<<

© Copyrighted Material

15 m o .c te a g h s .a w w w Motherhood and : Constructing m o .c te a g h s and Challenging Normativitya . w w w

m 1 o Susan B. Boyd .c te a g h s .a w w w

m o .c te a g h An extensive explores how law interacts withs the social institution of .a w motherhood and with the ideological frameworks that contributew to women’s oppression w

m in western, liberal states. This chapter’s main concern is witho feminist theories about law’s .c te role in relation to motherhood, which reflects both coercivea and ideological aspects. That g h s is, women can be coerced into normative ideals of motherhood.a and penalized for failure to w w conform, but women can also ‘consent’ or choose to conformw to ideological norms, raising

m o far more complex questions for feminists and for feminist.c legal strategy. The chapter also te a explores the degree to which law and feminist legalg strategies reinforce and/or challenge h s .a dominant ideologies of motherhood, which are wrooted in the histories of race, class, gender w w and sexuality. m o .c Another theme of this chapter is the differentialte impact of legal , depending a g h on whether a is working class or smiddle class, racialized or non-racialized, lesbian .a w or straight, disabled or able-bodied, andw so on. All women can be detrimentally affected w

m by dominant legal norms, but womeno who depart from normative white, middle-class, .c te heterosexual motherhood are likelya to be scrutinized more heavily and treated more g h s coercively than those who are able.a to conform. The question of law’s differential impact w w on women whose social locationw differs from this standard also poses important questions

m o about feminist legal strategies,.c including whether they lapse into essentialist or ‘maternalist’ te a g modes of analysis. h s .a This chapter proceeds won the premise that motherhood is socially constructed through w w the interaction of complex structures and ideologies. The first part explains this process and m o .c is then followed by twote illustrative case studies on and . The risk a g h of essentialism is takens up in the next part on legal strategy. The last part of the chapter .a w uses examples of ‘transgressivew motherhood’ to suggest future directions for feminist legal w

m theory and concludeso with questions that continue to challenge feminist legal engagement .c te with motherhood.a g h s .a w w w

m o .c te a g h s .a w w w

1 Thanks to my SSHRC-funded research team on ‘autonomous motherhood’, Dorothy Chunn,

Fiona Kelly and Wanda Wiegers, for comments on an earlier draft and to Vanessa Munro and Margaret Davies for their graceful editorial work.

© Copyrighted Material The Ashgate Research Companion to

© Copyrighted Material The Social Construction of Motherhood: Law’s Ideological Role m o .c te a g h Despite women’s biological potential to conceive, gestate, give birth and lactate, ‘[m]otherhoods .a w is not a natural condition’ (Smart 1996: 37). Numerous feminist scholars havew shown w

institution m how the of motherhood is socially constructed in different historicalo periods, .c te yet is presented ideologically as a natural consequence of biological differencesa between g h s women and men. Indeed, in their review of feminist approaches to motherhood,.a Katherine w w O’Donovan and Jill Marshall (2006: 107) found that social construction is thew most common

m o approach within second wave ’s analysis of motherhood. Adrienne.c Rich (1976) is te a often credited as the first feminist to have presented a scholarly analysisg of motherhood as h s .a an institution and to deconstruct the notion of an inherent maternal winstinct. Motherhood, w w mothering, and family structures are all shaped by social, economic and cultural contexts, m o which in turn are framed by the interlocking structures of gender,.c race, class and sexuality. te a g h As Martha Fineman puts it, motherhood is a colonized concept,s something physically .a w occupied and experienced by women, but defined, controlled,w and given legal content by w

m patriarchal ideology (1995: 38). o .c te Early feminist treatments of motherhood often drew ona materialist feminist approaches g h s to the family within capitalist , including the.a work of sociologists and political w w economists about the (hetero)sexual division of labourw within both public and private

m o spheres that developed within the context of industrial.c capitalism (Boyd 1997). For instance, te a Michèle Barrett and Mary McIntosh (1982) showedg that the traditional, nuclear, ‘anti-social’ h s .a or privatized family plays a particular role withinw capitalism as a socio-economic institution w w and an ideology. Among other things, the family provides ‘free’ reproductive labour by m o .c women in relation to the care of children andte workers which, in turn, allows productive a g h labour to be pursued on the assumption thats the ‘private’ sphere of family is handling care .a w work. Feminist historians have shown thatw as fathers became increasingly linked with the w

m public world of paid work in the nineteentho and twentieth centuries, and children became .c te an economic cost to families, mothersa were constructed as the ‘divinely appointed guardians g h s of the family’ (Backhouse 1981: 239)..a Ironically, this idealized and deeply gendered role for w w did not necessarily translatew into legal in relation to children (Boyd 2003).

m o These structural insights about.c the material basis for motherhood have been adopted by te a many authors (see, for example,g Fineman 1995), often combined with attention to the role h s .a of ideology. w w w The concept of ideology has been deployed to refer to the ways in which law both m o .c constructs and normalizeste a set of ideas about motherhood, often distracting attention away a g h from its material roots.s This concept has facilitated an increasingly complex understanding .a w of law’s roles in thew social construction of motherhood. The notion of ideology also assists w

m in understandingo the dynamics through which women are regulated by law across and .c te through theira differences and, specifically, how mothers are constructed as ‘good’ or g h s ‘bad’, depending.a on their adherence to the expectations of the ‘normative mother’ (Boyd w w 1996, Finemanw 1995, Kline 1993). Marlee Kline evocatively summarized the significance of

m o ideology.c in the regulation of motherhood and highlighted its relationship to traditional te a familyg structures during a period of proliferation of literature on the ideology of motherhood h s .a (see,w for example, Fineman and Karpin 1995). w w

By the dominant ideology of motherhood, I mean the constellation of ideas and images in western capitalist societies that constitute the dominant ideals of motherhood

© Copyrighted Material 268 Motherhood and Law

© Copyrighted Material against which women’s lives are judged. The expectations established by these ideals m o .c limit and shape the choices women make in their lives, and construct the dominant te a g h criteria of “good” and “bad” mothering. They exist within a framework of dominant s .a w ideologies of motherhood, which, in turn, intersect with dominant ideologies of family.w w

m (Kline 1993: 310) o .c te a g h s The key normative expectations associated with the ideology of motherhood.a are that (1) w w a must be a mother before she will be considered a proper adult woman,w thus tying

m o motherhood with ; (2) a ‘good’ mother will be selflessly available.c to her children, te a taking primary care of them; (3) a ‘good’ mother will do so in the contextg of a heterosexual, h s .a nuclear family model premised on privatized female dependence andw domesticity. These w w expectations may shift over time and even countenance working mothers (Boyd 2003, m o .c Murphy 1998), but those who deviate may still be constructed aste unfit, which in turn can a g h compromise their legal ties with their children. At best, motherss may ‘win’ a legal claim, .a w but in a manner that reproduces oppressive dominant normsw about women and mothers. w

m For instance, arguments from both prosecution and defenceo in relation to mothers who .c te are charged with murdering their infants often reinforcea dominant norms of motherhood g h s (Cunliffe 2011). Whereas the prosecution typically attempts.a to portray the woman as a bad w w mother because she departs from those norms, the defencew offers of the woman’s

m o conformity with maternal ideals. .c te a The requirement that mothers behave selflesslyg in relation to children in their primary h s .a care has important consequences, not least by limitingw their ability to take up paid work. As w w well, mothers’ rights are often constructed in opposition to the rights of their children, which m o .c may undermine ‘the fundamental bond thatt eexists between most mothers and their children’ a g h (Murphy 1998: 691). This oppositional treatments of mothers and children is manifested .a w particularly in relation to child protectionw law, where women can be defined as failing to w

m adequately protect their children eveno if the risk to the child is generated by other factors, .c te such as poverty (Kline 1993). Even amore acute are situations where a pregnant woman is g h s positioned as a risk to the health of.a her fetus (Diduck 1993). w w This example illustrates that wlaw is not the only institution that reproduces the ideology

m o of motherhood through its .c discursive power: ‘discourses such as feminism, modern te a rationality, science, social workg and psychology’ interact with law ‘in a kind of shifting h s .a hierarchy’ and also ‘are imbuedw with such factors as race, class and sexuality’ (Diduck 1993: w w 462). In combination with other professional discourses, such as science or medicine or m o .c psychiatry, law can bete particularly powerful in scrutinizing maternal conduct, particularly a g h in relation to child protections and criminal law (Cunliffe 2011, Diduck 1993, Raitt and Zeedyk .a w 2004). For example,w state removal of children from mothers labelled as mentally ill reflects w

m processes througho which on mental health and child protection interact with the power .c te of the psychiatrica paradigm (Langer 2009, Mosoff 1997). In these processes, the ideology of g h s motherhood.a can facilitate law’s coercive aspect. w w Mothersw who are already marginalized, notably as a result of poverty, race or

m o aboriginality,.c are most vulnerable to being labelled ‘unfit’. For instance, due to the te a g correlationh between race and poverty in the United States, which has a high percentage s .a of poorw Black families headed by women, a particularly pathological representation of w w Black single motherhood prevails: ‘Ideologically, in America, single motherhood is Black’

(Roberts 1993b: 25). Single and African-American mothers have been demonized in poverty and child welfare discourses, the mainstream solution often being a patriarchal

© Copyrighted Material 269 The Ashgate Research Companion to Feminist Legal Theory

© Copyrighted Material one of locating absent fathers and returning them to the family, particularly to make a m o financial contribution (Fineman 1995). .c te a g h Child protection disputes between a parent and state authorities graphically reveals the .a w ways in which poverty and race are implicated in the regulation of motherhood. wModern w

m child protection relies on the assessment of risk, based on a belief in othe ability .c te to predict future harm to children. As Karen Swift (2010) has shown, the ideologya of risk g h s can distort and deflect attention away from the relations of race, class and. a gender that are w w structured into child welfare processes, stripping them of their ideological wbaggage. Single

m o mothers especially are constructed as a ‘risk class’, ‘who can legitimately .bec intruded upon, te a scrutinized indefinitely and held to account for their daily activities’ (Sgwift 2010: 143). The h s .a experience of aboriginal mothers in Canada’s child welfare systemw similarly highlights w w a history of colonialist and racist processes of regulation of indigenous families and yet m o simultaneously erases this history through the application of the .bestc interests of the child te a g h standard (Kline 1993). Whether actual harm to children is effectivelys prevented through .a w these intrusive regulatory processes is questionable. w w

m As these examples suggest, it is not only individual motherso who may be deemed to .c te have fallen short of ideological expectations; rather, entirea groups of women may be judged g h s as unfit for motherhood based on their social location. a (Kline 1993: 312–313). Moreover, as w w the historical antecedents of the ideology of motherhoodw (including highly problematic

m o race and class-based eugenics-derived birth control .cdiscourses) have faded, its roots and its te a problematic impact on some groups of women areg rendered invisible so that the construct h s .a of the ‘bad mother’ is presented as unbiased or ‘innocent’.w w w That said, the normative frameworks surrounding motherhood are not static but shift m o .c in form and content through history and acrosste cultures. The legal system has been one a g h key way in which those norms have beens communicated and reinforced and, sometimes, .a w challenged. For example, although procreationw by contemporary Black mothers is often w

m devalued and discouraged, at earlier pointso in American history, procreation by Black slave .c te women was desirable, albeit for problematica reasons (Roberts 1993b: 7–10). Their children g h s replenished the master’s supply . ofa slaves, yet slave mothers were deprived of any legal w w claim to their children. Althoughw this severing of maternal ties was eventually abolished,

m o parallels have been drawn with.c the modern system of state intervention in the homes of te a Black mothers, who are moreg likely to be under scrutiny and have their children removed h s .a (Murphy 1998: 708, Robertsw 1993b: 13–15). w w In addition to shifts in ideological frameworks, women’s experiences of motherhood can m o .c vary widely. These variationste may correlate to the interaction of factors such as class, race, a g h sexuality and immigrations , but also to women’s different approaches to motherhood, .a w including some women’sw resistance to normative expectations or to the experience of w

m motherhood altogethero (Arendell 2000). A mother’s definition of her own experience may .c te differ radicallya from the socio-legal construction of her mothering. For example, an ‘unwed g h s Black teenager.a … may experience motherhood as a rare source of self-affirmation, while w w society deemsw her motherhood to be illegitimate and deviant’ (Roberts 1993b: 4).

m o Class.c too plays a key role in mediating the operation of the ideology of motherhood. te a Middleg class women are exhorted to be stay-at-home mothers and criticized for engaging h s .a in workw outside the home, but single mothers and the working poor receive contradictory w w messages; they might be expected to take paid work to avoid unemployment and being

categorized as lazy, yet still be criticized for taking paid work (Gavigan and Chunn 2007: 749). As well, paid domestic or care work, too often performed by racialized, ‘othered’

© Copyrighted Material 270 Motherhood and Law

© Copyrighted Material women who may well be mothers themselves, and based on exploitative conditions, enables m o .c middle- and high-income mothers to mediate the contradictions between paid work andte the a g h conventional expectations of motherhood (Blackett 2011). Poor, racialized mothers sin the .a w United States have been caught in impossible situations under policies of no-fault evictionsw w

m from public housing based on drug-related activity by their children, where motherso are .c te held responsible for their children in circumstances offering them little materiala ability to g h s rectify the problem (Austin 2002). .a w w The social construction of motherhood is also related to concepts of men andw masculinity,

m o fatherhood, gender, heteronormativity, and the division of labour (Smart. cand Sevenhuijsen te a 1989). On the one hand, motherhood is held up as the ultimate definitiong of what it means h s .a to be a woman; on the other hand, for women who do not become mothersw in the expected w w context, motherhood can be discouraged (Kline 1993). Even lesbian mothers, parenting m o .c intentionally outside the heterosexual mainstream, can be measuredte against (potentially a g h contradictory) expectations that children should have fathers or sthat lesbian mothers should .a w adhere to a nuclear family model (Kelly 2011). w w

m Even as traditionalist ideologies on patriarchal authorityo within the family dissipated .c te in the late twentieth century and women entered the laboura force in increasing numbers, g h s dominant norms about motherhood were still reinforced.a in much popular culture and in w w the media, generating difficulties for individual women.w Women continue to be expected

m o to provide care for children and others, yet these. c expectations of ‘domesticity’ generate te a economic dependency in most mothers (Williamsg 2000). With the costs of ‘inevitable h s .a dependency’ being privatized within the family,w and with women typically being allocated w w the burden of caring for inevitable dependency, a ‘derivative dependency’ arises in m o .c mother/caretakers (Fineman 1995: 161–164).te Mothers become economically dependent on a g h either a wage-earning partner or on (diminishing)s state assistance. This dependency is not .a w necessarily resolved when mothers participatew in the workforce, where they tend to earn w

m less money than other women and fathers,o even controlling for the that they work fewer .c te hours due to the demands of their carea responsibilities: ‘being a mother is incompatible with g h s being an ideal worker’ (Becker 2002:.a 68). The depression in mothers’ wages is lifelong, as are w w its consequences, including povertyw among elderly women (Crittenden 2001).

m o Because ideological expectations.c have shifted over time, any clear dichotomy between te a good and bad mothers is g now difficult to sustain. Ideological frameworks have been h s .a complicated as equality hasw become a dominant norm, as fathers have been expected to w w participate more fully in the lives of their children (Boyd 2003) and as mothers are expected m o .c to be responsible markette citizens (Gavigan and Chunn 2007). The rise of gender symmetry in a g h relation to legal parenthoods must, however, be contrasted with the ongoing disproportionate .a w responsibility thatw women still bear for child care, and the extent to which ‘mother work’ has w

m been rendered invisibleo in the face of legal trends promoting paternal rights (Fineman 1995). .c te Two case studiesa on criminal law and family law will next serve to illustrate the shifting g h s nature of the.a social construction of motherhood. w w w

m o .c te a g Caseh Study: Criminalizing Mothers s .a w w w The ‘bad’ or ‘unfit’ mother is a powerful, yet over-simplified figure in Western lawand

literature, which identify her ‘as the woman whose neglectful, abusive, reckless, or murderous behavior threatens or destroys her children’ (Ashe and Cahn 1993: 80). Dorothy

© Copyrighted Material 271 The Ashgate Research Companion to Feminist Legal Theory

© Copyrighted Material Roberts (1993a) suggests that women’s criminal conduct can often be explained through a m o focus on their refusal to mother or failure to care properly for their children; these mothers.c te a g h are penalized largely for their violation of gender norms and studying them illuminatess the .a w mechanisms through which the institution of motherhood confines women and wpunishes w

m them if they resist. The criminal law both contributes to the construction of dominanto norms .c te of motherhood and reveals the complexities of women’s struggle against a ‘self-annihilatinga g h s role’ under which she must take on any risk to ensure her child’s safety (Roberts.a 1993a: 96, w w 100). For instance, the punishment of mothers who fail to protect their childrenw from abuse

m o by a male partner holds women, often battered themselves, responsible .cfor violence in the te a family and enforces the notion that mothers must be selfless. Marie Asheg and Naomi Cahn h s .a (1993) argue for more contextualized accounts that counter portrayalsw of bad mothers as w w either autonomous, fully responsible evildoers or helpless victims. m o Law coercively reinforced the notion that motherhood is an .c inevitable by-product of te a g h heterosexual activity by criminalizing women’s efforts to controls their reproductive lives .a w through the use of contraceptives and abortion (Smart 1996). wEven once the coercive aspect w

m of criminal law prohibitions are removed in relation, say, oto abortion, women’s struggles .c te to retain control over pregnancy and access to abortion servicesa continue (Gavigan 1992), g h s illustrating the intersection between law and other normative.a frameworks such as medicine. w w Racialized differences can also be identifiedw in struggles for women’s reproductive

m o autonomy: whereas white, middle class women have.c historically concerned themselves te a primarily with contesting criminal laws that restrictg their ability to choose not to become h s .a pregnant, such as contraception or abortion, poorw women of colour are often more concerned w w with challenging restrictions that constrain their choices to procreate in a healthy, supported m o .c manner, including coercive measures such aste sterilization (Roberts 1993b: 32–33). a g h More complex are the laws on maternals neonaticide. ‘Draconican’ seventeenth-century .a w English laws on infanticide, later adoptedw in Canada, regulated women’s sexuality w

m by applying only to unmarried mothers,o working with a presumption of guilt and .c te imposing capital punishment (Smarta 1996: 43). often refused to convict, however, g h s acknowledging the lack of alternatives.a facing many women (see also Backhouse 1984). In w w the face of this juror leniency, lesserw offences such as concealment were added as a way to

m o secure convictions. In the twentieth.c century, sex-specific offences were introduced in some te a jurisdictions, with a focus ong a mother’s failure to fully recover from the effects of childbirth h s .a or lactation and a disturbancew to the balance of her mind. Some (see, for example, Smart w w 1996) see this modern incarnation as a medical-legal category that constructs women’s m o .c ‘deviance’ in bio-psychologicalte terms rather than in relation to socio-economic difficulties a g h facing women. Otherss challenge the notion that infanticide law straightforwardly reflects .a w the medicalizationw of women’s or the construction of ‘bad’ mothers. Based in part w

m on the fact that oCanadian law created a separate offence rather than England’s mitigation .c te approach, Kirstena Johnson Kramar (2005) argues that this law recognized women’s unique g h s experiences .aof pregnancy and childbirth, including socio-economic hardship. w w Since thew early 1990s, a moral panic has arisen and the medical-legal system has taken

m o a more .c punitive approach to mothers whose children die. This harsher approach must te a be understoodg against the backdrop of women’s attainment of formal legal equality and h s .a enhancedw , which inculcate a notion that women must be reproductively w w responsible for their actions in relation to newborns, who have become ‘wholly deserving

victim[s]’ (Kramar 2005: 14). Indeed, a combination of adversarial legal processes, erroneous representations of relevant medical knowledge, and deviation from some normative

© Copyrighted Material 272 Motherhood and Law

© Copyrighted Material expectations of motherhood likely combined to generate a wrongful conviction of an m o .c Australian mother for murdering her infants (Cunliffe 2011). Kathleen Folbigg was a competentte a g h mother, but her occasional resistance to mothering overshadowed the positive indicia.s .a w Fiona Raitt and Suzanne Zeedyk (2004) similarly link wrongful convictions to assumptionsw w

m that murderous mothers can be identified through their standard of childcareo and their .c te emotional reactions to children’s death or illness. They also suggest that contemporarya legal g h s cases of unexplained infant deaths are haunted by the spectre of a diagnosis of.a Munchausen w w Syndrome by Proxy, under which mothers are suspected of deliberately causingw harm to

m o their children in order to gain attention. Mothers who are suspected of .criminalc behaviour te a may well be subjected to more rigid standards (Cunliffe 2011: 203–204),g with a ‘retributive h s .a impulse’ towards women labelled as ‘bad’ mothers (Langer 2009: 218).w w w

m o .c te a g h Case Study: Law s .a w w w

m Child custody law exemplifies the use of ideology to analyse ao field that some view asprivileging .c te motherhood and also illustrates the relational nature of thea ideology of motherhood with g h s other ideologies, for example on fatherhood. Mothers have.a been constructed as the favoured w w darlings of the law when engaged in disputes overw their children. However, whereas a

m o mother who conforms to the ideological expectations.c of the middle class, heterosexual, stay- te a at-home mother might be favoured in an ,g her sister who, say, works outside the h s .a home and delegates aspects of her child’s care tow another might be viewed as a less worthy w w candidate because she selfishly placed her own interests above those of the child (Boyd 2003, m o .c Mason 1999, Murphy 1998). In some periods,te mothers who betrayed their marriage vows by a g h adulterous conduct or, worse still, for lesbians relationships, were assessed as unsuitable for .a w custody. w w

m By reading a child’s best interests againsto the mother’s degree of conformity to ideological .c te norms, the legal system reinforcesa dominant expectations of mothers both in situations g h s where a mother ‘wins’ custody and.a where she ‘loses’. While this ideology quite clearly w w operates against the interests of womenw who fail to conform to it and has a particular impact

m o on women whose mothering .isc viewed as marginal or threatening to dominant norms (for te a example, lesbian mothers), itg by no means privileges in any absolute manner women who h s .a appear to conform by being,w say, heterosexual or able-bodied. Even when a form of maternal w w presumption dominated the legal system, it was easy for a woman to fall from grace (Boyd m o .c 2003: 41–101, Murphyte 1998: 695). The ideology of motherhood structures and therefore a g h limits the lives of alls women: any woman who appears at a given time to conform to the .a w norms can lapse andw lose a privileged status. This insight challenges any efforts to draw w

m stark contrasts betweeno ‘good’ and ‘bad’ mothers in reality, as opposed to ideology, and .c te illustrates the adisciplining effects of ideological norms on all mothers (Boyd 1996). g h s Child custody.a law also reveals the dilemmas of feminist inspired law reform. The w w apparentlyw progressive move to emphasize a child’s best interests rather than parental

m o conduct. c or assumptions about maternal care produced negative consequences for many te a g mothers.h The late twentieth-century focus on and no-fault s .a renderedw less visible the social and economic forces that reinforce women’s responsibility w w for children (Boyd 2003, Fineman 1995, Mason 1999). Moreover, the rise of fathers’ rights

advocacy was embedded in this formal equality approach to parenthood, contributing to the trend towards ‘gender symmetry’. As a result, the language of maternal care became

© Copyrighted Material 273 The Ashgate Research Companion to Feminist Legal Theory

© Copyrighted Material discredited, depriving women of a legitimate voice with which to express their experience m o of caring for children. Fineman coined the term ‘the neutered mother’ to denote the multiple.c te a g h ways in which the concept of Mother has been taken out of context by being de-gendered,s .a w de-raced and de-classed (1995: 67). Although the dominance of the ideology of motherhoodw w

m in earlier periods did not empower mothers as such, instead reinforcing an image ofo mothers .c te as selfless, pure, full-time carers of children within the heterosexuala nuclear family, the g h s resonance of this norm lost its power in law near the end of the twentieth century,.a as mother w w love became an increasingly ‘exhausted script’ (Smart 1991: 486) and claimsw of ‘father love’

m o and fathers’ rights prevailed. .c te a Carol Smart’s empirical work revealed that mothers more often expressg their taken-for- h s .a granted caregiving responsibility for children as ‘caring for’, whereasw fathers talk about w w ‘caring about’ (loving) children, which ‘can produce a sentimental rush of concern and can be m o instrumental in producing legislative reforms’ (1991: 489). The evolving.c family law system te a g h values ‘caring about’ above ‘caring for’ in the moral register, meanings that fathers’ claims .a w are heard positively while mothers’ claims appear self-interested.w Moreover, mothers who w

m fail to facilitate paternal with children after divorceo have become identified as bad .c te or vindictive mothers, giving birth to the image of the ‘noa contact mother’, whose anxieties g h s about contact are read as selfishness (Rhoades 2002). Being.a a ‘bad’ mother was never really w w about a mother’s relationship with her child, but ratherw about her conduct in relation to

m o norms about family; now an important aspect of a mother’s.c role is her responsibility to foster te a a child’s relationship with a father. g h s .a Having explored the social construction of motherhoodw and the role of ideology in legal w w processes, the next section turns to questions of feminist legal strategy. m o .c te a g h s .a w Legal Strategy: Reinforcing orw Challenging w

m the Ideology of Motherhood?o .c te a g h s Feminists have debated whether .feminista legal strategies reinforce or challenge dominant w w ideologies of motherhood. To thew extent that legal arguments emphasize the uneven playing

m o field between mothers and.c fathers, notably, women’s ongoing responsibility for careof te a children and related economicg difficulties, the ideology of motherhood can be reinforced, h s .a producing negative repercussionsw for mothers who cannot meet the normative model w w (see, for example, Kline 1993, Mosoff 1997). This strategic impulse can also be charged m o .c with essentialism andte ‘fix[ing] women as second-class citizens in a patriarchal structure’ a g h (Mason 1999: 15). Thats said, the history of feminist engagement in this field illuminates .a w why feminists oftenw emphasize the specificity of motherhood rather than gender neutrality. w

m To the extent thato this strategy is rooted in an appreciation of the social construction of .c te motherhood asa embedded in stubbornly entrenched socio-economic structures, it can be g h s viewed as realist.a rather than essentialist. Nevertheless, negative or unintended consequences w w can be identified.w

m o Many.c nineteenth- and early twentieth-century feminists embraced a maternal feminism te a that correlatedg motherhood with a special capacity for nurturing, but this approach was h s .a largelyw rejected in the campaigns for equal rights in the 1960s and 1970s (Fineman 1995: w w 36–37, 77). The that characterized the early second wave of the women’s

movement was optimistic about involving men as equal parents and moving mothers into the labour force. Gender-based assumptions related to parenthood should be eliminated and

© Copyrighted Material 274 Motherhood and Law

© Copyrighted Material men should behave more like women – by participating equally in child care in the ‘private’ m o .c sphere of the family. A common argument was that gender-specific statutory language,te a g h for instance, maternal presumptions in custody law, should be eliminated becauses they .a w reinforced assumptions that mothers should care for children and fathers need notw (Mason w

m 1999: 3). Some feminists favoured a joint custody norm for that reason, and otherso did so .c te because it might better take account of the fact that some women parent withina extended g h s networks and recognize that mothers are differently located according to factors.a such as race w w and class (Bartlett and Stack 1986). w

m o Optimism about eliminating sex roles through law reforms such as joint.c custody waned te a as feminists realized that significant social and economic forces impededg the equal sharing h s .a of parental responsibilities and any major shifts in the public/privatew divide (Boyd 1997). w w A substantive equality analysis emerged both to explain the apparent failure of formal m o .c equality and to argue for a more nuanced understanding of women’ste inequality in relation to a g h family and child care; an inequality that too often leads to povertys (Becker 2002). The sexual .a w division of labour prevails not only in heterosexual families,w but in workplace practices w

m favouring workers who are unimpeded by care responsibilities.o Feminists began to argue .c te more strenuously for jobs to be restructured to accommodatea mothers and for more systemic g h s changes to acknowledge the ‘derivative dependency’ of .amothers/caregivers (Fineman 1995). w w Rena Uviller recognized early on that the move towardsw equal custody rights for fathers

m o could result in equality with a vengeance against mothers:.c ‘under the guise of sex-neutrality, te a women who want their children may be at a distinctg disadvantage in custody disputes due h s .a to their inferior earning capacity and an enduringw social bias against working mothers’ w w (1978: 109). In addition, when the economic roles of mothers are considered, an (often false) m o .c assumption of equality quickly comes into playte based on a notion that women can compete a g h equally in the workplace. When applieds to both financial responsibilities such as child .a w support and child custody decisions, mothersw are placed in a bind: they are penalized in w

m child custody assessments for workingo outside the home and yet are expected to financially .c te provide on an equal basis for their childrena (Boyd 2003: 115–120, Murphy 1998). g h s In child custody law, a strategy.a focused around a primary care presumption emerged w w (see, for example, Mason 1999,w Smart and Sevenhuijsen 1989), with arguments for a

m o revamped maternal presumption.c being in the minority (Mason 1990–91, Uviller 1978). Under te a a primary care presumption,g the parent who was the primary caregiver in the past should h s .a obtain custody in contestedw cases, unless proven unfit, or if all other factors were equal. w w This ostensibly gender-neutral feminist focus on primary care has been the subject of much m o .c debate due to its potentialte to reinforce problematic assumptions about women’s essential a g h capacity for caregiving.s As Jane Murphy notes (1998: 692), ‘protecting children is often best .a w achieved by protectingw their caretaker parent – their mother’, but this strategy can reinforce w

m maternal stereotypes.o Proponents of the care presumption do not promote essentialism .c te per se, yet theira work can be read as buttressing the sexual division of labour because it g h s seeks acknowledgement.a of women’s more onerous responsibilities. Mary Anne Case (2001) w w even arguesw against policies such as enhanced support for caregivers from government or

m o employers,.c in part because increasing such benefits would generate more discrimination te a g againsth women in the labour force. Her proposed solution is a formal equality approach s .a to parentingw and services directed to children rather than parents. Others defend the care w w argument on the grounds that it is necessary to highlight a key source of women’s inequality

and is sometimes transgressive (e.g. Becker 2002, Kessler 2005).

© Copyrighted Material 275 The Ashgate Research Companion to Feminist Legal Theory

© Copyrighted Material Feminists who adopt a care approach can also be charged with failure to take account of m o differences related to race, sexuality, and class – overlooking differences among women.c as te a g h mothers and men as fathers. The primary care presumption is critiqued for its reinforcements .a w of maternal care within the nuclear family, its failure to recognize alternativew family w

m structures of care such as extended families, and its potential to permit challenges oto custody .c te claims by mothers with disabilities, given they can easily be cast as unfit or unablea to take g h s primary responsibility for care (see, for example, Mosoff 1997). The presumption.a can also w w be portrayed as regressive in comparison to liberal feminist and fathers’ rightists’w claims for

m o equal roles for men and women as parents. .c te a Fathers’ rights advocates have taken up the formal equality argumentg for equal treatment h s .a of mothers and fathers, suggesting that law is biased in favour of w mothers and rests on w w sexist stereotypes (Boyd 2003: 102–129). They have demanded legal presumptions of joint m o custody and, more recently, have successfully challenged laws related.c to the (sur)naming of te a g h children, which in turn is often based on whether a father is nameds by a mother on the birth .a w registration. As Hester Lessard (2004) demonstrates, the apparentlyw benign construction of w

m mothers and fathers as formally equal draws on a bio-genetico model of parenthood that .c te erases the deeply political and ideological nature of the legala ordering of parent–child, and g h s parent–parent relationships. .a w w Despite such insights, feminist approaches to motherhoodw have not had marked impact

m o on legal policy, perhaps because the arguments are.c complex and can be misunderstood te a as reinforcing gendered roles within the family. gIn many countries, shared parenting has h s .a won the day as the dominant normative framework,w with an attendant heteronormative w w emphasis on gender symmetry between fathers and mothers (Boyd 2010). That said, it is m o .c difficult to see what better strategy mightte have been pursued. Arguably, feminist discourse a g h in this field has been misunderstood in a sclimate that reflects a ‘backlash’ to social and legal .a w initiatives that appear to favour mothersw (Sheldon 2001). w

m The next section asks whether a focuso on transgressive mothering can enrich feminist .c te legal scholarship on motherhood. a g h s .a w w w

m o Transgressive Motherhood.c te a g h s .a We have seen that normativew expectations of mothers are tied to the notion that proper w w motherhood occurs within the context of the white, heterosexual, nuclear, middle class m o .c family and to gender teroles. Lively debates continue about how feminists should approach a g h motherhood. Legal s moves to encourage gender symmetry before socio-economic forces .a w enable it have beenw aptly critiqued (see, for example, Boyd 2003, Fineman 1995). Nevertheless w

m it is risky for feministso to be perceived as resisting men’s equal involvement with children or .c te to argue for maternala autonomy in fields where children’s interests are central (Boyd 2010). g h s Feminists.a who focus on care and motherhood have, however, importantly complicated w w liberal individualistw approaches to autonomy by emphasizing the nexus between

m o relationships.c and autonomy (Boyd 2010, Nedelsky 1989, O’Donovan and Marshall 2006). te a Specifically,g the care relationships between mothers and children enable children to become h s .a autonomousw persons. Yet, due to still powerful societal expectations that mothers will w w provide primary care and the strong sense of responsibility that many/most mothers feel

towards their children, child-rearing imposes significant material constraints on female autonomy. Women’s ‘pregnant embodiment’ (Young 1990) – their more continuous

© Copyrighted Material 276 Motherhood and Law

© Copyrighted Material physical experience in relation to children as a result of pregnancy, breastfeeding, and m o .c care responsibility – prevents them from being able to opt in and out of involvement withte a g h children as men can choose to do. Despite long-standing feminist calls for men tos share .a w parenting and for society to support work–life balance, this constraint remains entrenched.w w

m While care is not inevitably women’s work, the choices that most women make too embrace .c te motherhood, despite the disincentives (Becker 2002), imply ongoing gendered consequencesa g h s into the future. The challenge is how to recognize the gendered dynamics of.a care without w w overemphasizing heteronormative birth and genetic ties and ignoring thew significance of

m o social parenting and families of choice. .c te a Gender asymmetry persists in both the social realities of parenthoodg highlighted above h s .a and the social construction of genetic ties, and mothers are by no meansw favoured. Many w w feminists have cautioned about an increasing emphasis on the genetic tie (Lessard 2004), m o .c which seems to be invoked more easily in favour of legal fatherhood,te especially to enforce a g h financial obligations (Sheldon 2001), but also in other contexts.s Whereas in earlier periods, .a w mothers had exclusive rights and responsibilities in relationw to ‘illegitimate’ children w

m and fathers garnered legal rights mainly through marriageo to a birth mother, that degree .c te of maternal autonomy has been eroded (Smart and Sevenhuijsena 1989: 8–9). Although g h s reproductive technologies open opportunities to move.a beyond traditional notions of w w filiation and the two-parent hegemony, maternity remainsw a naturalized concept that too

m o often fuses genetic, gestational and caregiving roles.c (Mykitiuk 2001). As a result, maternal te a legal status tends to be accorded to women only if theyg fulfil both biological and behavioural h s .a requirements. For instance, a birth mother’s failurew to properly care for a child ‘denaturalizes’ w w her, rendering her unfit. Yet a lesbian non-biological co-mother is often not viewed as a legal m o .c parent, despite her care and intention (Kellyte 2011, Millbank 2008) even if she is a caregiver. a g h This part of the chapter explores whethers a focus on ‘transgressive motherhood’ can .a w disrupt the over-emphasis on genetic tiesw and imprisonment of many feminist conversations w

m about motherhood within tropes of o heteronormativity, including the notion that fathers .c te should be equal parents. Laura Kesslera (2005) argues that feminists have been overly g h s critical or pessimistic about the relationship.a between caregiving and women and notes that w w ‘transgressive caregiving’ can bew a form of political resistance, even a subversive practice.

m o This idea holds potential because.c it focuses on elements of resistance within a traditionally te a gendered terrain. Lessons cang be drawn from feminist work on women who transgress h s .a the normative ideals of motherhood,w for instance, lesbian, surrogate, Black, single and w w criminalized mothers. m o .c Lesbian motherhoodte clearly disrupts the focus on genetic ties, given that most lesbian a g h birth mothers rely ons sperm donors for conception, yet donors rarely act as social parents. .a w Very often, a lesbianw co-mother without a genetic tie assumes that role (Kelly 2011, Millbank w

m 2008). Lesbian o co-mothering also challenges any automatic connection between birth .c te mothers and primarya care, with empirical studies on lesbian mothers revealing a focus on g h s intentional and.a care relationships rather than genetic ties (see, for example, Kelly 2011). At a w w more generalw level, O’Donovan and Marshall suggest, drawing on Sara Ruddick (1989: 51)

m o that all women.c who choose to mother might be regarded as ‘adoptive’, in the sense that even te a g birth mothersh must make a commitment to protect, nurture and train a child after the act s .a of birthw (2006: 109). Given still strong expectations that birth mothers undertake mothering, w w they argue that the distinction between birthing and mothering must be more clearly drawn,

noting that it is even less acceptable now than it once was for an unmarried mother to ‘give

© Copyrighted Material 277 The Ashgate Research Companion to Feminist Legal Theory

© Copyrighted Material away’ her child. A distinction might accordingly be drawn between birthing labour and m o mothering, as well as sperm donation and parenting. .c te a g h The challenge is how to devise a system that recognizes care relationships and sunder .a w which donors are not automatically regarded as legal parents, unless intended, andw also to w

m recognize intended lesbian co-mothers. Ruthann Robson (1992) suggests that legal argumentso .c te in relation to (lesbian) motherhood can have a deeply problematic ‘domesticating’a effect and g h s that the very category of ‘mother’ as a legal category may domesticate lesbians.a under the w w power of law and restrict lesbian choice. Indeed, early innovative efforts tow use the idea of

m o functional parenthood to recognize lesbian mothers (see, for example, Polikoff.c 1990) often te a resulted in legal outcomes contrary to their original intention (Millbankg 2008). In other h s .a words, the transgressive potential of lesbian motherhood has been difficultw to translate in w w the legal realm. Both Fiona Kelly (2011) and Jenni Millbank (2008) propose reforms that rely m o on intentionality rather than functionality to ascribe legal parentage..c Presumptions of legal te a g h parenthood would be made upon the occurrence of certain events,s such as consent by a non- .a w birth mother to her partner’s attempt to conceive through assistedw conception. Consensual w

m opt-in methods would exist for third parties, thus disruptingo the nuclear model. This line of .c te thought is reminiscent of Fineman’s proposal (1995) to placea the mother/child relationship g h s at the centre of socio-legal policy, but allow for opt-in.a relationships. The marital unit is w w displaced in favour of an emphasis on care relationships,w using the metaphor of the mother/

m o child dyad, which could be expanded via . .c te a Possibly in tension with the emphasis on intentiong in determining legal parenthood is h s .a surrogate motherhood, given earlier feminist supportw for the birth mother when considering w w whether surrogacy should be honoured (e.g. Shanley 1993). They were concerned m o .c that surrogate mothers could not give meaningfulte consent prior to birth, that the potential for a g h exploitation was significant based on factorss such as age, class and race as well as emotional .a w vulnerability, and that exchange of moneyw for women’s reproductive services would w

m commodify women and children. Moreo recently, these concerns have been tested against .c te empirical research and found to bea largely unfounded (Busby and Vun 2010). The focus g h s has shifted to regulatory measures.a that can ensure women’s autonomy and minimize the w w potential for exploitation and commodification,w yet women’s unique capacity for pregnancy

m o has not been erased. As in .c , birth mothers might retain the right to reverse a te a decision to relinquish a childg within a short period after birth (Busby and Vun 2010: 89). The h s .a specificities of pregnancyw and birth are taken into account even as the ability of women to w w exercise reproductive autonomy is honoured. Both forms of maternal labour – birthing and m o .c (intentional) motheringte – are respected, but distinguished (O’Donovan and Marshall 2006). a g h As we have seen,s the history of Black motherhood also challenges dominant constructions .a w of motherhood, withw women often having to fight to control their fertility and for legal w

m rights to their children.o As well, the practice in many African-American communities is for .c te ‘othermothers’a to assist blood mothers (Kessler 2005, Roberts 1993a: 132–133). Othermothers g h s need not be.a blood relatives so, as with practices of parenting within some indigenous w w communities,w their role in parenting challenges the nuclear family model (Kline 1993).

m o As with.c intentional parenting, these practices highlight relationships in parenting and te a downplayg biological connections. Similarly, single mothers by choice often rely on support h s .a networksw outside family ties (Kelly 2012, Kessler 2005: 24–25). The challenge for feminists w w is how to recognize this direction while not erasing women’s role in pregnancy and birth.

Kessler (2005) suggests that law could recognize multiple parents for one child, but other feminists suggest risks in using this method to disrupt the nuclear model. Many mainstream

© Copyrighted Material 278 Motherhood and Law

© Copyrighted Material law reforms over-emphasize the need to find fathers for children, with particular troubling m o .c consequences for the families of single, divorced and lesbian mothers (Fineman 1995, Kellyte a g h 2011, Robson 1992). Proposals to move in this direction must be done carefully, with respects .a w both for birth mothers and for intentional parenting relationships. Still, not all legalw parents w

m need to be designated as primary (Kessler 2005). o .c te Placing single motherhood, another form of transgressive mothering, at a the heart of g h s feminist analysis can assist and potentially build bridges across racial divides.. aDespite social w w and legal efforts to persuade Black women to marry, ‘white mothers’ livesw are becoming

m o structurally more similar to the lives of Black mothers’ (Roberts 1993b: 27),.c with unmarried te a single motherhood on the rise. Black single motherhood can be seeng as an example of h s .a resistance against suggestions that a return to patriarchal family structuresw will improve the w w welfare of women and their children. m o .c Taking this resistance further may be difficult, in partte because the overt nature of a g h patriarchal definitions of motherhood has given way to more ‘innocent’s mechanisms.S helley .a w Gavigan and Dorothy Chunn (2007) dispel any notion of w an evolutionary progression w

m away from a stigmatized treatment of single mothers. Havingo once been regarded as the .c te most deserving recipients of public assistance, sole-supporta mothers have been rendered g h s undeserving during the restructuring of welfare law in.a most liberal states. Single mothers w w might have had to meet difficult eligibility hurdles (beingw a ‘fit and proper’ person to care for

m o children) or attempt to obtain support from putative.c fathers, but the original welfare system te a was designed to compensate – minimally – for theg failure or inability of a male breadwinner h s .a to provide. With the rise of neoliberalism, however,w single mothers are constructed as w w employable market citizens with responsibility for their own support. Meanwhile the m o .c unpaid labour performed by mothers ‘becomeste less visible and less articulated’ (Gavigan a g h and Chunn 2007: 767) and single motherss who do not engage in paid work are constructed .a w as a drain on the public purse. w w

m Despite these disincentives and theo fact that women’s ability to define legal motherhood .c te autonomously from men is constraineda by the impetus to ‘find fathers’ for children, planned g h s single motherhood is on the rise .a (Kelly 2012). This form of transgressive mothering also w w raises questions about the discoursew of neoliberal responsibility. Many single mothers by

m o choice have planned their motherhood,.c often using assisted reproduction or adoption, in te a what might be regarded as ga ‘responsible’ manner. Many are well-educated, middle-class h s .a and financially secure. Despitew their relative privilege, the legal system has not made it easy w w for these single mothers to establish themselves as the sole legal parent of a child or to escape m o .c accusations that they arete depriving children of fathers (Kelly 2012). In the future, a challenge a g h may be for feministss to ensure that arguments for social and legal support for single mothers .a w do not favour onlyw the more privileged or responsible women, just as some progressive legal w

m changes accommodatedo only exemplary lesbian mothers (Robson 1992: 177–178). .c te Roberts hasa said that ‘[i]t may be in the lives of those most outcast by patriarchy that g h s we will catch.a a glimpse of a liberated motherhood’ (1993b: 28). When mothers who have w w harmed theirw children are brought into the frame, more difficult but important transgressive

m o mothering.c issues arise. Roberts sees inflicted by mothers as connected to the te a g contradictoryh role of children as both the source of mothers’ vulnerability, with their s .a childrenw being held hostage to both individual men and to society, and also a source of w w their power and resistance. For instance, slave women sometimes committed against

their children in an attempt to defy their masters’ exploitation of their reproduction (Roberts 1993a: 134). An approach to liberated motherhood that identified with (some) criminal

© Copyrighted Material 279 The Ashgate Research Companion to Feminist Legal Theory

© Copyrighted Material mothers, with a focus on oppositional actions that are subversive and liberatory rather than m o subjugating of children, would not excuse all mothers who hurt their children, but rather.c te a g h ask feminists to confront the complexity of women’s subordination and the radical measuress .a w required to eradicate it (Roberts 1993a: 141). w w

m Ashe and Cahn (1993) similarly emphasize consideration of the figure of the ‘bad’o mother, .c te including taking seriously the fact that some mothers harm their children. Ina resisting a g h s notion that mothers must inevitably be good, and avoiding a polarized view.a of women as w w either fully responsible moral agents or the victims of individual men and patriarchy,w these

m o authors put mothers who engage in child abuse into context. For instance,.c maternal abuse te a must also be seen against the backdrop of women’s disproportionate careg responsibilities h s .a as well as their own abuse by male partners. Ashe and Cahn (1993) askw how who w w defend mothers who have fallen short of the ideals of motherhood can find moral worth in m o their clients, challenging feminists to always place a woman’s acts.c and choices into context. te a g h As always, the problem is that more ambivalent and complex accountss of motherhood are .a w not necessarily comprehensible in law or legal advocacy. Nevertheless,w many criminalized w

m mothers have struggled with material constraints, includingo poverty and their own abuse, .c te on their ability to provide for or protect their children. a g h s These contextual insights raise a final point highlighted.a by many feminists: that it is w w more crucial than ever in neoliberal times favouringw a shrunken state, to emphasize that

m o care is a public good and that material support for caregivers.c is necessary. To the extent that te a mothers continue to carry and suffer the consequencesg of disproportionate responsibility for h s .a care (Boyd 2003, Fineman 1995, Kessler 2005), publicw recognition and compensation for their w w care labour is required. In the longer term, revisioning the relationship between labour in m o .c the home and the public sphere of work andte politics (including adequate childcare choices, a g h a sort of public ‘othermothering’) remainss necessary in order to support the choices that .a w women as mothers ought to be able to makew – and yet, so rarely are able to in a world that w

m relies on their unpaid care labour. Nancyo Hirschmann (2010) suggests that the call for state .c te and employer support for family anda care responsibilities must be taken with a grain of g h s salt, and that relies.a on men sharing equally in child rearing. This point may w w hold water for heterosexual mothersw in relationships, but public support remains essential

m o for transgressive mothers who.c do not have partners. Making it possible for women to te a undertake mothering outsideg of traditional relationships empowers all mothers and allows h s .a them to explore non-oppressivew ways of parenting. w w

m o .c te a g h Conclusion s .a w w w

m Despite the joys oand transgressive potential that it offers, motherhood remains an institution .c te that contributesa to women’s systematic inequality and, therefore, forms a crucial site of g h s debate and struggle.a for feminists engaged with law. Many questions persist. How can more w w robust socialw and economic supports for the work of motherhood be sought without falling

m o into essentialist.c reductions of women to motherhood, or mothers to mothering? What space te a for autonomyg exists for mothers, in an historical period where the importance of fathers to h s .a children’sw well-being is regarded as key? Should all women’s choices be honoured in feminist w w legal strategies, even if a choice (for example, to be a stay at home mother) embeds a woman

in oppressive social formations? Do women’s differences as mothers outnumber what they hold in common and can a common legal strategy be contemplated? Can anti-essentialist

© Copyrighted Material 280 Motherhood and Law

© Copyrighted Material approaches be recognized without undermining feminist struggles to legally recognize m o .c the significance of maternal relationships with children? Does a focus on t e care-giving or a g h intentional relationships rather than bio-genetic ties provide a constructive direction sor is a .a w combination of the two needed? No one can answer all such questions,w but w

m the literature reviewed in this chapter provides a basis for addressing them in theo future. .c te a g h s .a w w References w

m o .c te a Arendell, T. 2000. Conceiving and investigating motherhood: the decade’sg scholarship. h s .a Journal of Marriage and the Family, 62(4), 1192–1207. w w w Ashe, M. and Cahn, N. 1993. Child abuse: a problem for feminist theory. Texas Journal of m o .c Women and the Law, 2(1), 75–112. te a g h Austin, R. 2002. Step on a crack, break your mother’s back: poors moms, myths of authority, .a w and drug-related evictions in public housing. Yale Journalw of Law and Feminism, 14(2), w

m 273–289. o .c te Backhouse, C.B. 1981. Shifting patterns in nineteenth-centurya Canadian custody law, in g h s Essays in the History of Canadian Law Volume 1, edited.a by D.H. Flaherty. Toronto: The w w Osgoode Society, 212–248. w

m o Backhouse, C.B. 1984. Desperate women and compassionate.c : infanticide in nineteenth- te a century Canada, University of Toronto Law Journalg , 34(4), 447–478. h s .a Barrett, M. and McIntosh, M. 1982.The Anti-Socialw Family. London: Verso. w w Bartlett, K.T. and Stack, C.B. 1986. Joint custody, feminism and the dependency dilemma. m o .c Berkeley Women’s Law Journal, 2(1), 9–41.te a g h Becker, M. 2002. Care and feminists. Wisconsins Women’s Law Journal, 17(1), 57–110. .a w Blackett, A. 2011. Introduction: Regulatingw Decent Work for Domestic Workers. Canadian w

m Journal of Women and the Law, 23(1),o 1–45. .c te Boyd, S.B. 1996. Is there an ideologya of motherhood in (post)modern child custody law? g h s Social and Legal Studies, 5(4), 495–521..a w w Boyd, S.B. (ed.), 1997. Challengingw the Public/Private Divide: Feminism, Law, and Public Policy.

m o Toronto: University of Toronto.c Press. te a Boyd, S.B. 2003. Child Custody,g Law, and Women’s Work. Don Mills: Oxford University Press. h s .a Boyd, S.B. 2010. Autonomyw for mothers? Relational theory and parenting apart. Feminist w w Legal Studies, 18(2), 137–158. m o .c Busby, K. and Vun, D.te 2010. Revisiting the handmaid’s tale: feminist theory meets empirical a g h research on surrogates mothers. Canadian Journal of Family Law, 26(1), 13–93. .a w Case, M.A. 2001. Howw high the apple pie? A few troubling questions about where, why, w

m and how theo burden of care for children should be lifted. Chicago-Kent Law Review, 76(3), .c te 1753–1788.a g h s Crittenden, .a A. 2001. The Price of Motherhood. New York: Metropolitan Books. w w Cunliffe, Ew. 2011. Murder, Medicine and Motherhood. Oxford: Hart Publishing.

m o Diduck,. cA. 1993. Legislating ideologies of motherhood. Social and Legal Studies, 2(4), 461–485. te a g Fineman,h M. 1995. The Neutered Mother, The Sexual Family, and Other Twentieth Century s .a Tragedies.w New York and London: Routledge. w w Fineman, M.A. and Karpin, I. (eds), 1995. Mothers in Law: Feminist Theory and the Legal

Regulation of Motherhood. New York: Columbia University Press.

© Copyrighted Material 281 The Ashgate Research Companion to Feminist Legal Theory

© Copyrighted Material Gavigan, S.A.M. 1992. Morgentaler and beyond: abortion, reproduction and the courts, m o in The Politics of Abortion, edited by J. Brodie, S.A.M. Gavigan and J. Jenson. Toronto:.c te a g h Oxford University Press, 117–146. s .a w Gavigan, S.A.M. and Chunn, D.E. 2007. From mothers’ allowance to mothers needw not w

Osgoode Hall Lawm Journal apply: Canadian welfare law as liberal and neo-liberal reforms. o , .c te 44(4), 733–772. a g h s Hirschmann, N.J. 2010. Mothers who care too much. Boston Review. [Online]. 35(4)..a Available w w at: http://bostonreview.net/BR35.4/hirschmann.php [accessed: 22 Januaryw 2012].

m o Kelly, F. 2011. Transforming Law’s Family: The Legal Recognition of Planned Lesbian.c Motherhood. te a Vancouver: UBC Press. g h s .a Kelly, F. 2012. Autonomous from the start: single mothers by choice.w Child and Family Law w w Quarterly, 24(3), 257–283. m o Kessler, L.T. 2005. Transgressive caregiving. Florida State University.c Law Review, 33(1), 1–87. te a g h Kline, M. 1993. Complicating the ideology of motherhood: child welfares law and First Nation .a w women. Queen’s Law Journal, 18(2), 306–342. w w

m Kramar, K.J. 2005. Unwilling Mothers, Unwanted Babies: Infanticideo in Canada. Vancouver: UBC .c te Press. a g h s Langer, R. 2009. A dignified and caring mother: an examination.a of Munchausen Syndrome w w by Proxy . Psychiatry, Psychology and Law, w16(2), 217–239.

m o Lessard, H. 2004. Mothers, fathers, and naming: reflections.c on the law equality framework te a and Trociuk v. British Columbia (Attorney General).g Canadian Journal of Women and the h s .a Law, 16(1), 165–211. w w w Mason, M.A. 1990–1991. Motherhood v. equal treatment. Journal of Family Law, 29(1), 1–50. m o .c Mason, M.A. 1999. The Custody Wars. New York:te Basic Books. a g h Millbank, J. 2008. The limits of functionals family: lesbian mother litigation in the era of the .a w eternal biological family. Internationalw Journal of Law, Policy and the Family, 22(2), 149–177. w

m Mosoff, J. 1997. A dressed in medicalo white and judicial black: mothers with mental .c te health histories in child welfarea and custody, in Challenging the Public/Private Divide: g h s Feminism, Law, and Public Policy.a , edited by S.B. Boyd. Toronto: University of Toronto w w Press, 227–252. w

m o Murphy, J.C. 1998. Legal images.c of motherhood: conflicting definitions from welfare reform, te a family and the criminal law.g Cornell Law Review, 83(3), 688–766. h s .a Mykitiuk, R. 2001. Beyondw conception: legal determinations of filiation in the context of w w reproductive technologies. Osgoode Hall Law Journal, 39(4), 771–816. m o .c Nedelsky, J. 1989. Reconceivingte autonomy: sources, thoughts and possibilities. Yale Journal a g h of Law and , 1(1), 7–36. .a w O’Donovan, K. andw Marshall, J. 2006. After birth: decisions about becoming a mother, in w

m Feminist Perspectiveso on Family Law, edited by A. Diduck and K. O’Donovan. New York: .c te Routledge,a 101–122. g h s Polikoff, N. .a 1990. This child does have two mothers: redefining parenthood to meet the w w needs ofw children in lesbian-mother and other nontraditional families. Georgetown Law

m o Journal.c , 78(3), 459–576. te a Raitt, g F. and Zeedyk, S. 2004. Mothers on trial: discourses of cot death and Munchausen’s h s .a Swyndrome by Proxy. Feminist Legal Studies, 12(3), 257–278. w w Rhoades, H. 2002. The no contact mother: reconstructions of motherhood in the era of the

new father. International Journal of Law, Policy and the Family, 16(1), 71–94.

© Copyrighted Material 282 Motherhood and Law

© Copyrighted Material Rich, A. 1976. Of Woman Born: Motherhood as Experience and Institution. New York: W.W. m o .c Norton & Company. te a g h Roberts, D. 1993a. Motherhood and crime. Iowa Law Review, 79(1), 95–141. s .a w Roberts, D. 1993b. Racism and patriarchy in the meaning of motherhood. American Universityw w

m Journal of Gender and the Law, 1(1), 1–38. o .c te Robson, R. 1992. Mother: the legal domestication of lesbian existence. , 7(4),a 172–185. g h s Ruddick, S. 1989. Maternal Thinking. New York: Ballantine Books. .a w w Shanley, M.L. 1993. Surrogate mothering and women’s freedom: a critiquew of contracts for

m o human reproduction. Signs, 18(3), 618–639. .c te a Sheldon, S. 2001. Sperm bandits, birth control and the battle of theg sexes.Legal Studies, h s .a 21(3), 460–480. w w w Smart, C. 1991. The legal and moral ordering of child custody. Journal of Law and Society, m o .c 18(4), 485–500. te a g h Smart, C. 1996. Deconstructing motherhood, in Good Enough Motherings , edited by E. Silva. .a w London: Routledge, 37–57. w w

m Smart, C. and Sevenhuijsen, S. (eds), 1989. Child Custody ando the Politics of Gender. London: .c te Routledge. a g h s Swift, K. 2010. Risky women: the role of risk in the construction.a of the single mother, in The w w Legal Tender of Gender: Law, Welfare and the Regulationw of Women’s Poverty, edited by S.A.M.

m o Gavigan and D.E. Chunn. Oxford: Hart Publishing,.c 143–163. te a Uviller, R.K. 1978. Fathers’ rights and feminism: theg maternal presumption revisited, Harvard h s .a Women’s Law Journal, 1(1), 107–130. w w w Williams, J. 2000. Unbending Gender: Why Family and Work Conflict and What to do About it. m o .c New York: Oxford University Press. te a g h Young, I.M. 1990. Pregnant embodiment:s subjectivity and alienation, in Throwing Like .a w a and other Essays in Feminist Philosophyw and Social Theory, edited by I.M. Young. w

m Bloomington: Indiana University Press,o 160–174. .c te a g h s .a w w w

m o .c te a g h s .a w w w

m o .c te a g h s .a w w w

m o .c te a g h s .a w w w

m o .c te a g h s .a w w w

© Copyrighted Material 283