one may consult (Scholz, 2018a) from which this short survey has been adapted. With these papers we have already entered present work on Weyl geometric methods. In the next chapters we turn towards actual researches in greater breadth.

4 Interlude

Let us first lay open the notations and concepts used in the rest of our presentation. They are oriented at the historical literature but deviate from it where it seems advisable.

4.1 Basic concepts, notation and IWG

In the following we use scale weights such that quantities of dimension length L scale with weight 1, w L = 1 (different from Weyl’s practice and, correspondingly, the precedingpartof this( ) article in which the conventionof “quadratic” scale weights = 1 with w L 2 is used). Like usual we assume a non-scaling vacuum velocity of light c (and) a non-scaling Planck constant ~; time T, mass M, and energy E scale then respectively by w T = 1, w M = w E = 1.57 These weights will be called Weyl weights; they are( the) negatives( of) the( mass/energy) − weights used by elementary particle physicists. The simplest way to define a Weylian metric on a differentiable manifold M is by specifying an equivalence class g = g, ϕ , consisting of a pseudo-Riemannian µ ν [( )] metric g (locally g = gµν dx dx ),the Riemannian component of the Weylian metric, ν and a real-valued differential 1-form ϕ (locally ϕ = ϕν dx ) representing the scale connection. Equivalence g, ϕ g˜, ϕ is defined by the gauge transformation ( )∼( ) e dΩ g˜ = Ω2g, ϕ = ϕ d log Ω = ϕ , (12) − − Ω with a strictly positive re-scalinge function Ω on M.58 Choosing a representative g, ϕ g means to gauge the metric. ( If) the ∈ scale connection is closed in some gauge g, ϕ , dϕ = 0, it is so in any gauge and is locally (i.e., in simply connected regions)( exa)ct with potential, say ω, such that ϕ = dω. Weyl’s length transfer can then be integrated − − ϕ γ ω Ω = γ ( Û) = e∫ e− 57 If F. Hehl’s suspicion that the velocity of light may vary with the gravitational potential turns out to be right (if one considers more precise solutions of the Maxwell equation in GR than assumed in the optical limit), a specification like, e.g., a constraint to conformally flat Riemannian metric, has to be included in the definition of c. 58 Note the difference to eq. (2), due to the different conventions for scaling weights.

29 independently of the path γ. One therefore speaks of an integrable Weyl geometry (IWG). Locally a gauge of the form g˜, 0 with ( ) 2 ϕ γ 2ω g = γ ( Û) = g ϕ = ϕ + ω = ˜ e ∫ e− and ˜ d 0 (13) can be chosen, the Riemann gauge of an IWG. Because of the remaining freedom of choosing different scale gauges this does not mean, however, a structural reduction to Riemannian geometry. That may be important for physical applications, if there are reasons to assume or to explore the possibility that measuring instruments (“clocks”) don’t adapt to the Riemann gauge. The Jordan frame of Brans-Dicke theory, e.g., corresponds to Riemann gauge if the latter is being formulated in terms of IWG. The still ongoing debate on the question which frame, respectively gauge, expresses measured quantities best in BD theory shows that an a priori preference for the Riemann gauge may be a shortcut shadowing a physically important question. A more fundamental difference to Riemannian geometry arises, if there is an obstruction f = dϕ , 0. f is the curvature of the scale connection, shorter the scale curvature (not to be confused with the scalar curvature R of the affine connection). Physically it expresses the field strength of the scale connection, often called the Weyl field of the structure. The uniquely defined affine connection compatible with g, ϕ will often be written as Γ, if context makes clear what is meant. In more[( complicated)] contexts we write more explicitly Γ = Γ g, ϕ , although the second expression might suggest a scale gauge dependence of Γ(, which) is not the case. Γ decomposes into gauge dependent contributions like in (3), Γ g, ϕ = Γ = Γ g + Γ ϕ with Γ g the Levi-Civita connection of g and ( ) ( ) ( ) ( )

µ µ µ µ Γ ϕ = δ ϕλ + δ ϕν gνλ ϕ , (14) νλ( ) ν λ − 1 here without the factor 2 in comparison to (3) because of the modified weight convention. Γ itself is gauge invariant. The covariant derivative and the curvature tensors Riem, Ric will usually de- note the ones due to the Weyl∇ geometric affine connection Γ. They are scale invari- ant. In any gauge they decompose into a gauge dependent Riemannian component, Riem g , Ric g , and anotheroneexpressingthecontributionof thescale connection Riem (ϕ), Ric (ϕ), etc.59 The scalar curvature scales with weight w R = 2. The( scaling) ( ) behavior of (scalar, vector, tensor, spinor) fields(X) on− a Weylian manifold M, g, ϕ has to be specified by a corresponding scale weight w X according( to invariance[( )] principles of the Lagrangian or, from a more empirical point( ) of view, according to its physical dimension. From a mathematical point of view

59 Compare fn. 48. For the scale connection component Riem ϕ of the Weyl geometric Riemann µ = µ µ + α ( µ) α µ curvature one finds R ϕ νλκ g λ Γνκ g κ Γνλ Γνκ Γαλ ΓνλΓακ (Yuan, 2013, eq. (9)). There is also a gauge( invariant) decomposition∇( ) − ∇( of Riem) into what Weyl− called directional curvature and length curvature, which must not be confused with the gauge dependent decomposition just mentioned. The length curvature F as part of the Riemann tensor is closely related to the scale = µ = µ connection 2-form f dϕ; its components are Fνκλ δν fκλ. As F and f can easily be translated into one another; they are often identified in loose speech.−

30 w X specifies the representation type of the scale group for the adjoint bundle (to the( scale) bundle) in which X lives. The full covariant derivative of fields X in the sense of the Weyl geometric structure in a gauge g, ϕ has to take into account the scale connection in addition to the Levi-Civita of(g. It) will be called scale covariant derivative D (Dirac’s “co- covariant derivative, p. 22) and is given by

DX = g X + w X X . (15) ∇( ) ( )⊗ ν ν In coordinates this is for a vector field ξ of weight w, e.g., Dµξ = µ + wϕµ ξ . Weyl understood the compatibility of a Weylian metric represented(∇ by g, ϕ with) an affine connection Γ in the sense that parallel transport by Γ has to “respect( ) the length transfer”. This condition can be stated more formally as vanishing of the scale covariant derivative of g:

Dg = 0 Γ g = 2ϕ g (16) ⇐⇒ ∇( ) − ⊗

The term Q with Qλµν := 2ϕλgµν on the r.h.s. of the equation is a necessary conceptual feature for ensuring− the metric compatibility of the affine connection in the sense of Weyl geometry. From the viewpoint of Riemannian geometry, in contrast, it appears as a deviation from the norm, and has been termed “non-metricity” by Schouten, in this special form containing g as “semi-metricity”. Using the scale covariant derivative the Weyl geometric affine connection can be written in a form close to the one for the Levi-Civita connection (Jiménez/Koivisto, 2014, eq. (46)):

λ 1 λα Γ g, ϕ = g Dµgνα + Dν gαµ Dαgµν (17) ( )µν 2 ( − ) Thecondition(16)issometimesusedasanentrypointfordefining Weyl structures (pseudo-Riemannian, Hermitian, quaternionic etc.).

Definition: A (pseudo-Riemannian) Weyl structure is given by a triple M, c, of a dif- ferentiable manifold M, a pseudo-Riemannian conformal structure c = (g and∇) a covariant derivative , such that for all g c there is a differential 1-form ϕ for which[ ] g+2ϕ g = 0. ∇ ∈ ∇ ⊗ Gauge transformations of type (12) for changes of the representative of c are a consequence of this definition (Ornea, 2001). Weyl introduced scale invariant geodesics by the usual condition u u = 0 for the covariant derivative = g, ϕ of the tangent field u = γ τ of a curve∇ γ τ . In coordinates and with Γ =∇ Γ g∇(, ϕ this) is Û( ) ( ) ( ) γλ + Γλ γµγν = 0 . (18) Ü µν Û Û Different to Riemannian geometry, scale invariant geodesics are (usually) not parametrized by curve length. This can be changed by introducing gauge dependent re-parametrizations of γ, that is a class of curves with the same trace as Weyl’s scale invariant geodesics such that the tangent fields scale with weight w γ = 1. This leads to introducing scale covariant geodesics of weight w γ = 1,(Û characterised) − (Û) −

31 by the condition Dγγ = γ γ ϕ γ γ = 0, or in coordinates Û Û ∇ Û Û − (Û)Û λ λ µ ν ν λ γ + Γ γ γ ϕν γ γ = 0 . (19) Ü µν Û Û − Û Û ν λ The difference between the solutions of (18) and (19) (in coordinates ϕν γ γ ) is proportional to γ. It thus does not change the direction of the curve, butÛ onlyÛ its Û parametrization. This results in γ g γ, γ = 0 for a scale covariant geodesic, and a constant length function l = g γ,∇γÛ ( like(Û Û in)) Riemannian geometry.60 The length function l is not(Û onlyÛ) constantalong a scale covariantgeodesicbut also scale invariant, because of w l = w g γ, γ = 2 1 1 = 0. For l = 1 the integrated length of a geodesic (with regard( ) to( the(Û RiemannianÛ)) − −g component of a gauge g, ϕ ) can be read off from the parametrization. It is, of course, scale dependent. ( ) Similarly the (squared) Riemannian length of any differentiable curve l2 γ = R( ) g γ τ , γ τ dτ is a scale dependent quantity. If one corrects the integrand by the ( (Û ) (Û )) Weylian∫ length transfer function, one finds that the integral

2 2 ϕ γ l γ = e ( Û)g γ τ , γ τ dτ (20) W ( ) ¹ ∫ ( (Û ) (Û )) leads to a scale invariant curve length lW (up to a constant factor depending on the Ω τ0 value of the rescaling function Ω at the initial point of the curve e ( )). This holds for any ϕ. It can be considered as the Weylian length of the curve. For an integrable Weyl geometry this boils down to measuring curve lengths in Riemann gauge (13).

4.2 Weyl geometric gravity, in particular in IWG

The following remarks refer to the gravitational sector only. Theories building on such an approachwill add matter fields and their couplingsto the gravitational sector (some special case follow in the next sections). Scalar fields coupling to the Hilbert term will be treated here as part of the gravitational sector, although in certain respects, in particular their energy-momentum, they also behave like matter fields. A matter-like contribution to the energy-momentum results from their kinetic term which is not considered in this section, but see sec. 5.4. Weyl geometric gravity is a scale in/co-variant theory. Its Lagrangians L are scale covariant functions of weight w L = n with a scale invariant Lagrange density L = L det g . In the following we( ) assume− n = 4. Typical gravitational Lagrangians | | are thenp of the form

2 µν 4 2 2 2 Lgrav = α1φ R + α2 fµν f + α3φ + β1 R + β2 Ric + β2 Riem + ..., (21) where φ is a scale covariant real scalar field of weight w φ = 1, Riem, Ric, and R denote the Weyl geometric Riemann, Ricci and scalar curvatu( ) res,− f = dϕ is the field

60 For the Riemannian case see, e.g., (Kühnel, 1999, p. 92).

32 2 = µ νκλ 2 = µν strength of the scale connection (Weyl field), Riem R νκλ Rµ , Ric Rµν R , and the dots indicate other quadratic terms in Weyl geometric cuvature of weight 4 including, if one wants, the (conformal) Weyl tensor of the Riemannian component− in any gauge. Weyl never considered the α1 and β2 terms (i.e., for him always α1 = β2 = 0), moreover he considered β1 = 0 in (Weyl, 1918a), respectively β3 = 0 in (Weyl, 1923b); Dirac assumed all βi = 0 i = 1, 2, 3 etc. There are indications that the quadratic curvature terms of the classical( Lagrang) ian and the Weyl field term may be of importance in strong gravity regimes and also for the quantization of gravity (sec. 5.3, 5.4). With β1 = β3 = 1, β2 = 4 the explicitly given quadratic curvature terms of (21) in L reduce to the scalar density− κ of the Gauss-Bonnet theorem as generalized by Chern: κ = R2 4Ric2 + Riem2 det g (22) ( − ) | | p For orientable compact differentiable manifolds in dimension n = 4 the theorem tells us that 32π χ M = κ g dx , ( ) ¹M ( ) with χ M the Euler-characteristic of M and g any Riemannian metric g on M. Interestingly( ) recent authors realized that Weyl geometric field theories for which the Riemannian component of the quadratic curvature Lagrange densities reduce to the topologically preferred Gauss-Bonnet form κdx behave particularly well with regard to unitarity (Tanhayi et al., 2012) and stability (Jiménez/Koivisto, 2014). Scale covariant theories with α1 , 0 and a nowhere vanishing gravitational scalar field have a scale gauge in which the scalar field is constant, φ  φ0. Here the following convention is used:

 denotes equalities which only hold is specific scale gauges.

The gauge with φ  φ0 will be called the scalar field gauge with regard to φ (in short φ-gauge). If the coefficient of the modified Hilbert term assumes the value, 2  1 1 2 α1φ 16πG − 2 Ep (EP the reduced Planck energy), it specifies the Einstein gauge. Theories( ) with∼ a distinguished scalar field φ allow to define:

With regard to φ scale invariant observable quantities of a scale covariant field X with weight w = w X are given by forming the proportion with φ w , i.e, by Xˇ = φw X. ( ) − This boils down to determining the field values in φ-gauge (up to the constant w factor φo ). Probably that was the reason for Utiyama to consider φ as a “measuring field” (see p. 21). These theoretical considerations may get underpinned physically, if reasons turn up which allow to conclude that the result of measuring processes (e.g., atomic clocks) are displayed in the scalar field gauge of φ. The scaling of the Higgs field Φ indicates in this direction, if it underlies a common biquadratic potential with the gravitational field φ (sec. 5.3). If one spells out the modified Hilbert term of (21) in terms of the Riemannian and the scale connection contributions to R,

ν ν R = R g + R ϕ with R ϕ = n 1 n 2 ϕν ϕ 2 n 1 g ν ϕ (23) ( ) ( ) ( ) −( − )( − ) − ( − )∇( )

33 1 2 ν = a mass term 2 mϕ ϕν ϕ for the Weyl field turns up, which in dimension n 4 would 2 = 2 indicate the impressive value mϕ 6 EP. Evenif oneallows forquantumcorrections, or includes other terms in an approach of this type, one arrives at a mass far beyond experimental access (e.g. at the LHC). Bosonic couplings of the Weyl field thus occur at extremely small distances (close to the Planck length); their effects integrate out at longer distances, comparable to the invisibility of the weak interaction at microscopic scales. For investigations in low energy regions, i.e., at laboratoryor astronomical scales, Weyl geometric gravity can thus be effectively modelled in termsofscaleconnections with vanishing curvature, dϕ = 0, i.e. in the frameworkof integrable Weyl geometry. In a Lagrangian approach the reduction to the effective theory can be expressed by µν introducing Lagrange multiplier terms λµν f (like in (31)). In the following we therefore introduce a simplified version of Weyl geometric gravity in the framework of IWG by the external constraint of a vanishing scale curvature, dϕ = 0. Even then the scalar field φ contains an additional degree of freedom in comparison with σ Einstein gravity. In the Riemann gauge it can be expressed as φ  φ0e− , where  Rg Rg denotes equality in the Riemann gauge; similarly  for the Einstein gauge. Eg The simplified version of Weyl geometric gravity is a scalar-tensor theory in which the new scalar degree of freedom is expressed partially by the scalar field and partially by the (integrable) scale connection. This can be seen as follows: The data in an arbitrary scale gauge arise from Riemann gauge by (length-) rescaling with a real valued function Ω = eω :

2ω σ+ω g  e g, ϕν  ∂νω ϕ  dω , φ  φ0 e−( ) (24) − ( − ) The information of the new dynamical degree of freedom is now no longer encoded by the scalar field alone, but is being distributed among the scalar field and the scale connection, i.e., encoded by the pair φ, ϕ . In the Einstein gauge gˆ, ϕ,ˆ φˆ , specified ( ) ( ) by φˆ  φ0, the respective values are

2σ gˆ  e− g ϕˆν  ∂νσ φˆ  φ0 (constant) . (25) Eg Eg Eg

The dynamical information of the new degree of freedom is here completely con- tained in the integrable scale connection with integral σ, while the scalar field has become a constant. This has interesting dynamical consequences for inertial paths, if they follow Weyl geometric geodesics (section 5.4). At least test bodies do so. This is the case, because the doubly covariant energy momentum tensor Tµν scales with weight 2 (also in the non-integrable case).61 The “conservation” condition of GR translates,− at least in IWG, to a vanishing scale covariant divergence

61 m = 2 δLm = ∂ Lm For the Hilbert energy tensor Tµν( ) µν 2 µν Lm gµν this results from the − √ g δg − ∂g − | |   scaling weights w Lm = 4 and of g (similarly for the canonical energy tensor). It agrees with ( ) − 0 the “phenomenological” weight read off from the physical dimension of the energy density T 0; in dimension 4 w T 0 = w E L 3 = 4. ( 0 ) ([ − ]) −

34 µ DµT ν = 0 . (26) That allowsto generalize the classical Geroch-Jang theorem establishing the geodesic principle in Einstein gravity for test bodies (Geroch/Jang, 1975) without great effort to the framework of integrable Weyl geometry (Scholz, 2019, app. 5.3). The case of extended bodies is more complicated and needs further clarification.62 Let us be content with these short remarks. In the next section some topics in the foundations of gravity and Weyl geometric researches in other subfields of physics will be reviewed.

5 Interest today

After the reinterpretationof the original gauge idea as a phase factor in quantum me- chanics in the second half of the 1920s Weyl’s scale geometry (purely infinitesimal geometry) of 1918 lay dormant for nearly half a century, enhanced by Weyl’s own clear disassociation from this idea in the 1940s. Surprisingly, it lived up again reju- venated in the early 1970s, enriched by new concepts and triggered by new interests in conformal transformations in gravity theory, cosmology, quantum physics, and field theory. The following section discusses selected topics in which Weyl geometric methods enter crucially into ongoing present research. Of course this selection is quite subjective; it is necessarily biased by my own interests and delimited by the restrictions in perspective and knowledge of the author.

5.1 Philosophical reflections on gravity

Extending the Riemannian framework for gravity theories may help to clarify con- ceptual questions. This is, of course, a truism and holds not only for the Weyl geometric generalization but also, e.g., for Cartan geometry. Her we deal with the first option. A classical subject for this type of questions is the discussion of the problem which is the “physical frame” in Brans-Dicke theory. Brans-Dicke theory presupposes the framework of Riemannian geometry and uses conformal transformations not only for the metric but also for the scalar field, while keeping the affine connection arising as a solution of eq. (7) fixed.63 In a technical sense it works in the framework of an integrable Weyl structure M, c, , where the Jordanframecorrespondsto the Riemanngauge ofthe Weylian metric.( For∇) most practitioners this goes unnoticed. Exceptions are (Quiros et al., 2013b) and the authors of the Brazilian group of Weyl geometric gravity, (Almeida et al., 2014a,b;

62 The detailed study in (Ohanian, 2010) discusses, among others, the problem for the geodesic principle of extended bodies in BD theory. This cannot be translated 1 : 1 to the IWG case. 63 For modern presentations of BD theory see, e.g. (Fujii/Maeda, 2003); the transformation of the Levi-Civita geodesics of the Jordan frame to other frames are discussed in (ibid, sec. 3.4).

35 Romero, 2011).64 This theory is nearly a Weyl geometricscalar tensor theory arising from (21) with α2 = βi = 0, i = 1, 2, 3 by adding a quadratic scale covariant kinetic term of the scalar field α ν L∂φ2 = Dν φ D φ, (27) − 2 even though the L∂φ2 is usually not written explicitly in a scale covariant form  α ν but given in the Jordan frame in the form L∂φ2 2 ∂ν φ∂ φ. Additional terms arise in other frames from the respective conformal transfo− rmations. I consider such an approach as nearly Weyl geometric gravity, because often a matter term Lm is added, which breaks the scale invariance of the Lagrange density. That raises the question in which scale gauge (frame) the matter Lagrangian couples minimally to the Riemannian component of the metric. This is usually called the physical metric (or frame) (Fujii/Maeda, 2003, p. 227f.) and one has to decide in which relation the physical metric/frame/gauge stands to the Riemann/Jordan frame and the Einstein frame. In a Weyl geometric scalar tensor theory as conceived here, one better writes the matter Lagrangian in a scale covariant form (w Lm = 4). This leads to scale invariant dynamical equations (containing scale covariant( ) terms).− The physical breaking of the scale symmetry is a separate question and can be discussed at a later stage of the theory development. It is related to fixing the basic parameters of the measuring processes.65 Then one arrives at the scale gauge in which observational values are expressed directly. Let us assume, for the moment, that this is, e.g., the Einstein gauge.66 This is then also the frame (or gauge) in which the Lagrangian matter terms are expressed most directly in the form known from non-scale invariant formulations. Insofar this is the “physical gauge”. The Riemann gaugehas, ontheotherhand,the pleasantfeaturethatthe Weyl geodesicgeodesicsare identical to the Levi-Civita ones of the gauge. From a more conservative viewpoint one might say that the free fall trajectories of BD gravity are those of Riemann gauge. But free fall and matter Lagrangian are both important physical features of a theory of gravity. Which one should we then consider as “physical”? The two frames express different aspects of physical reality in a mathematically most direct way. In this sense both can be considered as “physical”; it does not matter which way, we only need to be clear what is meant. C. Romero, M. Pucheu and other authors of the Brazilian group mentioned above (sec. 3.2) use the framework of Weyl geometric gravity to discuss different inter-theory relations (Romero et al., 2012b; Romero, 2012a). In the first paper they discuss how Einstein gravity can be expressed in this wider framework by a scale-

64 Note, however, that Romero et al. have a peculiar view of BD theory, different from the usual one and influenced by their paradigm called WIST (Weyl integrable spacetime). This is a theory of gravity placed in an integrable Weyl geometric framework, but with a broken scale symmetry and Levi-Civita geodesics of the distinguished frame. In their view also in BD the free fall trajectories are determined by the Levi-Civita geodesics of a distinguished frame (which can be the Einstein frame) (Romero et al., 2012b, sec. 6). This modified version of BD theory is equivalent to WIST (Romero et al., 2012b, sec. 8). 65 Cf. (Quiros et al., 2013b) and (Scholz, 2017). 66 For an argument in favour of the Einstein gauge (under certain assumptions) see section 5.3, observation ( ). ∗

36 covariantization of dimensional quantities. In particular the gravitational constant is promoted to a scalar field (proportional to φ2 in our notation), which also couples to 4 the matter term (which then becomes φ Lm ). Their version of Weyl geometric scalar tensor theory (WIST) is shown to be equivalent to their view of BD theory.67 Finally they discuss the relationship between original Nordström’s scalar theory of gravity to the Einstein-Fokker version from the point of view of conformal transformations of a flat Lorentzian manifolds (Romero, 2012a). This has been taken up in a recent broader philosophicaldiscussion of the usefulness of a Weyl geometricpoint of view for this type of theory relation by P. Duerr (2019).

5.2 Matveev/Trautman on EPS

A critical point of the EPS approach, the question whether EPS compatibilty of a projective and a conformal structure implies Weyl compatibility, has recently been scrutinized by Matveev/Trautman (2014). Weyl presupposed the compatibility of a given pair of conformal and projective structures by considering only pairs which arise from a (presupposed) Weylian metric. In the EPS approach the compatibil- ity question has to be posed in greater generality; it was formulated in terms of the geometrical criterion of EPS-compatibility stated above (p. 25). Clearly Weyl compatibility implies EPS-compatibility. The main result of EPS claims the inverse. A counter-example to the equivalence of the two compatibility criteria would falsify the proof argumentationfor the main result of EPS. Referring to Weyl and the EPS paper, Matveev and Trautman announce “a theorem giving the necessary and sufficient conditions for compatibility of conformal and projective structures” and proudly claim that their result (Matveev/Trautman, 2014, p. 822) “completes a line of research initiated by Weyl and continued by physicists” (ibid. p. 824). They do so by giving a simple example of a non-integrable Weyl structure which they consider as a counterexample to the EPS result (ibid., sec. 3.). Of course this is wrong. The erroneous claim of having invalidated the main result of EPS results from a simple quid pro quo. The authors of (Matveev/Trautman, 2014) use a compatibility criterion of the structures p and c relying on the framework of Riemannian geometry and thus different from Weyl and from EPS: Definition. The conformal and projective structures c and p are said to be compatible if there is g c such that Γ g p. (Matveev/Trautman, 2014, p. 823, notation slightly adapted) ∈ ( ) ∈ This definition restricts the underlying metrical structure to the Riemannian case. I therefore call it the Riemann compatibility of a conformal and a projective structure. Of course Riemann compatibility is a much stronger criterion than Weyl compat- ibility (p. 25); no great wonder that Matveev/Trautman can give “counter examples” of pairs p, c for which the EPS compatibility holds, but not their own one. A veritable( ) achievement of the paper lies, on the other hand, in formulating an analytical criterion for the compatibility of two structures p and c (p. 823, ibid.),

67 See fn. 64.

37 even though it is established for Riemann compatibility only (Matveev/Trautman, 2014, equs. (7), (8)). It can easily be generalized (i.e. weakened) to the case of Weyl compatibility in the following way. For given p and c first choose an affine connection Γ p and a Riemannian metric g c, the latter with Levi-Civita connection Γ g . Any∈ Weylian metric subordinate to∈ the conformal structure c can be expressed( in) a scale gauge with Riemannian component g, i.e. in a gauge of the form g, ϕ with some real differential form ϕ. Denote its (Weylian) affine connection by (Γ g,) ϕ . Using the Thomas symbol Π Γ of an affine( connection) Γ ( ) 1 1 Πi Γ = Γi δi Γl δi Γl jk ( ) jk − n + 1 j lk − n + 1 k lj a necessary and sufficient condition for the projective equivalence of two affine connections Γ and Γ′ is the equality of their Thomas symbols, respectively the vanishing of the Thomas symbol for the difference:

Π Γ Π Γ′ = Π Γ Γ′ = 0 ( )− ( ) ( − ) For checking the Weyl compatibility of p and c one has to see, whether Γ g, ϕ and Γ are projectively equivalent, i.e. whether or not the Thomas symbol of their( difference) vanishes. Calculating first the Thomas symbol T for the difference of the Levi-Civita connection of g and of Γ,

T g, Γ := Π Γ g Γ , (28) ( ) ( ( )− ) the searched for difference Π Γ g, ϕ Γ can be expressed by T g, Γ and ϕ; it will be denoted by T g, ϕ, Γ = Π(Γ(g, ϕ)− Γ). In components it is: ( ) ( ) ( ( )− )

e i i 1 i i i T g, ϕ, Γ = T g, Γ + δ ϕk + δ ϕj gjk ϕ (29) ( )jk ( )jk n + 1( j k )− e Vanishing ofT˜ isnecessary and sufficientfor theprojectiveequivalenceof Γ g, ϕ and Γ, and thus the Weyl compatibility of the given projective and conformalstructures.( ) 68 Let us call T˜ the generalized Matveev symbol associated to a projective structure p and a Weylian metric g, ϕ subordinate to the conformal structure c. We thus get the result: [( )]

A projective structure p and a conformal structure c = g are Weyl compatible, if and only if there is a real differential form ϕ (not necessarily closed)[ ] such that for some (and thus for any) Γ p the generalized Matveev symbol (29) vanishes, T g, ϕ, Γ = 0. ∈ ( ) This argumentation follows step by step the one ine Matveev/Trautman (2014) al- though, as already said, this paper discusses the restricted case of Riemann compati- bility and dϕ = 0 only. It leads to a formal criterion for testing Weyl compatibility of

68 This is analogous to the left hand side of (Matveev/Trautman, 2014, eq. (7))); Matveev’s second criterion, eq. (6), is the integrability condition for the scale connection. It does not play a role here.

38 a projective and a conformal structure. A mathematical proof (or refutation) of the main result of EPS – and with it of the equivalence between Weyl compatibility and EPS-compatibility – remains a desideratum. Trautman’s remark in his commentary to the recent re-edition of the EPS paper has not lost its actuality:

I think it is clear that the subject requires and deserves further work. (Trautman, 2012, p. 1585).

5.3 How does the standard model relate to gravity?

Two mutually related aspects of the standard model of elementary particle physics (SM) out for considering it from a Weyl geometric perspective if one wants to know more about a possible link of the SM to gravity: the nearly scale covariance of the SM Lagrangian (of weight -4) in a Minkowskian background with only the Higgsmassterm breakingthescalesymmetry,andtheroleofthe Higgsscalar field Φ (weight w Φ = 1) itself. Since the first decade of the SM this has motivated authors to adapt the( ) SM− Lagrangian to a Weyl geometric framework and to enhance it by a scale invariant gravity sector. In the first three decades that often happened without mostauthorsknowingaboutsimilar attemptsundertakenbyother colleagues. Several of them brought forward idea that the (norm of the) initially still hypothetical Higgs field might play the role of a gravitional scalar field which couples to the generalized Hilbert term of (21) (Smolin, 1979; Cheng, 1988; Drechsler, 1999a; Drechsler/Tann, 1999b).69 With the role of the Higgs field being established and elevated to the status of an object of empirical research, all the more after the empirical confirmation of its physical reality in 2013, the attention has shifted to models with (at least) two scalar fields, a gravitational scalar field φ coupling to the Hilbert term and the Higgs field Φ as part of the matter sector, both scaling with the Weyl weight 1 respectively the mass/energy weight +1 used by the elementary particle physicists.− This allows to consider models in which the Higgs field couples indirectly to the gravitational sector through a common biquadratic potential term with the gravitational scalar 2 field (30) and/or directly (non-minimally) by an additional term α1′ Φ R added to the gravitational Lagrangian (21). These approaches are not mutually| exclusive| and may turn out crucial for establishing a link between the SM and gravity. Among the more recent studies some explore the conceptual and formal frame- work for importing the SM into a Weyl geometric scalar tensor theoryof gravitywith a modified Hilbert term in the classical Lagrangian (without quadratic gravitational terms and without considering quantization) (Nishino/Rajpoot, 2004, 2007, 2009; Scholz, 2011, 2017; Quiros, 2013a, 2014; Cesare et al., 2017). Interesting features arise already on this level if one assumes a common biquadratic potential for the gravitational scalar field and the Higgs field:

69 Cf. (Scholz, 2018a, sec. 11.5).

39 2 λ1 2 µ 2 λ 4 V Φ,φ = Φ φ + φ , λ, λ1 > 0, (30) ( ) 4 | | − λ1  4 2 λ1 4 µ 2 2 λ′ 4 µ = Φ Φ φ + φ λ′ = λ + , 4 | | − 2 | | 4 λ1

V = V Φ,φ g L − ( ) | | p Such a potential is considered in (Shaposhnikov/Zenhäusern,2009a; Shaposhnikov/Zenhaäusern, 2009b) for studying global scale symmetry in the SM on Minkowski space and has been imported to conformaltheoriesof gravityin (Bars et al., 2014).70 If the dynam- ical terms do not disturb the rest state of the potential minimum too strongly, there is a common minimum of the potential with ∂ Φ V,∂φV = 0 also in the locally scale symmetric framework. This “binds” the fields( | | together) in the sense of keeping them proportional, φ Φ , whichever scale gauge is considered. In particular the gauge in which the gravitational∼ | | scalar field is constant, Einstein gauge, is the same in which the norm of the Higgs field, i.e. its expectation value, is scaled to a constant. I propose to call it the Higgs gauge. Then the Higgs gauge and the Einstein gauge are identical in the rest state of the scalar fields, and the Lagrangian mass expressions of the form µ Φ 2 acquire 2 2 2 | | the constant value m = µ Φo = µev as usual in the electro-weak theory (v 246 GeV the reference energy| of| the electroweak interaction). In the literature this≈ is sometimes considered as a "generation" of mass (as though the mass terms did not exist already before) and the choice of Higgs gauge as a “breaking” of the scale symmetry (as though the scale symmetry had to be given up in the light of the physically preferred choice of the scale gauge). The latter perspective is unhappy because it obscures an important point for 2 roundingoff the Weyl geometricframework.As the mass term of the electron µe Φ scales with the norm of Higgs field Φ like the masses of all elementary particles,| | | | 2 2 2 it becomes constant with the latter, say m = µe Φo = µev . In accordance with e | | this the Rydberg constant Ry, important for the determination of atomic frequencies, scales (classically) with me, this allows to infer that time measurements which rely on atomic frequencies can be read off in the Higgs gauge = Einstein gauge.71 This leads to the observation: ( ) If Weyl geometric gravity with a gravitational scalar field φ is linked to the SM via a∗ biquadratic potential of φ and the Higgs field Φ, we expect that the Einstein gauge of the gravitational scalar field is identical to the Higgs gauge and corresponds to measurement units according to those of the new SI conventions.72 This can be interpreted as an adaptation

70 For the introduction to a Weyl geometric framework see (Cesare et al., 2017; Scholz, 2017). 4 α2 71 = e me = f Ry 2~ 2 me c, where e denotes the charge of the electron, αf the fine structure constant. 2 The energy levels En in the Balmer series of the hydrogen atom are given by En = Ry n− ; the other atomic frequencies are influenced by the Rydberg constant similarly, although in a more complicated way. With field quantization αf becomes dependent on the energy scale under consideration; the Higgs gauge as discussed here is therefore clearly a feature of the classical theory emerging from the quantum level at long ranges. 72 For the new SI conventions see footnote 35; the connecting link to Weyl geometric gravity is discusssed in (Scholz, 2017, sec. 5).

40 of atomic clocks to the local field constellation of the pair Φ, φ , the Higgs field and the gravitational scalar field. ( )

From a general point of view this is close to Weyl’s hypothesisof an adaptation of clocks to the local constellation of the gravitational field. But because of the central role of the Higgs field in the adaptation to Φ,φ the latter gains a more solid physical foundation than Weyl’s rather speculative( proposal) relating to the scalar curvature of spacetime (sec. 2.1). Note also that a biquadratic potential (30) gives the Higgs field a distinguished relation among the matter fields to the gravitational sector. Th other way round, the gravitational scalar field φ enters the so-called Higgs portal in a particularly simple form. Present day physicists want to understand the establishment of the Higgs gauge and/or Einstein gauge as a breaking of symmetry. This is what, e.g., the authors of (Nishino/Rajpoot, 2004) do. They consider the scalar field φ acquiring a constant values as a physical process of symmetry breaking, related to a Goldston boson which gives mass to the Weyl field and to the Higgs field. This is assumed to happen at an extremely high energy level far beyond the electroweak scale. Other authors go a step further and discuss a possible dynamical underpinning by a mechanism of a spontaneous breaking of scale symmetry in close analogy to the Coleman/Weinberg mechanism proposed in the early 1970s for the breaking of the U 1 symmetry in electroweak theory (Ohanian, 2016; Dengiz/Tekin, 2011; Tanhayi( et) al., 2012; Ghilencea, 2019). These studies work with a quantization of at least the scalar field and the Weyl field (the scale connection). Dengiz/Tekin for example start from a scale invariant Lagrangian including quadratic curvature terms in the gravitational sector. Applying a perturbative quantization scheme for the gravitational scalar field they find a Cole- man/Weinberg effect, after a “tedious renormalization and regularization procedure” at the two loop-level (Dengiz/Tekin, 2011, p. 4). Although there remains the caveat that at the minimum of the quantum corrected potential the perturbative calculation looses validity, they conclude that “the Weyl symmetry of the classical Lagrangian will not survive quantization” (ibid. p. 5). Ohanian and Ghilencea argue inversely. Ohanian assumes a scale invariant Lagrangian close to the Planck scale without the quadratic curvature terms, while Ghilencea uses a combined linear (modified Hilbert term) and quadratic gravitational Lagrangian with a prominent contribution of Weyl’s conformal curvature, which does not satisfy the Gauss-Bonnet constraint (22). Both authors find in their respective approaches that a Coleman-Weinberg-like consideration for the scalar field leads to breaking of scale symmetry for the low energy classical Lagrangian. This reduces the geometry to a Riemannian framework and the gravity to Einstein’s theory.73 In a follow up paper to (Dengiz/Tekin, 2011) Tahanyi and the authors of the first paper come to a different conclusion. They undertake a more fundamental study of quantum properties of the Weyl geometrically extended gravitational sector including quadratic expressions in the curvature and derive the full gravitational particle spectrum of the theory for an (Anti-) de-Sitter and a Minkowski background.

73 (Ohanian, 2016, p. 10f.), (Ghilencea, 2019, p. 7)

41 Theyfind the Gauss-Bonnetrelation (22) as a necessaryconstraint for unitarityof the quantized field theory with gravitational Lagrangian (21) and arrive at the conclusion:

. . . , the only unitary theory, beyond three dimensions, among the Weyl-invariant quadratic theories is the Weyl-invariant Einstein-Gauss-Bonnet model [our Lagrangian (21) con- strained by (22), ES] which propagates a massless spin-2 particle as well as massive spin-1 and massless spin-0 particles (Tanhayi et al., 2012, p. 8)

This is a highly interesting result. The mentioned particles are, of course, the graviton, the boson of the Weyl field (scale connection), and the boson of the gravitational scalar field. In this model the Weyl boson is extremely heavy as usual, and the Weyl field has only short range effects; on larger scales it can be represented classically by an integrable scale connection. The scalar field,onthe otherhand(anddifferentfrom Ohanian’s model), can support long range gravitational interactions in addition to the ones mediated by the graviton. For the classical theory this boils down to a Lagrangian constraint µν Lf = λµν f , (31) with Lagrangian multiplier functions λµν enforcing α2 = 0 in (21). In the light of Tanhanyi et al.’s derivation the classical Einstein gravity limit of Ohanian and Ghilenceaseems to resultfromthespecial choicesof their gravitational Lagrangians, both violating the Gauss-Bonnet constraint. The question still remains, whether for a Weyl symmetric bare Lagrangian – a kind of classical template for a quantum field theory under construction – the local scale symmetry is broken under quantization. Often the so-called trace anomaly is considered as an indicator that this is in fact the case. This means that the energy- momentum tensor of (pseudo-)classical quantum matter fields, represented by scalar fields or Dirac spinors, has a vanishing trace, whereas the expectation value of the quantized trace no longer vanishes. The trace anomaly has puzzled theoretical physicists for a long time, and is often interpreted as implying the breaking of scale invariance at the quantum level. The authors of (Codello et al., 2013) come to a different conclusion. The trace anomaly is, of course, present also in their approach, but it no longer signifies break- ing of the local scale invariance. The reason lies in a cancellation of the trace terms of the quantized fields by corresponding counter-terms that arise from a complex gravitational scalar field which they call a “dilaton”. In order to achieve this the au- thors use a coherent scale-covariantization of all terms by substituting dimensional constants with the appropriate power of the scalar field and a dimensionless coeffi- cient. In a series of examples they show that “with a suitable quantization procedure, the equivalence between conformal frames can also be maintained in the quantum theory” (Codello et al., 2013, p. 21). They even can show that the renormalization flow preserves the Weyl symmetry in their case studies. This stands in contrast to Dengiz/Tekin’s observation mentioned above. It would be interesting to see, whether a coherent scale covariantization as used by Codello/Percacci et al. can be imple- mented in their scheme too, leading to a maintenance of the scale symmetry also in the context of a perturbative quantization of gravity.

42 5.4 Open questions in cosmology and dark matter

Weyl geometric gravity can also be used to explore the open problems in cosmol- ogy and dark matter phenomena from its sight. Already Weyl started to consider cosmological questions in his extended geometrical framework. Since the retake of it by Dirac and the Japanese authors the conjecture that the Weyl field, or now also the gravitational scalar field, might help understanding dark matter effects has been expressed by different authors time and again. This is so still today. There even is an author of the 1970/80s, A. Maeder, who has taken up the line of inves- tigation following Dirac and Canuto after an interruption of several decades, with the goal of establishing links to the present research in cosmology and astrophysics (Maeder, 2017a,b,c) (cf. sec. 3.2). This is an interesting attempt, but as I can see the approach of these papers suffers from an incoherent usage of scale transformation conventions and an unclear dynamical basis. It needs more time and astronomical expertise to judge whether the striking results claimed by the author with regard to accounting for recent empirical data (CMB, galactic rotation, cluster dynamics) are crucially affected by the theoretical deficiencies, or whether they can be upheld in an improved framework. If so, Maeder’s approach would indicate a blueprint for a unifying account of cosmology and dark matter phenomena,which is rather, perhaps even fundamentally, different from the present mainstream picture of cosmology and dark matter. In the sequel I discuss two less incisive examples of recent research approaches to the field from the point of view of Weyl geometry. A review of the cosmological investigations of the Brazilian group initiated by M. Novello and its external Greek contributor J. Miritzis (see sec. 3.2) has been given at another place.74 Here I add a short discussion of studies by a group of authors around J. Jiménez and T. Koivisto (later also including L. Heisenberg) (Jiménez/Koivisto, 2014, 2016b; Jiménez et al., 2016a)andsupplementit bya remarkona recentproposalformodelling galactic and cluster dynamics in a Weyl geometric scalar tensor theory with an unconventional kinetic term (Scholz, 2019). A comparison of the Weyl geometric approach(es) with conformal cosmological models of a more general type, in particular C. Wetterich’s “universe without expansion” (Wetterich, 1988, 2013), would be an interesting task, but cannot be carried out here. Let us start the report on the first example with an interesting remark made by the two authors of the first paper about the reason for studying a Weyl geometric framework:

. . . (T)he nearly scale invariant spectrum of cosmological perturbations and the fact that the Higgs mass is the only term breaking scale invariance in the Standard Model of elementary particles are very suggestive indications that this could be an actual symmetry of a more fundamental theory that has been spontaneously broken (Jiménez/Koivisto, 2014, p. 2).

The paper is intended to lay the ground for further investigations of gravity and cosmology in the framework of Weyl geometry.

74 (Scholz, 2018a, sec. 11.6.4)

43 In the second paper, (Jiménez/Koivisto, 2016b), the framework is extended to what the authors call a generalized Weyl geometry. Here a linear connection Γ with non-vanishing torsion is accepted, accompanied by a concomitant generalization of the Weyl geometric compatibility condition (16) between the Riemannian component of the Weylian metric and the covariant derivative Γ : ∇( ) g = 2b ϕ g , (32) ∇ − ⊗ where b is any real valued parameter.The permissible linear connections in any scale gauge g, ϕ are then given by the 2-parameter family: ( ) µ µ µ µ µ Γ = Γ g + b′δ ϕλ + b δ ϕµ b′ϕ gµν (33) νλ ( )νλ ν λ − λ λ For b , b′ the connection has torsion, with Γµν Γνµ (the distorsion) being a linear expression in the Weyl field ϕ. For both parameters− equal 1 the usual (torsion free) Weyl geometric structure is included in the generalized framework.75 The authors study quadratic gravity theories in this generalized framework. With an interesting argumentthey constrain the quadratic terms by the (external) condition that their Riemannian component reduces to the Chern-Gauss-Bonnet form, (22) for case n = 4: The reason for this restriction is the well-known fact that the Gauss-Bonnet term (. . . ) leads to second order equations of motion for the metric tensor and, thus, avoids the potential presence of Ostrogradski’s instabilities (Jiménez/Koivisto, 2014, sec. III). This adds a classical field theoretic argument to the quantum field consideration reproduced in sec. 5.3 for constraining quadratic gravity theories by the Gauss- Bonnet relation. Like the Brazilian group Jiménez/Koivisto don’t insist on a scale invariance of their complete Lagrange density. Vaguely appealing to some “spontaneously” breaking of the scale symmetry at high energies, they add a (Weyl geometric) Einstein term which does the job, or at least documents a broken scale symmetry:

1 n 2 LE = M − R det g n = dim M −2 p | | ( ) p In later papers they use more general considerations also violating the scale in- variance of the total Lagrangian. This seems to be a precondition for constructing cosmological models which allow to establish links with the present mainstream discourse. (Jiménez/Koivisto, 2016b) starts with a general functional term of the form f R (with Weyl geometric scalar curvature R), which is transformed via a Lagrangian( ) constraint trick into the form of a scalar tensor theory of Brans-Dicke type, with the Lagrangian constraint function playing the role of the scalar field (Jiménez/Koivisto, 2016b, eq. (21)). In very simple cases (“taking into account only

75 The authors start from a slightly more general linear connection with three parameters b1, b2, b3 but soon specialize to the generalized metric compatibility of the general form (32), which implies b3 = 2b1 b2. The corresponding parameters used here are then given by b = b1 b2 , b′ = 1 b + b −. ( − ) 2 ( 2 3)

44 = + R2 the leading order quadratic correction to the Einstein-Hilbert action”, L R 6M 2 ) the authors arrive at a model which in the Riemannian case implies a special type of inflationary scenario (“Starobinsky inflation”). In their Weyl geometric gener- alization they find a 1-parameter generalization of this model due to the Weylian scale connection, similar to a vector field introduced also by other approaches in the literature. This is only the starting point for more extensive studies of cosmological models in (Jiménez et al., 2016a) undertaken with extended (wo-)manpowerby including L. Heisenberg into the team. The three researchers study a class of quadratic gravity theories in generalized Weyl geometry satisfying the Gauss-Bonnet relation and with a scale symmetry breaking Einstein-Hilbert term. By assuming an external constraint of a purely temporal and homogeneous scale connection they reduce their geometrical “vector tensor” theory to a scalar tensor theory with a scalar field (the temporal component of the scale connection) satisfying a non-dynamical algebraic constraint (ibid. p. 8). They study perturbations around the de Sitter universe and look for bouncing solutions, which arise for non-realistic values of the paramaters only. Finally properties arising from adding a matter component to the Lagrangian are studied. Resuming their work the authors find that

. . . the class of vector-tensor theories studied in this work and which naturally arise in the framework of geometries with a linear vector distortion can give rise to a rich an[d] interesting phenomenology for cosmology. (Jiménez et al., 2016a, p. 23)

This adds rich material to the stock of models already studied without generalizing the Weyl geometric structure by the Brazilian group and Miritzis; but it keeps still far away from the quest for an improved, or even alternative, understanding of empirical data. From a cultural point of view one might get the impression that now also part of the work in Weyl geometric gravity has joined the “postmodern” wave of studying the widest possible range of theoretical models with only vague allusions to the empirical data collected in astronomy and observational cosmology. The approach in (Scholz, 2019) has a different motivation. It deals with the question whether a Weyl geometric linear gravity theory (β1 = β2 = β3 = 0 in (21)) with scalar field can reproduce the deviation of galactic dynamics from the Newtonian expectation, i.e. imply MOND-like dynamics for low velocity trajectories, andleadto a gravitational light deflection which one would expect for a dark matter explanation of the anomalous galactic dynamics.76 According to (31) the author assumes a framework of integrable Weyl geometry (external constraint fµν = 0 in (21)) and studies the consequences of an unconventional kinetic term L∂φ of the scalar field. So far this approach can be understood as a generalized BD-type scalar field theory in a Weyl geometric setting; it furthermore has to assumes a screening of the scalar field which restricts its sphere of action to regimes of extremely weak gravity like in the superfluid approach to anomalous galactic dynamics (Berezhiani/Khoury, 2015,

76 MOND stands for the modified Newtonian dynamics devised by M. Milgrom (Milgrom, 1983). It is characterized by a new constant a0 with the dimension of an acceleration. For a recent survey see (Famaey/McGaugh, 2012).

45 2016, 2019). The kinetic term of the scalar field combines a cubic expression L∂φ3 in the partial derivatives of the scalar field ∂φ 3 and a second order derivative (in 2 | | ∂ φ) term L∂2φ, both of weight 4 and a scale invariant Lagrange density, −

L∂φ = L∂φ3 + L∂2φ . (34)

L∂φ3 is similar to the kinetic term in the first relativistic generalization of the MOND theory introduced by J. Bekenstein and M Milgrom, called RAQUAL (“relativistic aquadratic Lagrangian”) (Bekenstein/Milgrom, 1984). L∂2φ is adapted from the cosmological studies of Novello and the Brazilian group (Novello et al., 1993), but has been modified such that w L∂2φ = 4. Due to its special form it keeps the dynamical equation for φ of second( order.) 77− The Lagrangian density of baryonic matter is assumed to be brought into a scale invariant form such that its (twice covariant) Hilbert energy-momentum tensor scales with weight 2. Stretching the result of the Geroch-Jang theorem slightly, from test bodies to− extended bulk of matter, the free fall trajectories of matter can reasonably be assumed to follow Weyl geometric geodesics (see end of sec. 4.2). The Einstein gauge is considered as distinguished for indicating measured values of observable quantities (cf. ( ) in section 5.4). The Levi-Civita part Γ g of the affine connection in Einstein gauge∗ can be computed from the Riemannian( component) of the Weyl geometric Einstein equation, and the scale connection contribution Γ ϕ from the scalar field equation. Step by step the following properties of the model( are) established in (Scholz, 2019): 1 With the scale connection in Einstein gauge written in the form ϕ  dσ like Eg in (25), the weak field approximation of the scalar field equation leads to a non- linear Poisson equation for σ, known from Milgrom’s theory for the deep MOND regime, σ σ = 4πGao ρbar ∇·(|∇ |∇ ) with the usual MOND constant a0; Scholz calls it the Milgrom equation. It is sourced by baryonic matter only.78 2 σ induces an acceleration for free fall trajectories, due to the scale connection, aϕ = σ. It is of deep MOND type. 3 The weak−∇ field approximation for determining the Riemannian component g of the Weylian metric in the Einstein gauge boils down to a Newton approximation exactly like in Einstein gravity. It is sourced by the baryonic matter only, not by the scale field (see 4), and induces an acceleration aN like in Newton gravity with potential ΦN .

77 For the variation with regard to φ the second order terms of L∂2φ form a divergence expression; not so, however, while varying g. Thus the dynamical equation of φ remains of second order, while the L∂2φ term contributes essentially to the source term of the Einstein equation (the Hilbert energy-momentum tensor). 78 In complete generality, the scalar field equation in Einstein gauge is a scale covariant generaliza- tion of the Milgrom equation.

46 4 The scalar field has an energy momentum tensor with non-negligible energy 1 2 density ρφ = 4πG σ. This looks like dark matter, but is has negative ( )− ∇ pressures p1, p2, p3 with peculiar properties: (i) The contribution of the scalar field to the Newton-Poisson source (of the Einstein weak field equation) vanishes, ρφ + pj = 0. (ii) On the other hand it contributes to the gravitationalÍ light deflection. In the central symmetric case it does so by an additive contributionof2σto the deflection potential. For baryonic matter in Einstein gravity the deflection potential is 2ΦN.79 5 (i) 2 and 3 together imply a MOND-like phenomenologyfor test particles, with a deep MOND acceleration added to the Newtonian one, both with the source ρbar , in the regime of activity of the scalar field (screened for larger accelerations). (ii) The light deflection of the model is identical to the one expected for a source given by ρbar + ρφ in Einstein gravity. (iii) The “dynamical phantom mass” ρphant, i.e. the mass density expected in Newton gravity for generating the additional acceleration aϕ predicted by the model, coincides with the “optical phantom mass” ρphant′ which one would expect in a dark matter approachfor the same light deflection as in the model. Both agree = = with the mass/energy density of the scalar field, ρφ ρphant ρphant′ . Resumée: The gravitational effects for test bodies and for light rays of the model’s scalar field φ, observed in the Einstein gauge, coincide with those of a halo of (pressure-less) dark matter generating a Newtonian potential σ, althoughthe energy- momentum of the scalar field carries negative pressures and is, in this sense, similar to “dark energy”. The potential σ of the additional acceleration due to the scale connection is given by a Milgrom equation (with the baryonic matter as its source). This is an exceptional model among the many models which propose relativistic generalizations of Milgrom’s modified Newtonian dynamics. Most of them work with several scalar fields, often also with an additional dynamical vector field, and/or strange (non-conformal) deformations of the metric. The original RAQUAL theory, with only one additional scalar field, is inconsistent with the observed amount of gravitational light deflection in galaxies and clusters. To my knowledge the present Weyl geometric scalar tensor model is the only one with a single scalar field (at large scales, thus not counting the Higgs field here) leading to MOND-like dynamics and an according enhancement of the gravitational light deflection.80 But alas, its kinetic term looks so strange that it may remain an exercise in theory construction only. In any case, it deserves to be mentioned here as an outcome of recent and even present investigations in Weyl geometric gravity.

79 The deflection angle is computed from the first two components of the Ricci tensor like in 1 + (Carroll, 2004, p. 288f.). It is the gradient of 2 h00 h jj (for any 1 j 3), where h is the (− ) = + ≤1 ≤ + deviation of a weak field metric from the Minkowski metric, g η h. 2 h00 h jj thus plays the role of a deflection potential. (− ) 80 Of course that has to be checked by astronomers. Heuristic considerations indicate that the model may even “predict” the dynamics of galaxy clusters without assuming additional dark matter (Scholz, 2019, sec. 3.2).

47 6 An extremely short glance back and forth

We have seen an eventful trajectory of Weyl’s proposal for generalizing Riemannian geometry during the last century: from a promising first attempt (1918 to the middle of the 1920s) at formulating a type of geometry which was intended to bring the framework of gravity closer to the principles of other field theories, at that time essentially electromagnetism, through a phase of disillusion and non-observance (1930 – 1970), to a new rise in the 1970s. In the last third of the 20th century dispersed contributions to various fields of physics brought Weyl geometry back as a geometrical framework for actual research, partially fed by the introduction of a hypothetical scalar field which had at least one foot in the gravitational sector. But these new researches were far from influential on the main lines of development in theoretical physics. Although first hypothetical links between the new attempts at Weyl geometric generalizations of gravity theory and the rising standard model of elementary par- ticle physics were soon formulated, they remained rather marginal. Also the vistas opened up by Weyl geometric scalar tensor theories for astronomy at large scales and cosmology remained without a visible impact on the respective communities. One reasonforthe overallreservationmayhavebeenthe fact that, at that time, scalar fields played only a hypothetical, perhaps even only formal role within physical theories. This changed, of course, with the empirical confirmation of the Higgs boson. It may be worthwhile to investigate whether an additional scalar field with links to the Higgs portal and gravity can help to answer some of the open questions of the present foundational research in physics. Some of the recent work surveyed in this paper make already some steps in this direction. As it is always difficult to discern reliable patterns of actual developments, I leave it as a question for the future to judge whether this is a fruitful enterprise, or just another contribution to screening possible theory alternatives without clear evidence of empirical support. To end with a personal remark as a historian of mathematics who has spent some time on studying the development of this subfield of physical geometry: it is pleasant to see that, contrary to Weyl’s disillusionment in this regard after 1920, his beautiful and conceptually convincing idea for generalizing Riemannian geometry is still alive and helps triggering new lines of research also a century after it was first devised.

48 References

Abraham, Ralph; Marsden, Jerold E. 1978. Foundations of Classical Mechanics. Redwood City etc.: Addison Wesley. 5-th revised ed. 1985. 28 Afriat, Alexander. 2013. “Weyl’s gauge argument.” Foundations of Physics 43:699–705. 7, 13 Afriat, Alexander. 2019. “Logic of gauge.” In (Bernard/Lobo, 2019, p. 265–203). 7 Almeida, Tony S.; Formiga, Jansen B.; Pucheu, Maria L.; Romero, Carlos. 2014a. “From Brans- Dicke gravity to a geometrical scalar-tensor theory.” Physical Review D 89:064047 (10pp.). arXiv:1311.5459. 35 Almeida, Tony S.; Pucheu, Maria L.; Romero, Carlos. 2014b. A geometrical approach to Brans- Dicke theory. In Accelerated Cosmic Expansion, ed. C. Moreno Gonzales; J.E. Madriz Aguliar; L.M. Reyes Barrera. Vol. 38 of Astrophysics and Space Science Proceedings pp. 33–41. 35 Audretsch, Jürgen. 1983. “Riemannian structure of space-time as a consequence of quantum mechanics.” Physcial Review D 27:2872–2884. 26 Audretsch, Jürgen; Gähler, Franz; Straumann Norbert. 1984. “Wave fields in Weyl spaces and conditions for the existence of a preferred pseudo-riemannian structure.” Communications in Mathematical Physics 95:41–51. 26 Audretsch, Jürgen; Lämmerzahl, Claus. 1988. “Constructive axiomatic approach to spacetime torsion.” Classical and Quantum Gravity 5:1285–1295. 26 Bacciagaluppi, Guido. 2005. A conceptual introduction to Nelson’s mechanics. In Endophysics, time, quantum and the subjective, ed. R. Buccheri; M. Saniga; A. Elitzur. Singapore: World Scientific pp. 367–388. Revised postprint in philsci-archive.pitt.edu/8853/1/Nelson-revised.pdf. 27 Baeumler, Alfred; Schroeter, Manfred. 1927. Handbuch der Philosophie. Bd. II. Natur, Geist, Gott. München: Oldenbourg. 56 Bars, Itzhak; Steinhardt, Paul; Turok, Neil. 2014. “Local conformal symmetry in physics and cosmology.” Physical Review D 89:043515. arXiv:1307.1848. 40 Bekenstein, Jacob; Milgrom, Mordechai. 1984. “Does the missing mass problem signal the break- down of Newtonian gravity?” Astrophysical Journal 286:7–14. 46 Berezhiani, Lasha; Khoury, Justin. 2015. “Theory of dark matter superfluidity.” Physical Reviews D 92(103510). arXiv:1507.01019. 45 Berezhiani, Lasha; Khoury, Justin. 2016. “Dark matter superfluidity and galactic dynamics.” Physics Letters B 753:639–643. arXiv:1506.07877. 46 Berezhiani, Lasha; Khoury, Justin. 2019. “Emergent long-range interactions in Bose-Einstein condensates.” Physical Review D 99:076003. arXiv:1812.09332. 46 Bernard, Julien. 2013. L’idéalisme dans l’infinitésimal. Weyl et l’espace à l’époque de la relativité. Paris: Presse Universitaires de Paris Ouest. 12 Bernard, Julien. 2015. “La redécouverte des tapuscrits des conférences d’Hermann Weyl à Barcelone.” Revue d’histoire des mathématiques 21(1):151–171. 11 Bernard, Julien. 2018. “Riemann’s and Helmholtz-Lie’s problems of space from Weyl’s relativistic perspective.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 61:41–56. 11 Bernard, Julien; Lobo, Carlos (eds.). 2019. Weyl and the Problem of Space. From Science to Philosophy. Berlin etc.: Springer. 11, 49, 50 Blagojević, Milutin; Hehl, Friedrich. 2013. Gauge Theories of Gravitation. A Reader with Com- mentaries. London: Imperial College Press. 20, 52, 55 Borrelli, Arianna. 2015a. “The making of an intrinsic property: “symmetry heuristics” in early particle physics.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics A 50:59–70. 7, 18 Borrelli, Arianna. 2015b. “The story of the Higgs boson: the origin of mass in early particle physics.” European Physical Journal H 40(1):1–52. 7 Borrelli, Arianna. 2017. “The uses of isospin in early nuclear and particle physics.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 60:81–94. 7, 18 Bouvier, Paul; Maeder, André. 1979. “Scale invariance, metrical connection and the motions of astronomical bodies.” Astronomy and Astrophysics 73:82–89. 24

49 Bouvier, Pierre; Maeder, André. 1977. “Consistency of Weyl’s geometry as a framework for gravitation.” Astrophysics and Space Science 54:497–508. 24 Brans, Carl; Dicke, Robert H. 1961. “Mach’s principle and a relativistic theory of gravitation.” Physical Review 124:925–935. 16 Bregman, Alexander. 1973. “Weyl transformations and Poincaré gauge invariance.” Progress of Theoretical Physics 49:667–6992. 20 Bureau International des poids et mesures. 2011. “Resolutions adopted by the Gen- eral Conference on Weights and Measures (24th meeting), Paris, 17–21 October 2011.”. www.bipm.org/en/si/new si/. 17 Callan, Curtis; Coleman, Sidney;− Jackiw Roman. 1970. “A new improved energy-momentum tensor.” Annals of Physics 59:42–73. 23 Canuto, Vittorio; Adams, P.J.; Hsieh, S.-H.; Tsiang, Elaine. 1977. “Scale covariant theory of gravitation and astrophysical application.” Physical Review D 16:1643–1663. 23 Carroll, Sean. 2004. Spacetime and Geometry. San Francisco: Addison Wesley. 47 Castro, Carlos. 1992. “On Weyl geometry, random processes, and geometric quantum mechanics.” Foundations of Physics 22:569–615. 28 Cesare, Marco de; Moffat, John W.; Sakellariadou, Mairi. 2017. “Non-Riemannian geometry and the origin of physical scales in a theory with local conformal symmetry.” European Journal of Physics C 77(605). 12 pages, arXiv:1612.08066. 39, 40 Charap, John M.; Tait, W. 1974. “A gauge theory of the Weyl group.” Proceedings Royal Society London A 340:249–262. 22, 24 Cheng, Hung. 1988. “Possible existence of Weyl’s vector meson.” Physical Review Letters 61:2182– 2184. 24, 39 Codello, Alessandro; D’Orodico, Giulio; Pagani, Carlo; Percacci, Roberto. 2013. “The renor- malization group and Weyl invariance.” Classical and Quantum Gravity 30:115015 (22 pp.). arXiv:1210.3284. 42 Coleman, Robert; Korté, Herbert. 1984. “Constraints on the nature of inertial motion arising from the universality of free fall and the conformal causal structure of spacetime.” Journal of Mathematical Physics 25:3513–3526. 27 De Bianchi, Silvia. 2019. “From the problem of space to the epistemology of science: Hermann Weyl’s reflections on the dimensionality of the world.”. In (Bernard/Lobo, 2019, p. 189–209). 10 De Martini, Francesco; Santamato, Enrico. 2014a. “Interpretation of quantum-nonlocality by conformal geometrodynamics.” International Journal of Theoretical Physics 53:3308–3322. arXiv:1203:0033. 28 De Martini, Francesco; Santamato, Enrico. 2014b. “Nonlocality, no-signalling, and Bell’s the- orem investigated by Weyl conformal differential geometry.” Physica Scripta 2014:T163. arXiv:1406.2970. 28 De Martini, Francesco; Santamato, Enrico. 2015. “Proof of the spin-statistics theorem.” Foundations of Physics 45(7):858–873. 28 De Martini, Francesco; Santamato, Enrico. 2016. “Proof of the spin-statistics theorem in the relativistic regime by Weyl’s conformal quantum mechanics.” International Journal of Quantum Information 14(04):1640011. 28 Dengiz, Suat; Tekin, Bayram. 2011. “Higgs mechanism for new massive gravity and Weyl-invariant extensions of higher-derivative theories.” Physical Revie D 84(024033). 7 pages. 41 Dicke, Robert H. 1962. “Mach’s principle and invariance under transformations of units.” Physical Review 125:2163–2167. 5, 16 Dirac, Paul A.M. 1973. “Long range forces and broken symmetries.” Proceedings Royal Society London A 333:403–418. 20, 21, 22, 23 Dirac, Paul A.M. 1974. “Cosmological models and the large number hypothesis.” Proceedings Royal Society London A 338:439–446. 21 Drechlser, Wolfgang. 1999. “Mass generation by Weyl symmetry breaking.” Foundations of Physics 29:1327–1369. 24

50 Drechsler, Wolfgang. 1991. “Geometric formulation of gauge theories.” Zeitschrift f. Natur- forschung 46a:645–654. 24 Drechsler, Wolfgang. 1999a. “Mass generation by Weyl symmetry breaking.” Foundations of Physics 29:1327–1369. 39 Drechsler, Wolfgang; Tann, Hanno. 1999b. “Broken Weyl invariance and the origin of mass.” Foundations of Physics 29(7):1023–1064. arXiv:gr-qc/98020. 24, 39 Duerr, Patrick. 2019. “Unweyling three mysteries of Nordström gravity.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science B . Available online 14 September 2019. 37 Eddington, Arthur S. 1923. The Mathematical Theory of Relativity. Cambridge: University Press. 2nd edition 1924. 9, 22 Ehlers, Jürgen; Pirani, Felix; Schild, Alfred. 1972. The geometry of free fall and light propagation. In General Relativity, Papers in Honour of J.L. Synge, ed. L. O’Raifertaigh. Oxford: Clarendon Press pp. 63–84. 24, 25, 26 Einstein, Albert. 1921. “Über eine naheliegende Ergänzung des Fundamentes der allgemeinen Relativitätstheorie.” Sitzungsberichte der Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Berlin, physikalisch-math. Klasse pp. 261–264. In (Einstein, 1987ff., 7 Doc. 54, p. 411–416), in (Einstein, 2006, p. 198–201). 9 Einstein, Albert. 1987ff. The Collected Papers of Albert Einstein. Princeton: University Press. 6, 10, 51 Einstein, Albert. 2006. Akademie-Vorträge. Herausgegeben von Dieter Simon. Weinheim: Wiley- VCH. 51 Famaey, Benoît; McGaugh, Stacy. 2012. “Modified Newtonian dynamics (MOND): Observational phenomenology and relativistic extensions.” Living Reviews in Relativity 15(10):1–159. 45 Faraoni, Valerio. 2004. Cosmology in Scalar-Tensor Gravity. Dordrecht etc.: Kluwer. 18 Frauendiener, Jörg. 2000. “Conformal infinity.” Living Reviews in Relativity 3(4). 19 Fujii, Yasunori; Maeda, Kei-Chi. 2003. The Scalar-Tensor Theory of Gravitation. Cambridge: University Press. 18, 35, 36 Galison, Peter. 1997. Image and Logic. A Material Culture of Microphyics. Chicago: University Press. 7 Geroch, Robert; Jang, Pong Soo. 1975. “Motion of a body in general relativity.” Journal of Mathematical Physics 16:65–67. 35 Ghilencea, Dumitru M. 2019. “Spontaneous breaking of Weyl quadratic gravity to Einstein action and Higgs potential.” Journal of High Energy Physics 2019:Article 49. arXiv:1812.08613. 41 Goenner, Hubert. 2004. “On the history of unified field theories.” Living Reviews in Relativity 2004-2. http://relativity.livingreviews.org/Articles/lrr-2004-2. 4, 7 Goenner, Hubert. 2012. “Some remarks on the genesis of scalar-tensor theories.” General Relativity and Gravity 44(8):2077–2097. arXiv: 1204.3455. 16 Haantjes, Johannes. 1941. “The conformal Dirac equation.” Verhandelingen Koninklijke Neder- landse Akademie van Wetenschappen Amsterdam, Proceedings section of sciences 44:324–332. 15, 19 Hall, Brian C. 2001. Quantum Theory for Mathematicians. Berlin ets: Springer. 28 Hayashi, Kenji; Kugo, Taichiro. 1979. “Remarks on Weyl’s gauge field.” Progress of Theoretical Physics 61:334–346. 21 Hehl, Friedrich W.; Lämmerzahl, Claus. 2019. “Physical dimensioins/units and unvisersal con- stants: their invaricanc in special and general relativity.” Annalen der Physik 531(5):1800407, 10 pages. 17 Hehl, Friedrich W.; McCrea, J. Dermott; Kopczy`nski, W. 1988a. “The Weyl group and ist currents.” Physics Letters A 128:313–318. 24 Hehl, Friedrich W.; Mielke, Eckehard; Tresguerres, Romualdo. 1988b. Weyl spacetimes, the dilation current, and creation of gravitating mass by symmetry breaking. In Exact Sciences and their Philosophical Foundations; Exakte Wissenschaften und ihre philosophische Grundlegung, ed. W. Deppert; K. Hübner e.a. Frankfurt/Main etc.: Peter Lang pp. 241–310. 24 Heisenberg, Werner. 1957. “Quantum theory of fields and elementary particles.” Reviews of Modern Physics 29:269–278. 18

51 Hessenberg, Gerhard. 1917. “Vektorielle Begründung der Differentialgeometrie.” Mathematische Annalen 79:187–217. 8 Israelit, Mark. 1999. The Weyl-Dirac Theory and Our Universe. New York: Nova Science. 24 Israelit, Mark; Rosen, Nathan. 1992. “Weyl-Dirac geometry and dark matter.” Foundations of Physics 22:555–568. 24 Israelit, Mark; Rosen, Nathan. 1995. “Cosmic dark matter and Dirac gauge function.” Foundations of Physics 25:763–777. 24 Jiménez, Jose B.; Heisenberg, Lavinia; Koivisto, Tomi S. 2016a. “Cosmology for quadratic gravity in generalized Weyl geometry.” Journal of Cosmology and Astroparticle Physics 04(046):29 pages. 43, 45 Jiménez, Jose B.; Koivisto, Tomi S. 2014. “Extended Gauss-Bonnet gravities in Weyl geometry.” Classical and Quantum Gravity 31(13):135002. arXiv:1402.1846,. 31, 33, 43, 44 Jiménez, Jose B.; Koivisto, Tomi S. 2016b. “Spacetimes with vector distortion: Inflation from generalised Weyl geometry.” Physical Letters B 756:400–404. arXiv:1509.02476. 43, 44 Jordan, Pascual. 1952. Schwerkraft und Weltall. Braunschweig: Vieweg. 2nd revised edtion 1955. 16 Kastrup, Hans. 1962a. “Some experimental consequences of conformal invariance at very high energies.” Physics Letters 3:78–80. 18 Kastrup, Hans. 1962b. “Zur physikalischen Deutung und darstellungstheoretischen Analyse der konromen Transformationen von Raum und Zeit.” Annalen der Physik 9:388–428. 18 Kastrup, Hans. 1966. “Gauge properties of Minkowski space.” Physical Review 150(4):1183–1193. 19 Kastrup, Hans. 2008. “On the advancement of conformal transformations and their associated symmetries in goemetry and theoretical physics.” Annalen der Physik 17:631–690. 18, 19 Kibble, Thomas. 1961. “Lorentz invariance and the gravitational field.” Journal for Mathematical Physics 2:212–221. In (Blagojević/Hehl, 2013, chap. 4). 20 Kock, Anders. 2006. Synthetic Differential Geometry (2nd edition). London: London Mathematical Society. Revised version of 1st edition 1981. 12 Kostant, Bertram. 1970. Quantization and unitary representations. 1. Prequantisation. Vol. 170 of Lecture Notes in Mathematics Berlin etc.: Springer. 28 Kragh, Helge. 1999. Quantum Generations : A History of Physics in the Twentieth Century. Princeton: University Press. 7 Kragh, Helge. 2016. Varying Gravity. Dirac’s Legacy in Cosmology and Geophyics. Science Networks Heidelberg etc: Springer-Birkhäuser. 16, 21 Kühnel, Wolfgang. 1999. Differentialgeometrie. Kurven – Flächen – Mannigfaltigkeiten. Braun- schweig/Wiesbaden: Vieweg. English as Differential Geometry –Curves – Surfaces – Manifolds American Mathematical Society 2000. 32 Lehmkuhl, Dennis. 202x. “The first rival: Jordan’s scalar-tensor theory and its role in reconsidering the foundationis of General Relativity.” Manuscript in preparation. 16 Lehmkuhl, Dennis. 20yy. “The Einstein-Weyl correspondence on the geodesic principle.”. 6 Maeder, André. 1980. “The problem of varying G and the scale covariant gravitation and cosmol- ogy.”. 24 Maeder, André. 2017a. “An alternative to the ΛCDM model: the case of scale invariance.” Astrophysical Journal (834). 16 pages. 43 Maeder, André. 2017b. “Dynamical effects of the scale invariance of the empty space: The fall of dark matter?” Astrophysical Journal (849). 13 pages, arXiv:1710.11425. 24, 43 Maeder, André. 2017c. “Scale-invariant cosmology and CMB temperatures as a function of redshifts.” Astrophysical Journal (847):065. 7 pages,. 24, 43 Maeder, André. 2018. “The acceleration relation in galaxies and scale invariant dynamics: another challenge for dark matter.”. arXiv:1804.04484. 24 Matveev, Vladimir S.; Trautman, Andrzej. 2014. “A criterion for compatibility of conformal and proojective structures.” Communications in Mathematical Physics 329:821–825. 12, 26, 37, 38 Merker, Joël. 2010. Le problème de l’espace. Sophus Lie, Friedrich Engel et le probléme de Riemann-Helmholtz. Paris: Hermann. 11

52 Milgrom, Mordechai. 1983. “A modification of Newtonian dynamcis as a possible alternative to the hidden matter hypothesis.” Astrophysical Journal 270:365–370. 45 Nishino, Hitoshi; Rajpoot, Subhash. 2004. “Broken scale invariance in the standard model.”. arXiv:hep-th/0403039. 39, 41 Nishino, Hitoshi; Rajpoot, Subhash. 2007. “Broken Scale Invariance in the Standard Mode.” AIP Conference Proceedings 881:82–93. arXiv:0805.0613 (with different title). 39 Nishino, Hitoshi; Rajpoot, Subhash. 2009. “Implication of compensator field and local scale invariance in the standard model.” Physical Review D 79:125025. arXiv:0906.4778. 39 Novello, Mário, Oliveira L.A.R. 1986. “A marionette universe.” International Journal of Modern Physics A 1(4):943–953. 24 Novello, Mário; Oliveira, L.A.R.; Salim, Jose .M.; Elbaz, Edgar. 1993. “Geometrized instantons and the creation of the universe.” International Journal of Modern Physics D 1:641–677. 24, 46 Ohanian, Hans. 2010. “The energy-momentum tensor in General Relativity and in alternative theories of gravitation, and the gravitational vs. Inertial mass.”. arXiv:1010.5557[gr-qc]. 35 Ohanian, Hans. 2016. “Weyl gauge-vector and complex dilaton scalar for conformal symmetry and its breaking.” General Relativity and Gravity 48(25):DOI 10.1007/s10714–016–2023–8. arXiv:1502.00020. 41 Omote, Minoru. 1971. “Scale transformations of the second kind and the Weyl space-time.” Lettere al Nuovo Cimento 2(2):58–60. 20 Omote, Minoru. 1974. “Remarks on the local-scale-invariant gravitational theory.” Lettere al Nuovo Cimento 10(2):33–37. 20 O’Raifeartaigh, Lochlainn. 1997. The Dawning of Gauge Theory. Princeton: University Press. 55, 56 Ornea, Liviu. 2001. Weyl structures in quaternionic geomety. A state of the art. In Selected Topics in Geometry and Mathematical Physics, Vol. 1, ed. E. Barletta. Potenza: Univ. degli Studi della Basilicata pp. 43–80. arXiv:math/0105041. 31 Pauli, Wolfgang. 1940. “Über die Invarianz der Dirac’schen Wellengleichungen gegenüber Ähn- lichkeitstransformationen des Linienelementes im Fall verschwindender Ruhmasse.” Helvetia Physica Acta 13:204–208. In (Pauli, 1964, II, 918–922). 16 Pauli, Wolfgang. 1964. Collected Scientific Papers. Eds. R. Kronig, V.F. Weisskopf. New York etc.: Wiley. 53 Penrose, Roger. 1964. The light cone at infinity. In Relativistic Theories of Gravitation, ed. Leopold Infeld. Pergamon pp. 369–373. 19 Penrose, Roger. 1965. “Zero rest-mass fields including gravitation: asymptotic behaviour.” Pro- ceedings Royal Society London A 284:159–203. 18, 22 Perlick, Volker. 1987. “Characterization of standard clocks by means of light rays and freely falling particles’.” General Relativity and Gravitation 19:1059–1073. 27 Perlick, Volker. 1989. Zur Kinematik Weylscher Raum-Zeit-Modelle. Dissertationsschrift. Berlin: Fachbereich Physik, TU Berlin. 9, 27 Perlick, Volker. 1991. “Observer fields in Weylian spacetime models.” Classical and Quantum Gravity 8:1369–1385. 27 Pfister, Herbert. 2004. “Newton’s first law revisited.” Foundations of Physics Letters 17:49–64. 27 Pickering, Andrew. 1988. Constructing Quarks. Edinburgh: University Press. 7 Quiros, Israel. 2013a. “Scale invariance and broken electroweak symmetry may coexist together.”. arXiv:1312.1018. 39 Quiros, Israel. 2014. “Scale invariant theory of gravity and the standard model of particles.”. arXiv:1401.2643. 39 Quiros, Israel; Garcìa-Salcedo, Ricardo; Madriz, Aguilar José E.; Matos, Tonatiuh. 2013b. “The conformal transformations’ controversy: what are we missing.” General Relativity and Gravita- tion 45:489–518. arXiv:1108.5857. 35, 36 Romero, Carlos; Fonsec-Neto, J.B.; Pucheu, Maria L. 2012a. “Conformally flat spacetimes and Weyl frames.” Foundations of Physics 42:224–240. arXiv:1101.5333. 36, 37 Romero, Carlos; Fonseca-Neto, J.B.; Pucheu, Maria .L. 2011. “General relativity and Weyl frames.” International Journal of Modern Physics A 26(22):3721–3729. arXiv:1106.5543. 36

53 Romero, Carlos; Fonseca-Neto, J.B.; Pucheu, Maria L. 2012b. “General relativity and Weyl geometry.” Classical and Quantum Gravity 29(15):155015 (18pp). arXiv:1201.1469. 36 Rosen, Nathan. 1982. “Weyl’s geometry and physics.” Foundations of Physics 12:213–248. 24 Ryckman, Thomas. 2005. The Reign of Relativity. Philosophy in Physics 1915–1925. Oxford: University Press. 7 Santamato, Enrico. 1984a. “Geometric derivation of the Schrödinger equation from classical mechanics in curved Weyl spaces.” Physical Review D 29:216–222. 27 Santamato, Enrico. 1984b. “Statistical interpretation of the Klein-Gordon equation in terms of the spacetime Weyl curvature.” Journal of Mathematical Physics 25(8):2477–2480. 27 Santamato, Enrico. 1985. “Gauge-invariant statistical mechanics and average action principle for the Klein-Gordon particle in geometric quantum mechanics.” Physical Review D 32(10):2615– 2621. 27 Santamato, Enrico; De Martini, Francesco. 2013. “Derivation of the Dirac equation by conformal differential geometry.” Foundations of Physics 43(5):631–641. arXiv:1107.3168. 28 Scholz, Erhard. 2005. Local spinor structures in V. Fock’s and H. Weyl’s work on the Dirac equation (1929). In Géométrie au vingtième siècle, 1930 – 2000, ed. P. Nabonnand J.-J. Szczeciniarz D.Flament, J. Kouneiher. Paris: Hermann pp. 284–301. 13 Scholz, Erhard. 2006. The changing concept of matter in H. Weyl’s thought, 1918 - 1930. In The interaction between Mathematics, Physics and Philosophy from 1850 to 1940, ed. Jesper Lützen et al. Vincent F. Hendricks, Klaus F. Jørgensen. Dordrecht: Springer. [arxiv.org/math.HO/0409576]. 7 Scholz, Erhard. 2011. “Weyl geometric gravity and electroweak symmetry ‘breaking’.” Annalen der Physik 523:507–530. arxiv.org/abs/1102.3478. 39 Scholz, Erhard. 2016. The problem of space in the light of relativity: the views of H. Weyl and E. Cartan. In Eléments d’une biographie de l’Espace géométrique, ed. L. Bioesmat-Martagon. Nancy: Edition Universitaire de Lorraine pp. 255–312. arXiv1310.7334. 11 Scholz, Erhard. 2017. Paving the way for transitions – a case for Weyl geometry. In Towards a Theory of Spacetime Theories, ed. D. Lehmkuhl e.a. Vol. 13 of Einstein Studies Basel, Berlin etc.: Birkhäuser-Springer pp. 171–224. http://arxiv.org/abs/1206.1559. 36, 39, 40 Scholz, Erhard. 2018a. The unexpected resurgence of Weyl gometry in late 20-th century physics. In Beyond Einstein. Perspectives on Geometry, Gravitation and Cosmology, ed. S. Walter D. Rowe, T. Sauer. Vol. 13 of Einstein Studies Basel, Berlin etc.: Birkhäuser-Springer pp. 261–360. arXiv:1703.03187. 24, 29, 39, 43 Scholz, Erhard. 2018b. “Weyl’s search for a difference between ‘physical’ and ’mathematical’ auto- morphisms.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 61:57–67. arXiv:1510.00156. 15 Scholz, Erhard. 2019. “A scalar field inducing a non-metrical contribution to gravitational ac- celeration and a compatible add-on to light deflection.”. arXiv:1906.04989v2. 35, 43, 45, 46, 47 Scholz, Erhard (ed.). 2001. Hermann Weyl’s Raum - Zeit - Materie and a General Introduction to His Scientific Work. Basel etc.: Birkhäuser. 55 Schouten, Jan A. 1921. “Über die konforme Abbildung n-dimensionaler Mannigfaltigkeiten mit quadratischer Maßbestimmmung auf eine Mannigfaltigkeit mit euklidischer Maßbestimmung.” Mathematische Zeitschrift 11:58–88. 9, 11 Schouten, Jan Arnoldus; Haantjes, Jan. 1934. “Über die konforminvariante Gestalt der relativistis- chen Bewegungsgleichungen.” Verhandelingen Koninklijke Nederlandse Akademie van Weten- schappen Amsterdam, Afdeeling Natuurkunde, Reeks 1, Wiskunde etc. 1:869–872. English under https://neo-classical-physics.info/uploads/3/4/3/6/34363841/schouten_haantjes_-_conf._inv._of_maxwell.pdf. 15 Schouten, Jan Arnoldus; Haantjes, Jan. 1936. “Über die konforminvariante Gestalt der rela- tivistischen Bewegungsgleichungen.” Verhandelingen Koninklijke Nederlandse Akademie van Wetenschappen Amsterdam, Proceedings section of sciences 39:1059–1065. English under https://neo-classical-physics.info/uploads/3/4/3/6/34363841/schouten_-_conf._inv._of_rel._eom.pdf. 15

54 Sciama, Dennis W. 1962. On the analogy between charge and spin in general relativity. In Recent Developments in General Relativity Festschrift for L. Infeld. Oxford and Warsaw: Pergamon and PWN pp. 415–439. In (Blagojević/Hehl, 2013, chap. 4). 20 Shaposhnikov, Mikhael; Zenhäusern, Daniel. 2009a. “Quantum scale invariance, cosmological constant and hierarchy problem.” Physics Letters B 671:162–166. arXiv:0809.3406. 40 Shaposhnikov, Mikhael; Zenhäusern, Daniel. 2009b. “Scale invariance, unimodular gravity and dark energy.” Physics Letters B 671:187–192. arXiv:0809.3395. 40 Sigurdsson, Skuli. 1991. Hermann Weyl, mathematics and physics, 1900 – 1927 PhD thesis Harvard University, Department of the History of ’Science Cambridge. 7 Simms, David. 1978. On the Schrödinger equation given by geometric quantization. In Differential Geometrical Methods in Mathematical Physics II, ed. K. Bleuler; H.R. Petry; A. Reetz. Vol. 676 of Lecture Notes in Mathematics Berlin etc.: Springer pp. 351–356. 28 Smolin, Lee. 1979. “Towards a theory of spacetime structure at very short distances.” Nuclear Physics B 160:253–268. 24, 39 Śniarycki, Je¸drzej. 1980. Geometric Quantization and Quantum Mechanics. Berlin etc.: Springer. 28 Souriau, Jean-Marie. 1966. “Quantification géométrique.” Communications in Mathematical Physics 1:374–398. 28 Souriau, Jean-Marie. 1970. Structure des systèmes dynamiques. Paris: Duno. English as (Souriau, 1997). 28, 55 Souriau, Jean-Marie. 1997. Structure of Dynamical Systems. A Symplectic View ofh Physics. Berlin etc.: Springer. Translated from (Souriau, 1970) by C.-H. Cushman-de Vries. 55 Straumann, Norbert. 1987. “Zum Ursprung der Eichtheorien.” Physikalische Blätter 43:414–421. 6 Straumann, Norbert. 2001. Ursprünge der Eichtheorien. In Scholz (2001). pp. 138–160. 13 Tanhayi, M. Reza; Dengiz, Suat; Tekin, Bayram. 2012. “Weyl-invariant higher curvature gravity theories in n dimensions.” Physcial Review D 85(064016). 9 pages. 33, 41, 42 Trautman, Andrzej. 2012. “Editorial note to J. Ehlers, F.A.E. Pirani and A. Schild, The geometry of free fall and light propagation.” General Relativty and Gravity 441:1581–1586. 25, 26, 39 Utiyama, Ryoyu. 1973. “On Weyl’s gauge field.” Progress of Theoretical Physics 50:2028–2090. 20, 21 Utiyama, Ryoyu. 1975a. “On Weyl’s gauge field.” General Relativity and Gravitation 6:41–47. 20 Utiyama, Ryoyu. 1975b. “On Weyl’s gauge field II.” Progress of Theoretical Physics 53:565–574. 20, 21 Vizgin, Vladimir. 1994. Unified Field Theories in the First Third of the 20th Century. Translated from the Russian by J. B. Barbour. Basel etc.: Birkhäuser. 4, 7, 13 Wald, Robert. 1984. General Relativity. Chicago: University Press. 18 Wess, Julius. 1959. “On scale transformations.” Nuovo Cimento 14:527–531. 18 Wess, Julius. 1960. “The conformal invariance in quantum field theory.” Nuovo Cimento 18:1086– 1107. 18 Wetterich, Christian. 2013. “Universe without expansion.”. arXiv:1303.6878. 43 Wetterich, Christion. 1988. “Cosmologies with variable Newton’s constant.” Nuclear Physics B 302:645–667. 43 Weyl, Hermann. 1918/1997. Gravitation and electricity. In The Dawning of Gauge Theory, ed. L. O’Raifeartaigh. Princeton: University Press pp. 23–37. (English translation of Weyl (1918a)). 10 Weyl, Hermann. 1918a. “Gravitation und Elektrizität.” Sitzungsberichte der Königlich Preußischen Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Berlin pp. 465–480. In (Weyl, 1968, II, 29–42), English in (O’Raifeartaigh, 1997, 24–37). 6, 8, 10, 33, 55 Weyl, Hermann. 1918b. Raum, - Zeit - Materie. Vorlesungen über allgemeine Relativitätstheorie. Berlin etc.: Springer. Weitere Auflagen: 21919, 31919, 41921, 51923, 61970, 71988, 81993. 6, 22 Weyl, Hermann. 1918c. “Reine Infinitesimalgeometrie.” Mathematische Zeitschrift 2:384–411. In (Weyl, 1968, II, 1–28). 4, 6, 7, 8, 9

55 Weyl, Hermann. 1919. “Eine neue Erweiterung der Relativitätstheorie.” Annalen der Physik 59:101– 133. In (Weyl, 1968, II, 55–87). 4, 7, 8, 17 Weyl, Hermann. 1921a. “Das Raumproblem.” Jahresbericht DMV 30:92. Abstract of talk, extended version in (Weyl, 1968, II, 212–228), erroneously identical with Weyl (1922a). 11 Weyl, Hermann. 1921b. “Zur Infinitesimalgeometrie: Einordnung der projektiven und der konfor- men Auffassung.” Nachrichten Göttinger Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften pp. 99–112. In (Weyl, 1968, II, 195–207). 9, 11, 12, 13, 24, 26 Weyl, Hermann. 1922a. “Das Raumproblem.” Jahresbericht DMV 31:205–221. In (Weyl, 1968, II, 328–344). 11, 56 Weyl, Hermann. 1922b. Space – Time – Matter. Translated from the 4th German edition by H. Brose. London: Methuen. Reprint New York: Dover 1952. 6, 9, 10, 11 Weyl, Hermann. 1923a. Mathematische Analyse des Raumproblems. Vorlesungen gehalten in Barcelona und Madrid. Berlin etc.: Springer. Nachdruck Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchge- sellschaft 1963. 11 Weyl, Hermann. 1923b. Raum - Zeit -Materie, 5. Auflage. Berlin: Springer. 9, 10, 11, 19, 33 Weyl, Hermann. 1927. Philosophie der Mathematik und Naturwissenschaft. München: Oldenbourg. In (Baeumler, 1927, Bd. II A); separat. Weitere Auflagen 21949, 31966. English with comments and appendices Weyl (1949a), French Weyl (2017). 14 Weyl, Hermann. 1928. Gruppentheorie und Quantenmechanik. Leipzig: Hirzel. 21931, English translation R.P. Robertson, New York: Dutten 1931. 13 Weyl, Hermann. 1929. “Elektron und Gravitation.” Zeitschrift für Physik 56:330–352. In (Weyl, 1968, III, 245–267) [85]. English in (O’Raifeartaigh, 1997, 121–144). 16 Weyl, Hermann. 1931. “Geometrie und Physik.” Die Naturwissenschaften 19:49–58. Rouse Ball Lecture Cambridge, May 1930. In (Weyl, 1968, III, 336–345). 14 Weyl, Hermann. 1949a. Philosophy of Mathematics and Natural Science. Princeton: University Press. 21950, 32009. 14, 56 Weyl, Hermann. 1955. Symmetrie. Ins Deutsche übersetzt von Lulu Bechtolsheim. Basel/Berlin etc.: Birkhäuser/Springer. 21981, 3. Auflage 2017: Ergänzt durch einen Text aus dem Nachlass ‘Symmetry and congruence’, und mit Kommentaren von D. Giulini, E. Scholz und K. Volkert. 56 Weyl, Hermann. 1968. Gesammelte Abhandlungen, 4 vols. Ed. K. Chandrasekharan. Berlin etc.: Springer. 55, 56 Weyl, Hermann. 2017. Philosophie des mathématiques et des sciences de la nature. Traduit de l’anglais par Carlos Lobo. Genève: MétisPresses. 56 Weyl, Hermann. 2017/1949b. “Similarity and congruence: a chapter in the epistemology of sci- ence.”. ETH Bibliothek, Hs 91a:31. Published in (Weyl, 1955, 3rd edition, 153–166). 15 Woodhouse, N.M.J. 1991. Geometric Quantization. Oxford: Clarendon. 28 Yuan, Fang-Fan; Huang, Yong-Chang. 2013. “A modified variational principle for gravity in Weyl geometry.” Classical and Quantum Gravity 30(19):195008. arXiv:1301.1316. 9, 30

56