What Matters to a Machine?
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
IS SEMANTICS POSSIBLE? Author(S): Hilary Putnam Source: Metaphilosophy , July 1970, Vol
IS SEMANTICS POSSIBLE? Author(s): Hilary Putnam Source: Metaphilosophy , July 1970, Vol. 1, No. 3 (July 1970), pp. 187-201 Published by: Wiley Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/24434824 JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms Wiley is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Metaphilosophy This content downloaded from 99.137.65.114 on Tue, 12 Jan 2021 15:10:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms M ETA PHILOSOPHY Vol. 1, No. 3, July 1970 IS SEMANTICS POSSIBLE?" Hilary Putnam In the last decade enormous progress seems to have been made in the syntactic theory of natural languages, largely as a result of the work of linguists influenced by Noam Chomsky and Zellig Harris. Comparable progress seems not to have been made in the semantic theory of natural languages, and perhaps it is time to ask why this should be the case. Why is the theory of meaning so hard? The meaning of common nouns. To get some idea of the difficulties, let us look at some of the problems that come up in connection with general names. General names are of many kinds. -
Blame, What Is It Good For?
Blame, What is it Good For? Gordon Briggs1 Abstract— Blame is an vital social and cognitive mechanism [6] and reside in a much more ambiguous moral territory. that humans utilize in their interactions with other agents. In Additionally, it is not enough to be able to correctly reason this paper, we discuss how blame-reasoning mechanisms are about moral scenarios to ensure ethical or otherwise desirable needed to enable future social robots to: (1) appropriately adapt behavior in the context of repeated and/or long-term outcomes from human-robot interactions, the robot must interactions and relationships with other social agents; (2) avoid have other social competencies that support this reasoning behaviors that are perceived to be rude due to inappropriate mechanism. Deceptive interaction partners or incorrect per- and unintentional connotations of blame; and (3) avoid behav- ceptions/predictions about morally-charged scenarios may iors that could damage long-term, working relationships with lead even a perfect ethical-reasoner to make choices with other social agents. We also discuss how current computational models of blame and other relevant competencies (e.g. natural unethical outcomes [7]. What these challenges stress is the language generation) are currently insufficient to address these need to look beyond the ability to simply generate the proper concerns. Future work is necessary to increase the social answer to a moral dilemma in theory, and to consider the reasoning capabilities of artificially intelligent agents to achieve social mechanisms needed in practice. these goals. One such social mechanism that others have posited as I. INTRODUCTION being necessary to the construction of a artificial moral agent is blame [8]. -
Curriculum Vitae of Alvin Plantinga
CURRICULUM VITAE OF ALVIN PLANTINGA A. Education Calvin College A.B. 1954 University of Michigan M.A. 1955 Yale University Ph.D. 1958 B. Academic Honors and Awards Fellowships Fellow, Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences, 1968-69 Guggenheim Fellow, June 1 - December 31, 1971, April 4 - August 31, 1972 Fellow, American Academy of Arts & Sciences, 1975 - Fellow, Calvin Center for Christian Scholarship, 1979-1980 Visiting Fellow, Balliol College, Oxford 1975-76 National Endowment for the Humanities Fellowships, 1975-76, 1987, 1995-6 Fellowship, American Council of Learned Societies, 1980-81 Fellow, Frisian Academy, 1999 Gifford Lecturer, 1987, 2005 Honorary Degrees Glasgow University, l982 Calvin College (Distinguished Alumni Award), 1986 North Park College, 1994 Free University of Amsterdam, 1995 Brigham Young University, 1996 University of the West in Timisoara (Timisoara, Romania), 1998 Valparaiso University, 1999 2 Offices Vice-President, American Philosophical Association, Central Division, 1980-81 President, American Philosophical Association, Central Division, 1981-82 President, Society of Christian Philosophers, l983-86 Summer Institutes and Seminars Staff Member, Council for Philosophical Studies Summer Institute in Metaphysics, 1968 Staff member and director, Council for Philosophical Studies Summer Institute in Philosophy of Religion, 1973 Director, National Endowment for the Humanities Summer Seminar, 1974, 1975, 1978 Staff member and co-director (with William P. Alston) NEH Summer Institute in Philosophy of Religion (Bellingham, Washington) 1986 Instructor, Pew Younger Scholars Seminar, 1995, 1999 Co-director summer seminar on nature in belief, Calvin College, July, 2004 Other E. Harris Harbison Award for Distinguished Teaching (Danforth Foundation), 1968 Member, Council for Philosophical Studies, 1968-74 William Evans Visiting Fellow University of Otago (New Zealand) 1991 Mentor, Collegium, Fairfield University 1993 The James A. -
On How to Build a Moral Machine
On How to Build a Moral Machine Paul Bello [email protected] Human & Bioengineered Systems Division - Code 341, Office of Naval Research, 875 N. Randolph St., Arlington, VA 22203 USA Selmer Bringsjord [email protected] Depts. of Cognitive Science, Computer Science & the Lally School of Management, Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute, Troy, NY 12180 USA Abstract Herein we make a plea to machine ethicists for the inclusion of constraints on their theories con- sistent with empirical data on human moral cognition. As philosophers, we clearly lack widely accepted solutions to issues regarding the existence of free will, the nature of persons and firm conditions on moral agency/patienthood; all of which are indispensable concepts to be deployed by any machine able to make moral judgments. No agreement seems forthcoming on these mat- ters, and we don’t hold out hope for machines that can both always do the right thing (on some general ethic) and produce explanations for its behavior that would be understandable to a human confederate. Our tentative solution involves understanding the folk concepts associated with our moral intuitions regarding these matters, and how they might be dependent upon the nature of hu- man cognitive architecture. It is in this spirit that we begin to explore the complexities inherent in human moral judgment via computational theories of the human cognitive architecture, rather than under the extreme constraints imposed by rational-actor models assumed throughout much of the literature on philosophical ethics. After discussing the various advantages and challenges of taking this particular perspective on the development of artificial moral agents, we computationally explore a case study of human intuitions about the self and causal responsibility. -
Which Consequentialism? Machine Ethics and Moral Divergence
MIRI MACHINE INTELLIGENCE RESEARCH INSTITUTE Which Consequentialism? Machine Ethics and Moral Divergence Carl Shulman, Henrik Jonsson MIRI Visiting Fellows Nick Tarleton Carnegie Mellon University, MIRI Visiting Fellow Abstract Some researchers in the field of machine ethics have suggested consequentialist or util- itarian theories as organizing principles for Artificial Moral Agents (AMAs) (Wallach, Allen, and Smit 2008) that are ‘full ethical agents’ (Moor 2006), while acknowledging extensive variation among these theories as a serious challenge (Wallach, Allen, and Smit 2008). This paper develops that challenge, beginning with a partial taxonomy ofconse- quentialisms proposed by philosophical ethics. We discuss numerous ‘free variables’ of consequentialism where intuitions conflict about optimal values, and then consider spe- cial problems of human-level AMAs designed to implement a particular ethical theory, by comparison to human proponents of the same explicit principles. In conclusion, we suggest that if machine ethics is to fully succeed, it must draw upon the developing field of moral psychology. Shulman, Carl, Nick Tarleton, and Henrik Jonsson. 2009. “Which Consequentialism? Machine Ethics and Moral Divergence.” In AP-CAP 2009: The Fifth Asia-Pacific Computing and Philosophy Conference, October 1st-2nd, University of Tokyo, Japan, Proceedings, edited by Carson Reynolds and Alvaro Cassinelli, 23–25. AP-CAP 2009. http://ia-cap.org/ap-cap09/proceedings.pdf. This version contains minor changes. Carl Shulman, Henrik Jonsson, Nick Tarleton 1. Free Variables of Consequentialism Suppose that the recommendations of a broadly utilitarian view depend on decisions about ten free binary variables, where we assign a probability of 80% to our favored option for each variable; in this case, if our probabilities are well-calibrated and our errors are not correlated across variables, then we will have only slightly more than a 10% chance of selecting the correct (in some meta-ethical framework) specification. -
Philosophy of Artificial Intelligence
David Gray Grant Philosophy of Artificial Intelligence Note to the reader: this syllabus is for an introductory undergraduate lecture course with no prerequisites. Course Description In this course, we will explore the philosophical implications of artificial intelligence. Could we build machines with minds like ours out of computer chips? Could we cheat death by uploading our minds to a computer server? Are we living in a software-based simulation? Should a driverless car kill one pedestrian to save five? Will artificial intelligence be the end of work (and if so, what should we do about it)? This course is also a general introduction to philosophical problems and methods. We will dis- cuss classic problems in several areas of philosophy, including philosophy of mind, metaphysics, epistemology, and ethics. In the process, you will learn how to engage with philosophical texts, analyze and construct arguments, investigate controversial questions in collaboration with others, and express your views with greater clarity and precision. Contact Information Instructor: David Gray Grant Email: [email protected] Office: 303 Emerson Hall Office hours: Mondays 3:00-5:00 and by appointment Assignments and Grading You must complete all required assignments in order to pass this course. Your grade will be determined as follows: • 10%: Participation • 25%: 4 short written assignments (300-600 words) • 20%: Paper 1 (1200-1500 words) • 25%: Paper 2 (1200-1500 words) • 20%: Final exam Assignments should be submitted in .docx or .pdf format (.docx is preferred), Times New Roman 12 point font, single-spaced. Submissions that exceed the word limits specified above (including footnotes) will not be accepted. -
Machine Learning Ethics in the Context of Justice Intuition
SHS Web of Conferences 69, 00150 (2019) https://doi.org/10.1051/shsconf/20196900150 CILDIAH-2019 Machine Learning Ethics in the Context of Justice Intuition Natalia Mamedova1,*, Arkadiy Urintsov1, Nina Komleva1, Olga Staroverova1 and Boris Fedorov1 1Plekhanov Russian University of Economics, 36, Stremyanny lane, 117997, Moscow, Russia Abstract. The article considers the ethics of machine learning in connection with such categories of social philosophy as justice, conviction, value. The ethics of machine learning is presented as a special case of a mathematical model of a dilemma - whether it corresponds to the “learning” algorithm of the intuition of justice or not. It has been established that the use of machine learning for decision making has a prospect only within the limits of the intuition of justice field based on fair algorithms. It is proposed to determine the effectiveness of the decision, considering the ethical component and given ethical restrictions. The cyclical nature of the relationship between the algorithmic algorithms subprocesses in machine learning and the stages of conducting mining analysis projects using the CRISP methodology has been established. The value of ethical constraints for each of the algorithmic processes has been determined. The provisions of the Theory of System Restriction are applied to find a way to measure the effect of ethical restrictions on the “learning” algorithm 1 Introduction Accepting the freedom of thought is authentic intuition of justice of one individual in relation to The intuition of justice is regarded as a sincere, himself and others. But for artificial intelligence emotionally saturated belief in the justice of some (hereinafter - AI) freedom of thought is not supposed - position. -
Why Machine Ethics?
www.computer.org/intelligent Why Machine Ethics? Colin Allen, Indiana University Wendell Wallach, Yale University Iva Smit, E&E Consultants Vol. 21, No. 4 July/August 2006 This material is presented to ensure timely dissemination of scholarly and technical work. Copyright and all rights therein are retained by authors or by other copyright holders. All persons copying this information are expected to adhere to the terms and constraints invoked by each author's copyright. In most cases, these works may not be reposted without the explicit permission of the copyright holder. © 2006 IEEE. Personal use of this material is permitted. However, permission to reprint/republish this material for advertising or promotional purposes or for creating new collective works for resale or redistribution to servers or lists, or to reuse any copyrighted component of this work in other works must be obtained from the IEEE. For more information, please see www.ieee.org/portal/pages/about/documentation/copyright/polilink.html. Machine Ethics Why Machine Ethics? Colin Allen, Indiana University Wendell Wallach, Yale University Iva Smit, E&E Consultants runaway trolley is approaching a fork in the tracks. If the trolley runs on its cur- A rent track, it will kill a work crew of five. If the driver steers the train down the other branch, the trolley will kill a lone worker. If you were driving the trolley, what would you do? What would a computer or robot do? Trolley cases, first introduced by philosopher which decisions must be made? It’s easy to argue Philippa Foot in 19671 and a staple of introductory from a position of ignorance that such a goal is impos- Machine ethics isn’t ethics courses, have multiplied in the past four sible to achieve. -
The Oberlin Colloquium in Philosophy: Program History
The Oberlin Colloquium in Philosophy: Program History 1960 FIRST COLLOQUIUM Wilfrid Sellars, "On Looking at Something and Seeing it" Ronald Hepburn, "God and Ambiguity" Comments: Dennis O'Brien Kurt Baier, "Itching and Scratching" Comments: David Falk/Bruce Aune Annette Baier, "Motives" Comments: Jerome Schneewind 1961 SECOND COLLOQUIUM W.D. Falk, "Hegel, Hare and the Existential Malady" Richard Cartwright, "Propositions" Comments: Ruth Barcan Marcus D.A.T. Casking, "Avowals" Comments: Martin Lean Zeno Vendler, "Consequences, Effects and Results" Comments: William Dray/Sylvan Bromberger PUBLISHED: Analytical Philosophy, First Series, R.J. Butler (ed.), Oxford, Blackwell's, 1962. 1962 THIRD COLLOQUIUM C.J. Warnock, "Truth" Arthur Prior, "Some Exercises in Epistemic Logic" Newton Garver, "Criteria" Comments: Carl Ginet/Paul Ziff Hector-Neri Castenada, "The Private Language Argument" Comments: Vere Chappell/James Thomson John Searle, "Meaning and Speech Acts" Comments: Paul Benacerraf/Zeno Vendler PUBLISHED: Knowledge and Experience, C.D. Rollins (ed.), University of Pittsburgh Press, 1964. 1963 FOURTH COLLOQUIUM Michael Scriven, "Insanity" Frederick Will, "The Preferability of Probable Beliefs" Norman Malcolm, "Criteria" Comments: Peter Geach/George Pitcher Terrence Penelhum, "Pleasure and Falsity" Comments: William Kennick/Arnold Isenberg 1964 FIFTH COLLOQUIUM Stephen Korner, "Some Remarks on Deductivism" J.J.C. Smart, "Nonsense" Joel Feinberg, "Causing Voluntary Actions" Comments: Keith Donnellan/Keith Lehrer Nicholas Rescher, "Evaluative Metaphysics" Comments: Lewis W. Beck/Thomas E. Patton Herbert Hochberg, "Qualities" Comments: Richard Severens/J.M. Shorter PUBLISHED: Metaphysics and Explanation, W.H. Capitan and D.D. Merrill (eds.), University of Pittsburgh Press, 1966. 1965 SIXTH COLLOQUIUM Patrick Nowell-Smith, "Acts and Locutions" George Nakhnikian, "St. Anselm's Four Ontological Arguments" Hilary Putnam, "Psychological Predicates" Comments: Bruce Aune/U.T. -
APA Newsletter on Philosophy and Computers, Vol. 14, No. 2
NEWSLETTER | The American Philosophical Association Philosophy and Computers SPRING 2015 VOLUME 14 | NUMBER 2 FROM THE GUEST EDITOR John P. Sullins NOTES FROM THE COMMUNITY ON PAT SUPPES ARTICLES Patrick Suppes Patrick Suppes Autobiography Luciano Floridi Singularitarians, AItheists, and Why the Problem with Artificial Intelligence is H.A.L. (Humanity At Large), not HAL Peter Boltuc First-Person Consciousness as Hardware D. E. Wittkower Social Media and the Organization Man Niklas Toivakainen The Moral Roots of Conceptual Confusion in Artificial Intelligence Research Xiaohong Wang, Jian Wang, Kun Zhao, and Chaolin Wang Increase or Decrease of Entropy: To Construct a More Universal Macroethics (A Discussion of Luciano Floridi’s The Ethics of Information) VOLUME 14 | NUMBER 2 SPRING 2015 © 2015 BY THE AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL ASSOCIATION ISSN 2155-9708 APA NEWSLETTER ON Philosophy and Computers JOHN P. SULLINS, GUEST EDITOR VOLUME 14 | NUMBER 2 | SPRING 2015 but here we wish to celebrate his accomplishments in the FROM THE GUEST EDITOR fields of philosophy and computing one last time. John P. Sullins To accomplish that goal I have compiled some interesting SONOMA STATE UNIVERSITY pieces from an autobiography that Pat wrote some years ago but that he added to a bit for an event held in his honor November 17, 2014, marked the end of an inspiring at Stanford. In this document he explains his motivations career. On that day Patrick Suppes died quietly at the and accomplishments in various fields of study that are age of ninety-two in his house on the Stanford Campus, of interest to our community. In that section you will see which had been his home both physically and intellectually just how ambitious Pat was in the world of computer since 1950. -
Proper Names and Their Role in Social Ontology
Proper Names and Their Role in Social Ontology Marek Nagy Palacký University, Olomouc Abstract: The article deals with an applicability of John Searle’s theory of social ontology to linguistic category of proper names . We suggest that in the context of Searle’s theory we can consider proper names to be a kind of social institution . By several examples from anthropolinguistic research and from the field of theoretical onomastics we try to show that proper names meet conditions specified by John Searle, in particu- lar that – through different communities all over the world – they are “holders” of various types of deontic power . At the end of our article we shortly weigh the possibility that proper names can be regard as status indicators (in terms of Searle’s theory) too . Keywords: baptism, deontic power, onomastics, proper names, social ontology . Blake, John? Nothing here. Alright, try my legal name. You should use your full name. I like that name, Robin. Dark Knight Rises To speak about problems of proper names in the context of philo- sophical views of John Searle makes sense for various reasons . Primar- ily, professor Searle has dealt with the category of proper names re- peatedly: In fact, he started his career with the text Proper Names (see Searle 1958) and the conception presented here brought him directly in “textbooks” of this important philosophical debate; proper names as rather strange and interesting individuals are aptly shown also in Sear- le’s Speech Acts (see Searle 1969; the evidence of strangeness could be the mentioned and everlasting discussion on their reference behavior, Organon F 19 (2012), 137-147 © 2012 The Author. -
21 Moral Machines and the Threat of Ethical Nihilism
21 Moral Machines and the Threat of Ethical Nihilism Anthony F. Beavers In his famous 1950 paper where he presents what became the benchmark for success in artifi cial intelligence, Turing notes that “ at the end of the century the use of words and general educated opinion will have altered so much that one will be able to speak of machines thinking without expecting to be contradicted ” ( Turing 1950 , 442). Kurzweil suggests that Turing ’ s prediction was correct, even if no machine has yet to pass the Turing Test ( 1990 ). In the wake of the computer revolution, research in arti- fi cial intelligence and cognitive science has pushed in the direction of interpreting “ thinking ” as some sort of computational process. On this understanding, thinking is something computers (in principle) and humans (in practice) can both do. It is diffi cult to say precisely when in history the meaning of the term “ thinking ” headed in this direction. Signs are already present in the mechanistic and mathemati- cal tendencies of the early modern period, and maybe even glimmers are apparent in the thoughts of the ancient Greek philosophers themselves. But over the long haul, we somehow now consider “ thinking ” as separate from the categories of “ thoughtful- ness ” (in the general sense of wondering about things), “ insight, ” and “ wisdom. ” Intelligent machines are all around us, and the world is populated with smart cars, smart phones, and even smart (robotic) appliances. But, though my cell phone might be smart, I do not take that to mean that it is thoughtful, insightful, or wise. So, what has become of these latter categories? They seem to be bygones, left behind by scien- tifi c and computational conceptions of thinking and knowledge that no longer have much use for them.