Spinoza's Rejection of Teleology

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Spinoza's Rejection of Teleology SPINOZA’S REJECTION OF TELEOLOGY * EDWARD ANDREW GREETIS 1. INTRODUCTION Bennett, that Spinoza is consistent in his rejection of teleology. My argument will consist of two eleology is a highly contested topic in main parts. First, I argue that Lin misinterprets Spinoza scholarship. Spinoza’s discussion Spinoza by showing that his argument against of teleology, which comes in Appendix 1 Bennett is mistaken. Second, I aim to show that T Bennett is incorrect in claiming that Spinoza is of the ETHICS, appears to be a brutal assault on the concept. At one point, he even states that caught in an inconsistency; I argue that Spinoza “all final causes are nothing but human not only rejects all teleology but consistently does inventions.” 1 Nevertheless, many commentators, so, i.e., I argue for a nonteleological reading of such as Martin Lin, argue that Spinoza is conatus. committed to and employs teleological explanations of human action—the discussion 2. WHY SPINOZA REJECTS TELEOLOGY: BENNETT’S in Appendix 1 is merely an assault on divine ARGUMENT teleology, i.e., the notion that God had objectives in mind when creating the universe. On the other One of Spinoza’s objections against final hand, Jonathan Bennett argues that Appendix 1 causation in Appendix 1 is that it “completely is an argument against all final causation; overturns nature,” that is, “that which is prior in moreover, the metaphysics and philosophy of nature it makes posterior.” To borrow Bennett’s mind in the ETHICS show that Spinoza is analogy, teleology explains causes in terms of committed to a rejection of all teleological “pulls” (something subsequent in time explaining explanations. Bennett concedes, however, that something prior) instead of “pushes,” i.e., this exposes an inconsistency in the ETHICS: efficient cause determinism where, if A efficiently Spinoza argues against, and is committed to, a causes B, then B follows from A. Spinoza is rejection of all teleological explanations, but his arguing here that teleology is incompatible with concept of conatus, or endeavoring, which is the the efficient cause determinism, which he basis of his moral philosophy and psychology, is prescribes. used to explain human action teleologically. Some teleological explanations, however, Contrary to Bennett’s arguments, Lin seem to be tenable in a world of only efficient holds that not only is Spinoza not committed to causes. Consider the following: an idea a rejection of teleological explanations of human representing a future goal, or (i) causes an action action, his account of mental content actually (a). This is an efficiently caused event, which commits him to such explanations. In what can be explained teleologically. Although follows, I argue, contra Lin, that Spinoza is Spinoza would find this event untenable because committed to a rejection of teleology, and contra his system does not allow thought and extension—two, of the infinitely many, distinct * I am currently affiliated with San Diego State University where I work on Spinoza, philosophy of science, and attributes of substance, or God—to interact, we epistemology. My current projects involve Spinoza’s theory can modify the explanation to work. Spinoza’s of causation, especially his views on teleology. parallelism doctrine holds that the order and 1 I use G. H. R. Parkinson’s translation of the ETHICS, connection of ideas is the same as the order and unless otherwise noted. REVISTA Conatus - FILOSOFIA DE SPINOZA - VOLUME 4 - NÚMERO 8 - DEZEMBRO 2010 25 GREETIS, EDWARD ANDREW. SPINOZA’S REJECTION OF TELEOLOGY. P. 25-35. connection of things (E2P7).2 Thus, for every mode parallel. Thus, the causal powers of ideas cannot of thought, there is a parallel mode of extension— depend on the representational content of there is only one substance for Spinoza, so thought ideas—which represent the future goals or external and extension are merely ways of considering the objects involved in the teleological explanations in same substance. So (i) could not cause (a), but (i) question—because representational content is an could cause the idea parallel to (a), and, since the extrinsic property of ideas. Bennett clarifies the order and connection is the same for ideas and concepts of intrinsic and extrinsic properties of matter, (a) would be caused by the physical parallel ideas by comparing them to a page with ink on of (i). Spinoza’s parallelism therefore does not rule it. The page represents a map of Sussex. out this kind of teleological explanation. However, what the page and the person Bennett, nevertheless, contends that examining the page are intrinsically like conjures Spinoza also rejects this kind of teleological the thought “this is a map of Sussex,” not what explanation. Spinoza’s formulation of “appetite” the map indirectly represents5—if the intrinsic and much of Part 3 of the ETHICS is explicable properties did not change, the thought “this is a only if he is attempting to avoid letting anything map of Sussex” would be the same even if Sussex subsequent to x explain x (Bennett, 1984: 217). never existed (Bennett, 1984: 219). Lin further For example, Spinoza’s formulations of appetite elucidates why representational content is an and desire are nonteleological, and Bennett extrinsic property of ideas by likening extrinsic claims, and I agree, that it is an attempt to replace properties with causal histories.6 He asks us to the standard Scholastic teleological conceptions imagine a thing and its perfect duplicate; they of, among other things, will, appetite, and desire. both have a scratch on them (what they share is Spinoza writes in E4Def7: “by the end for the intrinsic to them), but the original was scratched sake of which we do something I understand by an external object last July, so they each have appetite,” and in E3P2S: “the decrees of the mind different causal histories, which is extrinsic to are simply appetites themselves.” And desire is them. In short, intrinsic properties are those simply “appetite together with a consciousness properties a thing has regardless of its relations of the appetite” (E3P9S). Appetite and desire to other things, while extrinsic properties are are further identified with the actual essence of relational properties—properties a thing has a thing (E3P7 and E3P9S). Moreover, some of solely in virtue of its relation to other things.7 Spinoza’s tenets require a rejection of the kind 5 of teleological explanation in question. Bennett uses “indirect representation” to indicate that 3 it is the content of the idea that represents objects external In the ‘short physical treatise ’ in Part 2 to us. The reason he adds “indirect” is because trivially, of the ETHICS, it is evident that the causal powers ideas represent body states due to Spinoza’s parallelism. of bodies rely only on size, shape, motion and This “representation,” however, simply means that the rest, etc., or intrinsic properties.4 Likewise, the idea is parallel to a body state. The idea parallel to a body causal powers of ideas rely only on intrinsic state will include properties other than representations of external objects (including, among other things, properties—recall that thought and extension are passions; the mind’s ideas retain a certain ratio of motion 2 By “order and connection,” Spinoza means that every and rest identical to the body’s ratio, which explains why cause and effect is numerically identical in both thought the mind is a composite, individual idea of the body; and and extension (Spinoza adheres to a rationalist causal each individual idea will be a parallel of an affection of the theory so causation is logical deduction: if A causes B, then body, meaning that the motion and rest, position, etc., of a B follows logically from A). That is, if body A causes B, body must have an idea parallel to it). These are the intrinsic then the idea parallel to A causes the idea parallel to B. properties of an idea. Although ideas represent, or parallel, 3 This treatise is found between E2P13 and P14. bodies, ideas also contain representations of external objects 4 Bennett translates Spinoza’s term “formaliter” as and intrinsic properties. I will use the term “represent” as “intrinsic” and claims that it is the inherent features of a synonymous with the content of an idea. thing. As we will see shortly, he compares intrinsic with 6 Bennett compares representative features with causal extrinsic, or representative features of an idea, i.e., the history as well, but I will provide Lin’s elucidation. content or meaning of an idea. I will explain “intrinsic” 7 It may be objected that on this account of “intrinsic,” and “representative” shortly. Here, his point is that motion and rest, direction, etc., are not intrinsic. representative features are not causally relevant in However, we can see why motion and rest, direction, etc., Spinoza’s discussion in the short physical treatise. are intrinsic properties by imagining an x,(TO BE CONTINUED) 26 REVISTA Conatus - FILOSOFIA DE SPINOZA - VOLUME 4 - NÚMERO 8 - DEZEMBRO 2010 GREETIS, EDWARD ANDREW. SPINOZA’S REJECTION OF TELEOLOGY. P. 25-35. Lin summarizes Bennett’s argument as that passions themselves are widely individuated follows: by citing E4P33, where Spinoza claims that there 1. The causal powers of bodies depend on intrinsic are “as many species of each emotion as there properties such as size, shape, and motion. are species of objects by which we are affected.” In other words, Lin claims, passions are 2. There is a parallelism between bodies and their individuated by their external causes. Spinoza properties and relations on the one hand and seems to provide further support for this claim ideas and their properties on the other. (E2P7) in E3P56Dem. In the demonstration, he argues that we are only acted on—passively affected— 3.
Recommended publications
  • Teleology and the Concepts of Causation
    Philosophica, 46 (2), 17–43, 1990. 128 Teleology and the Concepts of Causation he term ‘teleology’ was coined by the philosopher Christian Wolff in his Latin T treatise of 1728 and he defined it as indicating the part of natural philosophy that explains the ends, or purposes, of things.1 It has been used to describe a prominent feature of the theological views of Thomas Aquinas and the metaphysics of Aristotle. Some forty years ago, it was adopted by the founder of cybernetics to characterize a mechanism designed, among other things, to steer missiles to their target. Since the instrumental purpose of artificial devices would seem to belong to a domain that is somewhat different from the metaphysical purposes of Nature and its components, it is reasonable to suspect that the term has shifted its meaning and become ambiguous. Where ambiguities remain hidden, all kinds of nonsense can be generated. In the present essay, I argue that the problem with ‘teleology’ goes back to one of the four ‘explanatory principles’ that resulted from Aristotle’s examination of what we now call causation. After a brief survey of the contemporary uneasiness about teleology I present an exposition of Aristotle’s classification of causes, suggesting that modern science has been somewhat cavalier in dismissing all but one of the four. I suggest that an adequate analysis of the concept of efficient cause opens a way to showing that the notion of final cause, usually condemned as ‘teleological’, is in fact twofold and that one of its components does not at all infringe the accepted rules of science.
    [Show full text]
  • The Shortcomings of a Concept Inertia and Conatus in the Philosophy of Spinoza
    http://dx.doi.org/10.18778/8142-286-4.36 Alexandre Rouette Université du Québec à Trois-Rivières, Canada THE SHORTCOMINGS OF A CONCEPT INERTIA AND CONATUS IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA n the third part of the Ethics, Spinoza express the desire to talk about “human actions and appetites just as if it were a question of lines, planes, and bodies” (E3, Appendix).1 With this sentence, it seems clear that Spinoza sides with Hobbes and Descartes and that he wants to con- struct a mechanistic theory of the affects. In the same part of the Ethics, Spinoza also introduces the concept of conatus: “Each thing, as far as it can by its own power, strives to persevere in its being” (E3P6), Spinoza says. One will immedi- ately understand this concept of conatus as the core concept of his mechanistic theory of the affects, the concept without which this mechanistic account of the affects would be impossible. However, in the second part of the Ethics, there is another concept that could have accomplished that same goal, namely, the principle of inertia. In the words of Spinoza, “A body which moves or is at rest must be determined to motion or rest by another body, which has also been determined to motion or rest by another, and that again by another, and so on, to infinity” (E2L3). Inter- estingly enough, in the philosophy of Hobbes, the concept of endeavour/conatus is much nearer to the Spinozistic principle of inertia in its meaning than it is to the Spinozistic version of the conatus.
    [Show full text]
  • SPINOZA's ETHICS: FREEDOM and DETERMINISM by Alfredo Lucero
    SPINOZA’S ETHICS: FREEDOM AND DETERMINISM by Alfredo Lucero-Montaño 1. What remains alive of a philosopher's thought are the realities that concern him, the problems that he addresses, as well as the questions that he poses. The breath and depth of a philosopher's thought is what continues to excite and incite today. However, his answers are limited to his time and circumstances, and these are subject to the historical evolution of thought, yet his principal commitments are based on the problems and questions with which he is concerned. And this is what resounds of a philosopher's thought, which we can theoretically and practically adopt and adapt. Spinoza is immersed in a time of reforms, and he is a revolutionary and a reformer himself. The reforming trend in modern philosophy is expressed in an eminent way by Descartes' philosophy. Descartes, the great restorer of science and metaphysics, had left unfinished the task of a new foundation of ethics. Spinoza was thus faced with this enterprise. But he couldn't carry it out without the conviction of the importance of the ethical problems or that ethics is involved in a fundamental aspect of existence: the moral destiny of man. Spinoza's Ethics[1] is based on a theory of man or, more precisely, on an ontology of man. Ethics is, for him, ontology. He does not approach the problems of morality — the nature of good and evil, why and wherefore of human life — if it is not on the basis of a conception of man's being-in-itself, to wit, that the moral existence of man can only be explained by its own condition.
    [Show full text]
  • Descartes' Optics
    Descartes’ Optics Jeffrey K. McDonough Descartes’ work on optics spanned his entire career and represents a fascinating area of inquiry. His interest in the study of light is already on display in an intriguing study of refraction from his early notebook, known as the Cogitationes privatae, dating from 1619 to 1621 (AT X 242-3). Optics figures centrally in Descartes’ The World, or Treatise on Light, written between 1629 and 1633, as well as, of course, in his Dioptrics published in 1637. It also, however, plays important roles in the three essays published together with the Dioptrics, namely, the Discourse on Method, the Geometry, and the Meteorology, and many of Descartes’ conclusions concerning light from these earlier works persist with little substantive modification into the Principles of Philosophy published in 1644. In what follows, we will look in a brief and general way at Descartes’ understanding of light, his derivations of the two central laws of geometrical optics, and a sampling of the optical phenomena he sought to explain. We will conclude by noting a few of the many ways in which Descartes’ efforts in optics prompted – both through agreement and dissent – further developments in the history of optics. Descartes was a famously systematic philosopher and his thinking about optics is deeply enmeshed with his more general mechanistic physics and cosmology. In the sixth chapter of The Treatise on Light, he asks his readers to imagine a new world “very easy to know, but nevertheless similar to ours” consisting of an indefinite space filled everywhere with “real, perfectly solid” matter, divisible “into as many parts and shapes as we can imagine” (AT XI ix; G 21, fn 40) (AT XI 33-34; G 22-23).
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter Four T H E P L a C E O F T H E G O O D in Aristotle's Natural Teleology
    Chapter Four The Place of the Good in Aristotle's Natural Teleology by Allan Gotthelf In previous writings I have offered an interpretation of Aristotle's conception of final causality in terms of his conception of an "irreducible potential for form."1 I have argued that final causality is operative in nature, and teleological explanation thus appropriate, only when there is being actualized a potential for a complex organic outcome which is not ontologically reducible to a sum of actualizations of potentials of the organ- ism's elemental constituents. At no place in this analysis do I refer to the goodness of that complex organic outcome.2 Some recent writers have suggested that the absence of any reference to goodness in the analysis of Aristotelian ends is a mistake. Thus, one of the most influential recent discussions of teleological explanation, John Cooper's 1982 Owen Festschrift paper, "Aristotle on Natural Teleology," begins as follows: Aristotle believed that many (not, of course, all) natural events and facts need to be explained by reference to natural goals. He understands by a goal (ov evexa) whether natural or not, something good (from some point of view) that something else causes or makes possible, where this other thing exists or hap- pens (at least in part) because of that good. Copyright © 1988 Allan Gotthelf. Revised from the paper read November 19, 1987, at Clark University, as part of the Tenth Annual Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy. 1. Gotthelf 1976/77, reprinted with a long "Postscript 1986" as Gotthelf 1987a. Cf. Gotthelf 1980, 19876.
    [Show full text]
  • ARISTOTLE's TELEOLOGY and Uexk1tll's THEORY of LIVING NATURE
    ARISTOTLE'S TELEOLOGY AND UEXK1tLL'S THEORY OF LIVING NATURE THE purpose of this paper is to draw attention to a similarity between an ancient and a modern theory of living nature. There is no need to present the Aristotelian doctrine in full detail. I must rather apologize for repeating much that is well known. My endeavour is to offer it for comparison, and, incidentally, to clear it from misrepre- sentation. Uexkiill's theory, on the other hand, is little known, and what is given here is an insufficient outline of it. I do not maintain that either doctrine is right. I am fully aware that the problem of the essence of living nature by no means admits of an easy solution.' In offering for consideration the comparison contained in this paper I would go no farther than owning my belief that the two authors here discussed, both thinkers who combine an intensely philosophical outlook with a wide biological experience, are worth the attention not only of the historian of science and philosophy, but also of the student of philosophical biology. One of the various meanings which dv'at bears for Aristotle is that of a cause. In the second book of his Physics, as is well known, he investigates the philosophical character of that cause. The result is what we are accustomed to call his teleology. He maintains that not only rpoalpacr~sbut also dv'c is rTwvEIEKL r'tov alrlwv.2 This teaching has exercised a deep influence, especially throughout the Middle Ages. It has subsequently been discarded, especially since modern science established its mechanistic outlook on nature, which is strictly opposed to teleological explana- tions.
    [Show full text]
  • TELEOLOGY and DIALECTIC Introduction
    CHAPTER FIVE TELEOLOGY AND DIALECTIC Introduction: Teleology and Natural Science We have seen how Marx addresses several issues in the philosophy of science on his way to constructing his research principles which, in turn, lead him to theoretical conclusions. Several issues he addresses are shared with natural science, including conceptualizing variables, looking for their interrelations, and accounting for causal dynamics. Teleological explanation is one philosophy of science category that directs attention toward the temporal relationship between variables and their causal properties. In this chapter, I inquire into the logic of teleological explanation in natural and social science and how Marx’s approach addresses this issue as well as its political implications. Teleological reasoning comes up in the works of classical philoso- phers, Christian theologians, and modern philosophers of science. As expressed by Aristotle and Kant, teleological arguments depict things as existing or coming to exist because of the purpose or role they play in the world.1 It is a seductive way of thinking. Th ings are here because of what they do for us and/or for other things. Teleological reason, however, at its traditional rudimentary level at least, does not go beyond speculative reason as it simply rests on argument, not on test- able empirical demonstration. As these sorts of explanations are sub- ject to misleading us, we need to clarify teleology’s logic and root out 1 “Philosophers as divergent in their perspectives as Aristotle and Kant have
    [Show full text]
  • Cognitive Biases Explain Religious Belief, Paranormal Belief, and Belief in Life’S Purpose ⇑ Aiyana K
    Cognition 129 (2013) 379–391 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Cognition journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/COGNIT Cognitive biases explain religious belief, paranormal belief, and belief in life’s purpose ⇑ Aiyana K. Willard , Ara Norenzayan 1 Department of Psychology, The University of British Columbia, 2136 West Mall, Vancouver, BC V6T 1Z4, Canada article info abstract Article history: Cognitive theories of religion have postulated several cognitive biases that predispose Received 4 March 2013 human minds towards religious belief. However, to date, these hypotheses have not been Revised 25 July 2013 tested simultaneously and in relation to each other, using an individual difference Accepted 27 July 2013 approach. We used a path model to assess the extent to which several interacting cognitive tendencies, namely mentalizing, mind body dualism, teleological thinking, and anthropo- morphism, as well as cultural exposure to religion, predict belief in God, paranormal beliefs Keywords: and belief in life’s purpose. Our model, based on two independent samples (N = 492 and Religion N = 920) found that the previously known relationship between mentalizing and belief is Cognitive biases Paranormal belief mediated by individual differences in dualism, and to a lesser extent by teleological think- Purpose ing. Anthropomorphism was unrelated to religious belief, but was related to paranormal belief. Cultural exposure to religion (mostly Christianity) was negatively related to anthro- pomorphism, and was unrelated to any of the other cognitive tendencies. These patterns were robust for both men and women, and across at least two ethnic identifications. The data were most consistent with a path model suggesting that mentalizing comes first, which leads to dualism and teleology, which in turn lead to religious, paranormal, and life’s-purpose beliefs.
    [Show full text]
  • CG Jung and the Inheritance of Immanence
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Middle Tennessee State University: Journals@MTSU C. G. Jung and the Inheritance of Immanence C.G. Jung and the Inheritance of Immanence: Traces of Spinozistic, Nietzschean, and Freudian Influence in Analytical Psychology Christopher Myers Abstract Carl Jung, the founder of analytical psychology, was heavily influenced by both Nietzsche and Freud, both of whom were influenced, as Yovel notes in his The Adventures of Immanence, by Spinoza. Through his years of collaboration with Freud and his long-lasting fascination with Nietzsche (combined with Jung’s own semi-mystical tendencies, Jung became more of a Spinozian, than Nietzschean or Freudian. These Spinozistic traces can be detected in the framework of analytical psychology. A comparison is presented on the views of Spinoza, Nietzsche, Freud, and Jung on historical religion, the source of human motivation, and the liberating power of self- knowledge. Middle Tennessee State University 69 Scientia et Humanitas: A Journal of Student Research his investigation explores the intellectual genealogy that links seventeenth-cen- tury rationalist and Jewish ex-communicant, Baruch Spinoza, to the founder of analyticalT psychology, Carl Gustav Jung. In Spinoza and Other Heretics: The Adventures of Immanence, Yirmiyahu Yovel describes Spinoza’s influence upon Nietzsche and Freud. In Philosophical Issues in the Psychology of C.G. Jung, Marilyn Nagy investigates the inspiration of Plato, Kant, Schopenhauer and others on Jung. However, no effort has been made to in- vestigate the possibility that Spinozism might have trickled into Jungian thought through Nietzsche and Freud.
    [Show full text]
  • The Curious Case of Baruch Spinoza in Walter Ben­Ja­Min’S “Toward the Critique of Violence”
    The Curious Case of Baruch Spinoza in Walter Ben ja min’s “Toward the Critique of Violence” MASSIMO PALMA abstract Although Baruch Spinoza was im por tant for think ers of his gen er a tion, Walter Ben ja­ min seems to have com pletely ig nored the phi los o pher. Spinoza’s name ap pears just a few times in Ben ja min’s works, and Spinoza’s thought never seems to have been rel e vant to him. The only place where Ben ja min quotes a text of Spinoza’s, al beit be tween the lines, is in “Toward the Critique of Violence” (1921). Still, in this essay Ben ja min is far from enthu si as tic about the au thor of the Ethics. He names Spinoza as a pro po nent of nat u ral law the o ry, which Ben ja min dismisses in his search for a cri te rion with which to judge Gewalt. This ar ti cle seeks to in ves ti gate Ben ja min’s ap par ent hos til ity to Spinoza and to reexamine the re la tion ship be tween the two, from both a the o ret i cal and a po lit i cal per spec tive. keywords Walter Ben ja min, Baruch Spinoza, le gal vi o lence, nat u ral law, mi gra tion The names of Walter Ben ja min and Baruch Spinoza rarely ap pear along side one an other in the lit er a ture on Ben ja min.
    [Show full text]
  • The Relation Between Conception and Causation in Spinoza's
    Philosophers’ volume 13, no. 3 1. Introduction Imprint february 2013 If you asked a contemporary metaphysician to list her foundational, unanalyzed notions, she might say: possibility, object and part. Or per- haps: grounding, bundle and point. If you asked Spinoza, conception and causation would be at the top of his list. He uses these notions to THE RELATION state many of his most important doctrines, including necessitarianism and substance monism, as well as to define several of his key terms, in- cluding ‘mode’ and ‘action’. A correct understanding of the relation BETWEEN between conception and causation is therefore an essential part of our understanding of Spinoza’s metaphysics. There are many different ways of understanding this relation. For example: Curley [3, p.40, 74–5] identifies conception and causation, be- CONCEPTION AND cause he thinks that they are just different ways of talking about logical dependence; Della Rocca [5, p.44] also identifies conception and cau- sation but does not assimilate them to logical dependence; and New- CAUSATION IN lands [17, p.469] suggests that causation is reducible to conception. Un- derpinning all of these interpretations is what I will call the orthodox view. I wish to challenge this view. SPINOZA'S The orthodox view is grounded in the fourth axiom of part one, 1A4, of the Ethics. It reads: “Cognition of an effect depends on, and involves, cognition of its cause.”1 Given the way that Spinoza uses ‘involves’ and METAPHYSICS ‘conceived through’, this axiom uncontroversially entails:2 causation ! conception If one thing causes another thing, then the second thing is conceived John Morrison through the first thing.
    [Show full text]
  • Spinoza's Ethics Beth Lord
    EDINBURGH PHILOSOPHICAL GUIDES Spinoza's Ethics Beth Lord Spinoza’s Ethics Edinburgh Philosophical Guides Series Titles in the series include: Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason Douglas Burnham with Harvey Young Derrida’s Of Grammatology Arthur Bradley Heidegger’s Being and Time William Large Plato’s Republic D. J. Sheppard Spinoza’s Ethics Beth Lord Descartes’ Meditations on First Philosophy Kurt Brandhorst Husserl’s The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology Katrin Joost Nietzsche’s Thus Spoke Zarathustra Martin Jesinghausen and Douglas Burnham Spinoza’s Ethics An Edinburgh Philosophical Guide Beth Lord Edinburgh University Press © Beth Lord, 2010 Edinburgh University Press Ltd 22 George Square, Edinburgh www.euppublishing.com Typeset in 11/13pt Monotype Baskerville by Servis Filmsetting Ltd, Stockport, Cheshire, and printed and bound in Great Britain by CPI Antony Rowe, Chippenham and Eastbourne A CIP record for this book is available from the British Library ISBN 978 0 7486 3449 1 (hardback) ISBN 978 0 7486 3450 7 (paperback) The right of Beth Lord to be identifi ed as author of this work has been asserted in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. Contents Series Editor’s Preface vi Acknowledgements vii List of Figures viii Introduction 1 1. A Guide to the Text 15 Part I: Being, Substance, God, Nature 15 Part II: Minds, Bodies, Experience and Knowledge 49 Part III: The Affects 83 Part IV: Virtue, Ethics and Politics 103 Part V: Freedom and Eternity 136 2. Study Aids 159 Glossary 159 Further Reading 167 Types of Question you will Encounter 168 Tips for Writing about Spinoza 169 Bibliography 173 Index 179 Series Editor’s Preface To us, the principle of this series of books is clear and simple: what readers new to philosophical classics need fi rst and foremost is help with reading these key texts.
    [Show full text]