Robert Brandom and Bounded Posthumanism David Roden
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Mind Body Problem and Brandom's Analytic Pragmatism
The Mind-Body Problem and Brandom’s Analytic Pragmatism François-Igor Pris [email protected] Erfurt University (Nordhäuserstraße 63, 99089 Erfurt, Germany) Abstract. I propose to solve the hard problem in the philosophy of mind by means of Brandom‟s notion of the pragmatically mediated semantic relation. The explanatory gap between a phenomenal concept and the corresponding theoretical concept is a gap in the pragmatically mediated semantic relation between them. It is closed if we do not neglect the pragmatics. 1 Introduction In the second section, I will formulate the hard problem. In the third section, I will describe a pragmatic approach to the problem and propose to replace the classical non-normative physicalism/naturalism with a normative physicalism/naturalism of Wittgensteinian language games. In subsection 3.1, I will give a definition of a normative naturalism. In subsection 3.2, I will make some suggestions concerning an analytic interpretation of the second philosophy of Wittgenstein. In the fourth section, I will propose a solution to the hard problem within Brandom‟s analytic pragmatism by using the notion of the pragmatically mediated semantic relation. In the fifth section, I will make some suggestions about possible combinatorics related to pragmatically mediated semantic relations. In the sixth section, I will consider pragmatic and discursive versions of the mind-body identity M=B. In the last section, I will conclude that the explanatory gap is a gap in a pragmatically mediated semantic relation between B and M. It is closed if we do not neglect pragmatics. 2 The Hard Problem The hard problem in the philosophy of mind can be formulated as follows. -
Drafting the Inhuman: Conjectures on Capitalism and Organic Necrocracy
13 Drafting the Inhuman: Conjectures on Capitalism and Organic Necrocracy Reza Negarestani ‘And beyond all this we have yet to disturb the peace of this world in still another way..’. 1 Quod exitus sectabor iter? With the burgeoning popularity of speculative thought, it is becoming more evident that what is labelled as ‘speculative’ is more an epiphenomenon of the inquisitive re- negotiation of human faculties, their limits and vulnerabilities rather, than a counter- intuitive foray into the abyssal vistas unlocked by contemporary science. Accordingly, in the more extreme forms of speculative thought, political intervention and political analysis have been curtailed or at least have been temporarily suspended. This is be- cause the horizon of agency (of emancipation or intervention), ontological privileges and conditions of experience are precisely those ingredients of political thought which are under the process of critical interrogation. Yet strangely, it seems that speculative thought has not given up remarking on capitalism—this hypothetical mathesis uni- versalis of politico-economic problems—even in some of its most apolitical moments.2 For the purpose of understanding some of the disjunctive impasses between specula- tive thought and politics as well as possibilities for mobilizing a politics capable of us- ing the resources of speculative thought, this essay will concentrate its energy on the most recurring politico-economic figure of speculative thought: Capitalism. To do so, we shall, in proceeding steps, dissect the uncanny affinities between contemporary capitalism’s insinuations of an inhuman politics and speculative thought’s assault on the human’s ‘empirically overdetermined set of cognitive faculties impose[d] upon the speculative imagination’.3 We shall subsequently investigate the lines of correspond- 1. -
Durham E-Theses
Durham E-Theses Understanding, normativity, and scientic practice LEWENDON-EVANS, HARRY,EDWARD How to cite: LEWENDON-EVANS, HARRY,EDWARD (2018) Understanding, normativity, and scientic practice, Durham theses, Durham University. Available at Durham E-Theses Online: http://etheses.dur.ac.uk/12780/ Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-prot purposes provided that: • a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • a link is made to the metadata record in Durham E-Theses • the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Please consult the full Durham E-Theses policy for further details. Academic Support Oce, Durham University, University Oce, Old Elvet, Durham DH1 3HP e-mail: [email protected] Tel: +44 0191 334 6107 http://etheses.dur.ac.uk Understanding, Normativity, and Scientific Practice Harry Lewendon-Evans PhD Thesis Department of Philosophy Durham University 2018 Abstract Understanding, Normativity, and Scientific Practice Harry Lewendon-Evans Recent work in epistemology and philosophy of science has argued that understanding is an important cognitive achievement that philosophers should seek to address for its own sake. This thesis outlines and defends a new account of scientific understanding that analyses the concept of understanding in terms of the concept of normativity. The central claim is that to understand means to grasp something in the light of norms. -
5 Holism and Animal Minds
WML05 12/20/2006 6:36 PM Page 251 5 Holism and Animal Minds David Finkelstein 1 It’s not unusual for influential philosophers to make statements about the minds of nonlinguistic creatures that to a nonphilosopher would seem not merely implausible, but plainly and obviously false. For example, in his Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, Richard Rorty (1979, 187) defends the claim “that knowledge, awareness, concepts, . all descend on the shoulders of the bright child somewhere around the age of four, without having existed in even the most primitive form hitherto.” According to Rorty, a creature without language—whether human or nonhuman—is not aware of any- thing, and, contrary to what you might imagine when he climbs into bed with you each night, your dog has never once even noticed you. In arguing for this thesis, Rorty takes himself to be following the lead of Wilfrid Sellars. He quotes approvingly a passage from “Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind” in which Sellars (1997, 63) describes his own position as one “according to which all awareness of sorts, resemblances, facts, etc., in short all awareness of abstract entities—indeed, all awareness even of particulars—is a linguistic affair.” According to Rorty, Sellars finds an innocent way to allow that brutes may be said to enjoy a kind of awareness. As Rorty (1979, 182) reads him, Sellars distinguishes “between aware- ness-as-discriminative behavior and awareness as . being ‘in the logical space of reasons, of justifying what one says.’” He goes on: “Awareness in the first sense is manifested by rats and amoebas and computers; it is simply reliable signaling. -
Reza Negarestani – Glass Bead – 2017 1 Three Nightmares of The
Reza Negarestani – Glass Bead – 2017 1 Three Nightmares of the Inductive Mind Of all the disquieting riddles and paradoxes found in the arsenal of epistemological scepticism— understood as a systematic and piecemeal scrutiny into the methods and paradigms of the formation and justification of knowledge-claims—one problem has particularly proved, time and again, to be a never- ending source of cognitive vexation. With few notable exceptions, philosophers and philosophically- minded scientists and statisticians (e.g., Hume, Goodman, Putnam, Stegmüller, Boltzmann and De Finetti among others) have invariably either downplayed and deflected the seriousness of this problem and its variations, or have simply given up worrying about it in the hope that it may miraculously disappear. The said problem is nothing but David Hume’s strong version of the problem of induction which, unbeknownst to Hume himself, was destined to become the superacid of methodological scepticism capable, in the blink of an eye, of eating away the foundation of any epistemic project built on naïve forms of empiricism and rationalism. It is often the case that philosophers who pose sceptical problems recoil in fear once they realize the far- reaching implications of such problems, and Hume, with his problem of induction, is no exception. They rush into defusing their inadvertent exercise in scepticism. But systematic scepticism is something akin to an explosive chemical chain reaction. Once it is set off, with every passing minute it becomes more difficult to extinguish the flames. Pour on more water, and the fire spreads to areas you never imagined flammable. A genuine philosopher—regardless of her alliances—seeks to examine how far the fire spreads. -
Review Article Spirit in the Crypt Negarestani Vs Land
Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy, vol. 15, no. 1, 2019 REVIEW ARTICLE SPIRIT IN THE CRYPT NEGARESTANI VS LAND Vincent Le ABSTRACT: Iranian philosopher Reza Negarestani’s first 2008 book Cyclonopedia was written under the influence of Nick Land’s nihilistic and antihumanist philosophy which seeks to critique anthropomorphism by confronting us with our coming extinction beyond which our concepts of reason cannot reach. Since Cyclonopedia’s publication, however, Negarestani has left behind Landian nihilism to develop in his 2018 book Intelligence and Spirit a neorationalist philosophy of mind whose primary influences are Sellars, Brandom, and Hegel. At 579 clearly written yet dense pages, it is difficult even for a review article to encapsulate the book in its entirety. The first half of this article instead aims to provide a sense of the book’s overall project by focusing on how Negarestani outlines and develops his neorationalist philosophy through a critique of Land’s antihumanism. Never one to remain silent whilst others seek to resurrect Hegel from the dead, since December 2018, Land has been releasing a draft on his blog Urban Futures 2.1 of his new monograph Crypto- Current: Bitcoin and Philosophy, which proffers the most up to date articulation of his main antihumanist tenets. Having organized Intelligence and Spirit around Negarestani’s objections to Land, this article’s second half turns to Crypto-Current to see how Land is able to provide convincing responses to each of Negarestani’s objections, showing some to be based on strawman characterizations, others to stem from misunderstandings of Land’s position, and still others to lack traction at all. -
The Education of Kanzi and the Notion of Progress: Reza Negarestani's Intelligence and Spirit
Pli 30 (2019), 164-190 The Education of Kanzi and the Notion of Progress: Reza Negarestani’s Intelligence and Spirit BENJAMIN NORRIS I. Published a decade after his philo-fictional extravaganza Cyclonopedia: Complicity with Anonymous Materials,1 Reza Negarestani’s Intelligence and Spirit draws upon a wide range resources, philosophical and otherwise, in an attempt to ‘think a thought as grand as the universe itself’ as Ken Lui once framed the task placed upon any finite, intelligent species ‘worthy of the name’.2 More precisely, Negarestani describes ‘intelligence’ in such a way that its capability of thinking a thought this grand (one that transcends space, time and death itself) is rendered explicit. In order to accomplish 1 Reza Negarestani, Cyclonopedia: Complicity with Anonymous Materials (Mel- bourne: re-press, 2008). 2 ‘The universe is full of echoes and shadows, the after images and last words of dead civilizations that have lost the struggle against entropy. Fading ripples in the cosmic background radiation, it is doubtful if most, or any, of these messages will ever be de- ciphered. Likewise, most of our thoughts and memories are destined to fade, to disap- pear, to be consumed by the very act of choosing and living. That is not cause for sor- row, sweetheart. It is the fate of every species to disappear into the void that is the heat death of the universe. But long before then, the thoughts of any intelligent spe- cies worthy of the name will become as grand as the universe itself’. Ken Liu, ‘An Advanced Readers’ Picture Book of Comparative Cognition’ in The Paper Menagerie and Other Stories (New York: Saga Press, 2016), pp. -
Inferential Man: an Interview with Robert Brandom Jeffrey J
Inferential Man: An Interview with Robert Brandom Jeffrey J. Williams, Robert Brandom symploke, Volume 21, Numbers 1-2, 2013, pp. 367-391 (Article) Published by University of Nebraska Press For additional information about this article https://muse.jhu.edu/article/532830 [ This content has been declared free to read by the pubisher during the COVID-19 pandemic. ] INFERENTIAL MAN: AN INTERVIEW WITH ROBERT BRANDOM JEFFREY J. WILLIAMS Analytic philosophy, at least to those in literary studies, seems an arid pursuit focused on technical problems of language, often conveyed in the mathematical symbols of formal logic. However, just as literary theory is quite different from common portraits of it, analytic philosophy differs from such images and has changed considerably since the days of Rudolph Carnap. Robert Brandom is an analytic philosopher, but while following in its rationalist tradition, he argues for a revisionary perspective, holding that we obtain meaning through inference rather than reference to a state of affairs. And rather than the compartmentalized arguments of much analytic philosophy, often captured in a single essay, he has aimed to construct a systematic philosophy, notably in his 741-page book, Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment (Harvard UP, 1994). Another aspect of his revisionary stance is bringing several unlikely bedfellows, such as pragmatism and Hegel, into his version of analytic philosophy. Instead of disregarding the history of philosophy, he frequently evokes “the mighty dead.” Before he published Making It Explicit, Brandom gained a reputation from articles, unpublished papers, and talks as part of the “Pittsburgh School” of philosophy, which included colleagues Wilfrid Sellars, John McDowell, and others. -
The Pragmatic Century
The Pragmatic Century Richard J. Bernstein There are many ways of telling the story of the vicissitudes of pragmatism in the United States. I want to begin with a brief account of what may be considered the standard story, because I intend to challenge it. The stan- dard story goes something like this. Pragmatism was popularized primar- ily through the lecturing and writing of William James at the beginning of the twentieth century. We can even date the explicit introduction of the term “pragmatism” by James in his 1898 address, delivered at the Univer- sity of California, Berkeley, “Philosophical Conceptions and Practical Results.” In that address, James generously acknowledged his debt to Peirce, “one of the most original contemporary thinkers,” and he refers to “the principle of practicalism—or pragmatism as he called it, when I first heard him enunciate it at Cambridge in the early 1970s.” James initially gives a rather metaphorical description of “Peirce’s principle”: “the soul and meaning of thought, he says, can never be made to direct itself towards anything but the production of belief, belief being the demica- dence which closes a musical phrase in the symphony of our intellectual life.” Furthermore, “beliefs, in short are really rules of action; and the whole function of thinking is but one step in the production of habits of action” (James 1967: 348). In 1898, Peirce was barely known as a philoso- pher (except to a small group of admirers like James). As James’s popular version of pragmatism spread, Peirce was so appalled and outraged that he renamed his own doctrine of meaning “‘pragmaticism,’ which is ugly enough to be safe from kidnappers” (Peirce 1931: 5.414). -
Alleys of Your Mind: Augmented Intelligence and Its Traumas Its and Intelligence Augmented Your Mind: of Alleys (Ed.) Pasquinelli Matteo INTELLIGENCE
AUGMENTED Matteo Pasquinelli (Ed.) INTELLIGENCE Alleys of Mind: Your Augmented Intelligence and Its Traumas TRAUMAS PASQUINELLI Alleys of Your Mind Alleys of Your Mind: Augmented Intelligence and Its Traumas edited by Matteo Pasquinelli Bibliographical Information of the German National Library The German National Library lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliografie(GermanNationalBibliography);detailed bibliographic information is available online at http://dnb.d-nb.de. Published by meson press, Hybrid Publishing Lab, Centre for Digital Cultures, Leuphana University of Lüneburg www.meson-press.com Design concept: Torsten Köchlin, Silke Krieg Cover image: Michael Deistler Copy-editing: Jacob Watson The print edition of this book is printed by Lightning Source, Milton Keynes, United Kingdom. ISBN(Print):978-3-95796-065-8 ISBN(PDF): 978-3-95796-066-5 ISBN(EPUB): 978-3-95796-067-2 DOI:10.14619/014 The digital editions of this publication can be downloaded freely at: www.meson-press.com FundedbytheEUmajorprojectInnovationIncubatorLüneburg ThisPublicationislicensedundertheCC-BY-SA4.0(CreativeCommons AttributionShareAlike4.0Unported)license.Toviewacopyofthislicense, visit: http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/4.0/. Please note that the pictures used in the text by Orit Halpern are not cov- eredbythislicense:p.45,Serious Games I–IV©2009–2010HarunFarocki; p.57,AspenMovieMap,©1978–1979MIT;p.60,The Architecture Machine, ©1970MITPress;p.62,Softwareexhibitioncatalogue,©1970Jewish -
Some Strands of Wittgenstein's Normative Pragmatism, and Some
Some Strands of Wittgenstein’s Normative Pragmatism, and Some Strains of his Semantic Nihilism ROBERT B. BRANDOM §1. Strands of Normative Pragmatism FIRST READ THE TRIUMVIRATE of classical American pragmatists as an I undergraduate, under the tutelage of Bruce Kuklick. He saw them as instituting a vibrant philosophical tradition that was visibly continued not only by C. I. Lewis, but by his students Goodman and Quine. (More controversially, but I believe, also correctly, he further saw the semantic holism Quine shared with Sellars as picking up a central strand of the idealist tradition —represented in the Golden Age by Lewis’s teacher Josiah Royce— with which pragmatism had always been in conversation.) My Doktorvater Richard Rorty then made familiar to me an understanding of pragmatism sufficiently capacious to include such disparate and reciprocally unsympathetic philosophers as the early Heidegger and the later Wittgenstein, as well as Sellars, and Quine’s student Davidson. I came to think of pragmatism as a house with many mansions, comprising a number of more or less closely related but distinct and separable commitments, relating various thinkers in the way Wittgenstein made famous under the rubric of “family resemblances.” Excavating the conceptual antecedents of those various pragmatist views led me to see some of the most central among them as rooted firmly in the thought of the German Idealists, Kant and Hegel —as Peirce and Dewey had explicitly avowed1. Among the most important of these antecedents is a thought that I take it serves as a fundamental orienting insight for the later Wittgenstein. This is the idea that intentionality is through and through a normative phenomenon. -
What Is Inferentialism? Jaroslav Peregrin Institute of Philosophy, Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic & Faculty of Philosophy, University of Hradec Králové
What is inferentialism? Jaroslav Peregrin Institute of Philosophy, Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic & Faculty of Philosophy, University of Hradec Králové Inferentialism and Representationalism Inferentialism is the conviction that to be meaningful in the distinctively human way, or to have a 'conceptual content', is to be governed by a certain kind of inferential rules. The term was coined by Robert Brandom as a label for his theory of language; however, it is also naturally applicable (and is growing increasingly common) within the philosophy of logic1. The rationale for articulating inferentialism as a fully-fledged standpoint is to emphasize its distinctness from the more traditional representationalism. The tradition of basing semantics on (such or another variant of) the concept of representation is long and rich. (Note that what is in question is representationalist semantics, viz. the idea that linguistic meaning is essentially a matter of representation; not a general thesis about the role of representations within the realm of the mental.) The basic representationalist picture is: we are confronted with things (or other entities) and somehow make our words stand for them (individual philosophers vary, of course, about what is to be understood by stand for). Within this paradigm, the ‘essential’ words of our language are meaningful in so far as they represent, or stand for, something, and if there are other kinds of words, then their function is auxiliary: they may help compose complex representations etc. Many philosophers of the twentieth century took some form of representationalism for granted, seeing no viable alternative basis for semantics; others had more specific reasons for entertaining one or another form of it2.