A New Semantics for Overriding in Description Logics (Extended Abstract)∗

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A New Semantics for Overriding in Description Logics (Extended Abstract)∗ Proceedings of the Twenty-Sixth International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (IJCAI-17) A New Semantics for Overriding in Description Logics (Extended abstract)∗ Piero A. Bonatti, Marco Faella Iliana M. Petrova Luigi Sauro Universita` degli studi di Napoli Federico II [email protected] Abstract Inheritance blocking: In several nonmonotonic logics a concept with exceptional properties inherits none of the de- Nonmonotonic inferences are not yet supported by fault properties of its superclasses. For instance penguins, Description Logic technology, although their po- that are exceptional birds because they do not fly, do not in- tential usefulness is widely recognized. Lack of herit any of the other default properties of birds, such as hav- support to nonmonotonic reasoning is due to a ing wings and feathers. number of issues related to expressiveness, compu- Undesired CWA effects: In some nonmonotonic DLs, an tational complexity, and optimizations. This work exceptional concept is shrinked to the individuals that explic- contributes to the practical support of nonmono- itly belong to it; it may even become inconsistent. Using the tonic reasoning in description logics by introduc- penguin example again, by default no penguins exist unless ing a new semantics designed to address knowl- explicitly stated otherwise. After asserting that the individual edge engineering needs. The formalism is validated Opus is a penguin, the concept Penguin becomes the single- through extensive comparison with the other non- ton {Opus}. monotonic DLs, and systematic scalability tests. Limited control on role ranges: In most nonmonotonic DLs, the knowledge engineer cannot specify whether a role 1 Introduction should range only over normal individuals or not. In the DLs based on default logic, rational closure, and variants thereof, Many modern applications of description logics (DLs, for default properties never apply to role fillers. short), such as biomedical ontologies and semantic web poli- Silent removal of unresolved conflicts: Very frequently, cies, provide fresh motivations for extending DLs with non- unresolved conflicts between nonmonotonic assertions are a monotonic inferences. Some recent examples stemming symptom of a gap in the axiomatization. The correct res- from the biomedical domain are discussed in [Rector, 2004; olution of such conflicts is typically domain dependent and Stevens et al., 2007]. There, the goal of supporting default should require human intervention (see [Bonatti et al., 2015a; attributes and exceptions is deemed important enough to look 2015b] for a detailed discussion of this issue). Most non- for alternative representation methods, based on classical rea- monotonic logics hide such conflicts (i.e. they do not have soning and ontology design patterns. However, these solu- any visible consequence) thereby hindering their identifica- tions do not scale to more complex examples with multiple tion – a necessary step for the validation and correction of exception dimensions, as discussed in [Rector, 2004]: The knowledge bases. number of additional concepts introduced by the patterns may Moreover, the computational complexity of nonmonotonic grow exponentially. Moreover, such auxiliary concepts are DLs is almost always higher than the complexity of the cor- defined using computationally expensive constructs such as responding classical DL, and the tractability of the OWL 2 disjunction. So, even if the given knowledge base belongs to profiles is not preserved. The lack of optimization techniques some low-complexity fragment (such as the OWL2 profiles), for nonmonotonic DL reasoning is a further obstacle to the its nonmonotonic extension is generally not tractable. practical application of these logics. Nonmonotonic DLs natively support default inferences and Given the above motivations (more extensively articulated exceptions. However none of the standard nonmonotonic se- in the full paper), in this work we have investigated a new N mantics produces exactly the set of expected consequences, family of nonmonotonic DLs, called DL , aimed at address- N and this can be verified on a range of rather simple examples. ing the above drawbacks. The comparison of DL with the Some of the major known drawbacks are the following: major nonmonotonic DLs is summarized in Table 1. Prelim- ∗This is an extended abstract of the paper [Bonatti et al., 2015a], inary performance tests have been reported in the full pa- integrated with the developments in [Bonatti and Sauro, 2017], con- per and have been later extended in [Bonatti et al., 2015b] ditionally accepted for publication on the AIJ. This research is cur- using additional optimization techniques that show unparal- rently being funded by the European Unions Horizon 2020 research leled scalability properties over large nonmonotonic knowl- and innovation programme under grant agreement N. 731601. edge bases, with more than 105 axioms. For instance, sub- 4975 Proceedings of the Twenty-Sixth International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (IJCAI-17) Table 1: Summary of comparisons with other nonmonotonic DLs Features CIRC DEF AEL TYP RAT PR DLN no inheritance X X X X X X blocking no CWA effects X X X X X fine-grained control X(1) X on role ranges detects inconsistent (2) X(3) X prototypes unique deductive X X X closure preserves tractability (5) (5) X(4) implicit specificity X X X X other priorities X X X CIRC, DEF, AEL, TYP, RAT, PR stand, respectively, for Circumscribed DLs [Bonatti et al., 2009; 2011], Default DLs [Baader and Hollunder, 1995a; 1995b], Autoepistemic DLs [Donini et al., 2002], DLs with Typicality [Giordano et al., 2009; 2013], DLs with Rational Closure [Casini and Straccia, 2010; Casini et al., 2013] and their combination with inheri- tance networks [Casini and Straccia, 2013], and Probabilistic DLs [Lukasiewicz, 2008]. (1) Context dependent, see Example 29 in the full paper. (2) Only direct conflicts, as in Example 10 in the full paper. (3) Inconsistency may propagate to the entire KB. (4) Subsumption and assertion checking only, which suffice for application examples. (5) Currently proved for EL (Giovanni Casini, personal communication). sumption/assertion query answering over nonmonotonic vari- The informal meaning of C ⊑n D is: “all standard in- ants of the Gene Ontology with classical role fillers ranges stances, by default, satisfy C ⊑ D, unless stated otherwise”, from 0.25 to 2.46 seconds. that is, unless some higher priority axioms entail that some standard instances satisfy C ⊓ ¬D; in that case, C ⊑n D is N 2 The Family DL overridden. The instances of any concept NE are required to satisfy all the DIs that are not overridden in NE. N N Let DL be any description logic. The language of DL is The priority relation over DIs is denoted by ≺. DL obtained by adding a new concept name NC for each DL solves automatically only the conflicts that can be settled us- concept C. The new concepts are called normality concepts, ing ≺. Any other conflict should be regarded as a representa- although the term standard would be more appropriate since tion error (cf. the discussion of silent conflict removal in the N DL – unlike typicality logics and rational closure – has not introduction) and shall be resolved by the knowledge engi- been designed to model normality (as formalized by the KLM neer, typically by adding specific DIs. Unresolved conflicts postulates, for example). yield inconsistent normality concepts, that can be detected by N queries of the form NC ⊑ ⊥. DL has a utilitarian purpose, related to McCarthy’s N conventions [McCarthy, 1986], aimed at making knowledge The priority relation is a parameter of DL . The full pa- bases more manageable, e.g. by reducing their size, improv- per considers both the specificity-based priority of rational ing modularity, and so on. We may want to assert that by closure and a simpler kind of specificity adopted by circum- default a drug has contraindication X not because this is nor- scribed DLs [Bonatti et al., 2015a], namely: δ1 ≺ δ2 iff mally so, but rather for mitigating the effects of potential hu- man errors [Rector, 2004; Stevens et al., 2007]: It is safer KB |≈ pre(δ1) ⊑ pre(δ2) and KB 6|≈ pre(δ2) ⊑ pre(δ1) . to signal more contraindications than missing some; accord- N The expression α means that α is a conse- ingly, with the above default assertion, forgetting to define KB |≈ DL quence of . Due to space limitations, we do not report the the contraindications of a new drug cannot result in a miss- KB N model-theoretic definition of |≈ and present only its reduc- ing contraindication. The goal of DL is supporting such a tion to classical reasoning [Bonatti et al., 2015a]. For all sub- variety of knowledge engineering needs in a scalable way. Σ 1 N sumptions and assertions α, KB |≈ α holds iff KB |= α, A DL knowledge base is a disjoint union KB = S ∪ D N where Σ is the set of normality concepts explicitly occurring Σ where S is a finite set of DL inclusions and assertions and in KB∪{α}, and KB is a classical knowledge base obtained D is a finite set of defeasible inclusions (DIs, for short) that as follows (recall that KB = S ∪ D): are expressions C ⊑n D where C is a DL concept and D N a DL concept. If δ = (C ⊑n D), then pre(δ) and con(δ) 1In this classical translation, normality concepts are treated like denote C and D, respectively. new concept names. 4976 Proceedings of the Twenty-Sixth International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (IJCAI-17) DLN complexity Mamm lungs Mamm fins knowledge base ⊑n ∃ ⊑n ¬∃ DL subsumption and and concept SeaAnim fins Whales Mamm SeaAnim complexity assertion checking ⊑n ∃ ⊑ ⊓ consistency Dolphins ⊑ Mamm ⊓ SeaAnim ⊓ ∃ fins P P P ExpTime ExpTime ExpTime Table 3: The KB formalizing the example N2ExpTime PN2ExpTime PN2ExpTime N All results hold for specificity and other priority relations in 3 Behavior of DL C, where is the complexity of subsumption in P C DL A DI δ = (C ⊑n D) is roughly similar to a set of defaults stating, for each normality concept NE, that the instances of Table 2: Some complexity results NE satisfy C ⊑ D unless stated otherwise (equivalently, δNE holds by default).
Recommended publications
  • Denying a Dualism: Goodman's Repudiation of the Analytic/Synthetic Distinction
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 28, 2004, 226-238. Denying a Dualism: Goodman’s Repudiation of the Analytic/Synthetic Distinction Catherine Z. Elgin The analytic synthetic/distinction forms the backbone of much modern Western philosophy. It underwrites a conception of the relation of representations to reality which affords an understanding of cognition. Its repudiation thus requires a fundamental reconception and perhaps a radical revision of philosophy. Many philosophers believe that the repudiation of the analytic/synthetic distinction and kindred dualisms constitutes a major loss, possibly even an irrecoverable loss, for philosophy. Nelson Goodman thinks otherwise. He believes that it liberates philosophy from unwarranted restrictions, creating opportunities for the development of powerful new approaches to and reconceptions of seemingly intractable problems. In this article I want to sketch some of the consequences of Goodman’s reconception. My focus is not on Goodman’s reasons for denying the dualism, but on some of the ways its absence affects his position. I do not contend that the Goodman obsessed over the issue. I have no reason to think that the repudiation of the distinction was a central factor in his intellectual life. But by considering the function that the analytic/synthetic distinction has performed in traditional philosophy, and appreciating what is lost and gained in repudiating it, we gain insight into Goodman’s contributions. I begin then by reviewing the distinction and the conception of philosophy it supports. The analytic/synthetic distinction is a distinction between truths that depend entirely on meaning and truths that depend on both meaning and fact. In the early modern period, it was cast as a distinction between relations of ideas and matters of fact.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Logic 2018 Course Description (Tentative) January 15, 2018
    Philosophical Logic 2018 Course description (tentative) January 15, 2018 Valentin Goranko Introduction This 7.5 hp course is mainly intended for students in philosophy and is generally accessible to a broad audience with basic background on formal classical logic and general appreciation of philosophical aspects of logic. Practical information The course will be given in English. It will comprise 18 two-hour long sessions combining lectures and exercises, grouped in 2 sessions per week over 9 teaching weeks. The weekly pairs of 2-hour time slots (incl. short breaks) allocated for these sessions, will be on Mondays during 10.00-12.00 and 13.00-15.00, except for the first lecture. The course will begin on Wednesday, April 4, 2018 (Week 14) at 10.00 am in D220, S¨odra huset, hus D. Lecturer's info: Name: Valentin Goranko Email: [email protected] Homepage: http://www2.philosophy.su.se/goranko Course webpage: http://www2.philosophy.su.se/goranko/Courses2018/PhilLogic-2018.html Prerequisites The course will be accessible to a broad audience with introductory background on classical formal logic. Some basic knowledge of modal logics would be an advantage but not a prerequisite. Brief description Philosophical logic studies a variety of non-classical logical systems intended to formalise and reason about various philosophical concepts and ideas. They include a broad family of modal logics, as well as many- valued, intuitionistic, relevant, conditional, non-monotonic, para-consistent, etc. logics. Modal logics extend classical logic with additional intensional logical operators, reflecting different modes of truth, including alethic, epistemic, doxastic, temporal, deontic, agentive, etc.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Philosophy. Social Studies--Language Arts: 6414.16. INSTITUTION Dade County Public Schools, Miami, Fla
    DOCUMENT RESUME ED 086 604 SO 006 822 AUTHOR Norris, Jack A., Jr. TITLE Introduction to Philosophy. Social Studies--Language Arts: 6414.16. INSTITUTION Dade County Public Schools, Miami, Fla. PUB DATE 72 NOTE 20p.; Authorized Course of Instruction for the Quinmester Program EDRS PRICE MF-$0.65 HC-$3.29 DESCRIPTORS Course Objectives; Curriculum Guides; Grade 10; Grade 11; Grade 12; *Language Arts; Learnin4 Activities; *Logic; Non Western Civilization; *Philosophy; Resource Guides; Secondary Grades; *Social Studies; *Social Studies Units; Western Civilization IDENTIFIERS *Quinmester Program ABSTRACT Western and non - western philosophers and their ideas are introduced to 10th through 12th grade students in this general social studies Quinmester course designed to be used as a preparation for in-depth study of the various schools of philosophical thought. By acquainting students with the questions and categories of philosophy, a point of departure for further study is developed. Through suggested learning activities the meaning of philosopky is defined. The Socratic, deductive, inductive, intuitive and eclectic approaches to philosophical thought are examined, as are three general areas of philosophy, metaphysics, epistemology,and axiology. Logical reasoning is applied to major philosophical questions. This course is arranged, as are other quinmester courses, with sections on broad goals, course content, activities, and materials. A related document is ED 071 937.(KSM) FILMED FROM BEST AVAILABLE COPY U S DEPARTMENT EDUCATION OF HEALTH. NAT10N41
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    BAS C. VAN FRAASSEN Curriculum Vitae Last updated 3/6/2019 I. Personal and Academic History .................................................................................................................... 1 List of Degrees Earned ........................................................................................................................................................ 1 Title of Ph.D. Thesis ........................................................................................................................................................... 1 Positions held ..................................................................................................................................................................... 1 Invited lectures and lecture series ........................................................................................................................................ 1 List of Honors, Prizes ......................................................................................................................................................... 4 Research Grants .................................................................................................................................................................. 4 Non-Academic Publications ................................................................................................................................................ 5 II. Professional Activities .................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • The Analytic-Synthetic Distinction and the Classical Model of Science: Kant, Bolzano and Frege
    Synthese (2010) 174:237–261 DOI 10.1007/s11229-008-9420-9 The analytic-synthetic distinction and the classical model of science: Kant, Bolzano and Frege Willem R. de Jong Received: 10 April 2007 / Revised: 24 July 2007 / Accepted: 1 April 2008 / Published online: 8 November 2008 © The Author(s) 2008. This article is published with open access at Springerlink.com Abstract This paper concentrates on some aspects of the history of the analytic- synthetic distinction from Kant to Bolzano and Frege. This history evinces con- siderable continuity but also some important discontinuities. The analytic-synthetic distinction has to be seen in the first place in relation to a science, i.e. an ordered system of cognition. Looking especially to the place and role of logic it will be argued that Kant, Bolzano and Frege each developed the analytic-synthetic distinction within the same conception of scientific rationality, that is, within the Classical Model of Science: scientific knowledge as cognitio ex principiis. But as we will see, the way the distinction between analytic and synthetic judgments or propositions functions within this model turns out to differ considerably between them. Keywords Analytic-synthetic · Science · Logic · Kant · Bolzano · Frege 1 Introduction As is well known, the critical Kant is the first to apply the analytic-synthetic distinction to such things as judgments, sentences or propositions. For Kant this distinction is not only important in his repudiation of traditional, so-called dogmatic, metaphysics, but it is also crucial in his inquiry into (the possibility of) metaphysics as a rational science. Namely, this distinction should be “indispensable with regard to the critique of human understanding, and therefore deserves to be classical in it” (Kant 1783, p.
    [Show full text]
  • Description Logics—Basics, Applications, and More
    Description Logics|Basics, Applications, and More Ian Horrocks Information Management Group University of Manchester, UK Ulrike Sattler Teaching and Research Area for Theoretical Computer Science RWTH Aachen, Germany RWTH Aachen 1 Germany Overview of the Tutorial • History and Basics: Syntax, Semantics, ABoxes, Tboxes, Inference Problems and their interrelationship, and Relationship with other (logical) formalisms • Applications of DLs: ER-diagrams with i.com demo, ontologies, etc. including system demonstration • Reasoning Procedures: simple tableaux and why they work • Reasoning Procedures II: more complex tableaux, non-standard inference prob- lems • Complexity issues • Implementing/Optimising DL systems RWTH Aachen 2 Germany Description Logics • family of logic-based knowledge representation formalisms well-suited for the representation of and reasoning about ➠ terminological knowledge ➠ configurations ➠ ontologies ➠ database schemata { schema design, evolution, and query optimisation { source integration in heterogeneous databases/data warehouses { conceptual modelling of multidimensional aggregation ➠ : : : • descendents of semantics networks, frame-based systems, and KL-ONE • aka terminological KR systems, concept languages, etc. RWTH Aachen 3 Germany Architecture of a Standard DL System Knowledge Base I N Terminology F E I R Father = Man u 9 has child.>... N E T Human = Mammal. u Biped . N E Description C R E F Logic A Concrete Situation S C Y E John:Human u Father S John has child Bill . T . E M RWTH Aachen 4 Germany Introduction
    [Show full text]
  • Willard Van Orman Quine: the Analytic/Synthetic Distinction
    Willard Van Orman Quine: The Analytic/Synthetic Distinction Willard Van Orman Quine was one of the most well-known American “analytic” philosophers of the twentieth century. He made significant contributions to many areas of philosophy, including philosophy of language, logic, epistemology, philosophy of science, and philosophy of mind/psychology (behaviorism). However, he is best known for his rejection of the analytic/synthetic distinction. Technically, this is the distinction between statements true in virtue of the meanings of their terms (like “a bachelor is an unmarried man”) and statements whose truth is a function not simply of the meanings of terms, but of the way the world is (such as, “That bachelor is wearing a grey suit”). Although a contentious thesis, analyticity has been a popular explanation, especially among empiricists, both for the necessity of necessary truths and for the a priori knowability of some truths. Thus, in some contexts “analytic truth,” “necessary truth,” and “a priori truth” have been used interchangeably, and the analytic/synthetic distinction has been treated as equivalent to the distinctions between necessary and contingent truths, and between a priori and a posteriori (or empirical) truths. Empirical truths can be known only by empirical verification, rather than by “unpacking” the meanings of the terms involved, and are usually thought to be contingent. Quine wrestled with the analytic/synthetic distinction for years, but he did not make his thoughts public until 1950, when he delivered his paper, “The Two Dogmas of Empiricism” at a meeting of the American Philosophical Association. In this paper, Quine argues that all attempts to define and understand analyticity are circular.
    [Show full text]
  • A Fuzzy Description Logic
    From: AAAI-98 Proceedings. Copyright © 1998, AAAI (www.aaai.org). All rights reserved. A Fuzzy Description Logic Umberto Straccia I.E.I - C.N.R. Via S. Maria, 46 I-56126 Pisa (PI) ITALY [email protected] Abstract is such a concept: we may say that an individual tom is an instance of the concept Tall only to a certain degree Description Logics (DLs, for short) allow reasoning n ∈ [0, 1] depending on tom’s height. about individuals and concepts, i.e. set of individuals with common properties. Typically, DLs are limited to Fuzzy logic directly deals with the notion of vague- dealing with crisp, well dened concepts. That is, con- ness and imprecision using fuzzy predicates. Therefore, cepts for which the problem whether an individual is it oers an appealing foundation for a generalisation of an instance of it is a yes/no question. More often than DLs in order to dealing with such vague concepts. not, the concepts encountered in the real world do not The aim of this work is to present a general fuzzy DL, have a precisely dened criteria of membership: we which combines fuzzy logic with DLs. In particular we may say that an individual is an instance of a concept will extend DLs by allowing expressions of the form only to a certain degree, depending on the individual’s hC(a) ni (n ∈ [0, 1]), e.g. hTall(tom) .7i, with intended properties. Concepts of this kind are rather vague than precise. As fuzzy logic directly deals with the notion of meaning “the membership degree of individual a being vagueness and imprecision, it oers an appealing foun- an instance of concept C is at least n”.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 3 – Describing Syntax and Semantics CS-4337 Organization of Programming Languages
    !" # Chapter 3 – Describing Syntax and Semantics CS-4337 Organization of Programming Languages Dr. Chris Irwin Davis Email: [email protected] Phone: (972) 883-3574 Office: ECSS 4.705 Chapter 3 Topics • Introduction • The General Problem of Describing Syntax • Formal Methods of Describing Syntax • Attribute Grammars • Describing the Meanings of Programs: Dynamic Semantics 1-2 Introduction •Syntax: the form or structure of the expressions, statements, and program units •Semantics: the meaning of the expressions, statements, and program units •Syntax and semantics provide a language’s definition – Users of a language definition •Other language designers •Implementers •Programmers (the users of the language) 1-3 The General Problem of Describing Syntax: Terminology •A sentence is a string of characters over some alphabet •A language is a set of sentences •A lexeme is the lowest level syntactic unit of a language (e.g., *, sum, begin) •A token is a category of lexemes (e.g., identifier) 1-4 Example: Lexemes and Tokens index = 2 * count + 17 Lexemes Tokens index identifier = equal_sign 2 int_literal * mult_op count identifier + plus_op 17 int_literal ; semicolon Formal Definition of Languages • Recognizers – A recognition device reads input strings over the alphabet of the language and decides whether the input strings belong to the language – Example: syntax analysis part of a compiler - Detailed discussion of syntax analysis appears in Chapter 4 • Generators – A device that generates sentences of a language – One can determine if the syntax of a particular sentence is syntactically correct by comparing it to the structure of the generator 1-5 Formal Methods of Describing Syntax •Formal language-generation mechanisms, usually called grammars, are commonly used to describe the syntax of programming languages.
    [Show full text]
  • Program Description JULY 15, 2021
    Program Description JULY 15, 2021 Utah’s official 529 educational savings program About This Program Description my529 is a 529 plan legally known as a “qualified tuition program.” The Program Description contains information you should know before participating in the my529 plan. It includes information about certain risks, limitations, restrictions and fees in connection with opening and owning a my529 account. Before you invest in my529, carefully read the Program Description and any supplements to it. Purpose, Scope and Limitations of 529 Savings Plans Section 529 qualified tuition programs are intended to be used to save only for qualified education expenses of a beneficiary. Opening a 529 account for any other purpose is inappropriate. A 529 account should not be used to evade federal or state taxes or tax penalties. Investments Are Not Insured or Guaranteed Investments in my529 are not insured or guaranteed by my529, the State of Utah, the Utah Board of Higher Education, the Utah Higher Education Assistance Authority (UHEAA) Board or any other state or federal agency. Your investment could lose value. However, Federal Deposit Insurance Corporation (FDIC) insurance is provided for the FDIC-insured accounts up to certain limits. Units in my529 are not registered with the United States Securities and Exchange Commission (SEC) or with any state securities regulators. Other 529 Plans Non-Utah taxpayers and residents: The state in which you or your beneficiary pay taxes or live may offer a 529 plan that provides state tax or other benefits, such as financial aid, scholarship funds and protection from creditors, not otherwise available to you by investing in my529.
    [Show full text]
  • Topics in Philosophical Logic
    Topics in Philosophical Logic The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Litland, Jon. 2012. Topics in Philosophical Logic. Doctoral dissertation, Harvard University. Citable link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:9527318 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Other Posted Material, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use#LAA © Jon Litland All rights reserved. Warren Goldfarb Jon Litland Topics in Philosophical Logic Abstract In “Proof-Theoretic Justification of Logic”, building on work by Dummett and Prawitz, I show how to construct use-based meaning-theories for the logical constants. The assertability-conditional meaning-theory takes the meaning of the logical constants to be given by their introduction rules; the consequence-conditional meaning-theory takes the meaning of the log- ical constants to be given by their elimination rules. I then consider the question: given a set of introduction (elimination) rules , what are the R strongest elimination (introduction) rules that are validated by an assertabil- ity (consequence) conditional meaning-theory based on ? I prove that the R intuitionistic introduction (elimination) rules are the strongest rules that are validated by the intuitionistic elimination (introduction) rules. I then prove that intuitionistic logic is the strongest logic that can be given either an assertability-conditional or consequence-conditional meaning-theory. In “Grounding Grounding” I discuss the notion of grounding. My discus- sion revolves around the problem of iterated grounding-claims.
    [Show full text]
  • 2 Basic Description Logics 61
    2 Basic Description Logics Franz Baader Werner Nutt Abstract This chapter provides an introduction to Description Logics as a formal language for representing knowledge and reasoning about it. It first gives a short overview of the ideas underlying Description Logics. Then it introduces syntax and semantics, covering the basic constructors that are used in systems or have been introduced in the literature, and the way these constructors can be used to build knowledge bases. Finally, it defines the typical inference problems, shows how they are interrelated, and describes different approaches for effectively solving these problems. Some of the topics that are only briefly mentioned in this chapter will be treated in more detail in subsequent chapters. 2.1 Introduction As sketched in the previous chapter, Description Logics (DLs) is the most recent name1 for a family of knowledge representation (KR) formalisms that represent the knowledge of an application domain (the “world”) by first defining the relevant concepts of the domain (its terminology), and then using these concepts to specify properties of objects and individuals occurring in the domain (the world descrip- tion). As the name Description Logics indicates, one of the characteristics of these languages is that, unlike some of their predecessors, they are equipped with a formal, logic-based semantics. Another distinguished feature is the emphasis on reasoning as a central service: reasoning allows one to infer implicitly represented knowledge from the knowledge that is explicitly contained in the knowledge base. Descrip- tion Logics support inference patterns that occur in many applications of intelligent information processing systems, and which are also used by humans to structure and understand the world: classification of concepts and individuals.
    [Show full text]