Stone Duality and the Representation Theorem

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Stone Duality and the Representation Theorem Boolean Algebras and Topological Spaces Duality and Stone Spaces Representation theorems and examples Non-trivial dual notions Stone Duality and the Representation Theorem Matthew Gwynne 15th December 2008 Matthew Gwynne Stone Duality and the Representation Theorem Boolean Algebras and Topological Spaces Duality and Stone Spaces From Topological Spaces to Boolean Algebras Representation theorems and examples From Boolean Algebras to Topological Spaces Non-trivial dual notions Boolean Algebras and Topological Spaces Matthew Gwynne Stone Duality and the Representation Theorem Boolean Algebras and Topological Spaces Duality and Stone Spaces From Topological Spaces to Boolean Algebras Representation theorems and examples From Boolean Algebras to Topological Spaces Non-trivial dual notions Motivation We have seen already that fields of sets form boolean algebras. Another type of set system with similar properties to fields of sets are the topologies of topological spaces. Question Can we form boolean algebras from topological spaces? If so, how? Matthew Gwynne Stone Duality and the Representation Theorem Boolean Algebras and Topological Spaces Duality and Stone Spaces From Topological Spaces to Boolean Algebras Representation theorems and examples From Boolean Algebras to Topological Spaces Non-trivial dual notions Well, what do we have in an arbitrary topological space? Points in the space. Open sets and closed sets. So, given we already have the notion of a field of sets and the open sets form a nice set system, it is natural to consider such a system for the formation of a boolean algebra. Matthew Gwynne Stone Duality and the Representation Theorem Boolean Algebras and Topological Spaces Duality and Stone Spaces From Topological Spaces to Boolean Algebras Representation theorems and examples From Boolean Algebras to Topological Spaces Non-trivial dual notions So the topology τ of a topological space (X ; τ) is : closed under arbitrary union. closed under finite intersection. However, it is not in general closed under complementation. So we consider the largest subset of τ which is a field of sets, namely the clopen sets. Matthew Gwynne Stone Duality and the Representation Theorem Boolean Algebras and Topological Spaces Duality and Stone Spaces From Topological Spaces to Boolean Algebras Representation theorems and examples From Boolean Algebras to Topological Spaces Non-trivial dual notions The B functor Definition Given a topological space Y = (X ; τ), we define B(Y ) as boolean algebra formed by taking the field of clopen subsets of Y . Matthew Gwynne Stone Duality and the Representation Theorem Boolean Algebras and Topological Spaces Duality and Stone Spaces From Topological Spaces to Boolean Algebras Representation theorems and examples From Boolean Algebras to Topological Spaces Non-trivial dual notions Lemma B has the following properties, given the structure of all topological spaces C and the structure of all boolean algebras D : 1 For every X 2 C,B(X ) 2 D. 2 For every (f : X ! Y ) 2 C,B(f ): B(Y ) ! B(X ) 2 D 3 B(idX ) = idB(X ). 4 B(g ◦ f ) = B(f ) ◦ B(g) Translations which have such properties are called contravariant functors. Matthew Gwynne Stone Duality and the Representation Theorem Boolean Algebras and Topological Spaces Duality and Stone Spaces From Topological Spaces to Boolean Algebras Representation theorems and examples From Boolean Algebras to Topological Spaces Non-trivial dual notions Proof. (B is a contravariant functor). (1) is trivial (it is clear that B(X ) is a field of sets). For (2), we have B(f ) = f −1, so : 1 B(f )(fg) = f −1(fg) = fg (By Def of inverse image). 2 B(f )(A0) = f −1(A0) = f −1(A)0 = B(A)0 (trivial property of total inverse maps) 3 B(f )(A [ C) = f −1(A [ C) = f −1(A) [ f −1(C) = B(f )(A) [ B(f )(C) (trivial property of inverse maps) 4 B(f )(A \ C) = f −1(A \ C) = f −1(A) \ f −1(C) = B(f )(A) \ B(f )(C) (trivial property of inverse maps) (3) is trivial : B(id ) = id−1 = id == id X X X P(X ) (4) is again trivial : B(g ◦ f ) = (g ◦ f )−1 = f −1 ◦ g −1 = B(f ) ◦ B(g). Matthew Gwynne Stone Duality and the Representation Theorem Boolean Algebras and Topological Spaces Duality and Stone Spaces From Topological Spaces to Boolean Algebras Representation theorems and examples From Boolean Algebras to Topological Spaces Non-trivial dual notions So we can translate an arbitrary topological space into a boolean algebra, the question now is : Question Can we do the reverse? Can we translate a boolean algebra into a topological space? Matthew Gwynne Stone Duality and the Representation Theorem Solution Don't look into the individual boolean algebras, but consider the morphisms between them (i.e think from a category theoretical point of view). Boolean Algebras and Topological Spaces Duality and Stone Spaces From Topological Spaces to Boolean Algebras Representation theorems and examples From Boolean Algebras to Topological Spaces Non-trivial dual notions Problem Given such a boolean algebra, what can we actually do to form a topological space? Such structures are rather arbitrary. Matthew Gwynne Stone Duality and the Representation Theorem Boolean Algebras and Topological Spaces Duality and Stone Spaces From Topological Spaces to Boolean Algebras Representation theorems and examples From Boolean Algebras to Topological Spaces Non-trivial dual notions Problem Given such a boolean algebra, what can we actually do to form a topological space? Such structures are rather arbitrary. Solution Don't look into the individual boolean algebras, but consider the morphisms between them (i.e think from a category theoretical point of view). Matthew Gwynne Stone Duality and the Representation Theorem Boolean Algebras and Topological Spaces Duality and Stone Spaces From Topological Spaces to Boolean Algebras Representation theorems and examples From Boolean Algebras to Topological Spaces Non-trivial dual notions The Stone space functor Definition Given a boolean algebra A, the Stone space S(A) is the set of A homomorphisms from A to B2 with the induced topology from 2 . Matthew Gwynne Stone Duality and the Representation Theorem Boolean Algebras and Topological Spaces Duality and Stone Spaces From Topological Spaces to Boolean Algebras Representation theorems and examples From Boolean Algebras to Topological Spaces Non-trivial dual notions As a reminder : Definition The cantor space 2A is defined as the set of all functions from A to B2 = f0; 1g with the topology such that if one fixes an a 2 A and a b 2 B2 then the set ff : f (a) = bg is an open set in the subbase of 2A, i.e all open sets of 2A may be formed from the finite intersection (to form the base) of elements in the subbase and then arbitrary unions of elements in the base. Definition Given a subset U of a topological space (X ; τ), the induced topology of U from (X ; τ) is the τU := fU \ O j O 2 τg, giving the induced topological space (U; τU ). Matthew Gwynne Stone Duality and the Representation Theorem Boolean Algebras and Topological Spaces Duality and Stone Spaces From Topological Spaces to Boolean Algebras Representation theorems and examples From Boolean Algebras to Topological Spaces Non-trivial dual notions Lemma S is a contravariant functor from the boolean algebras to the topological spaces. Matthew Gwynne Stone Duality and the Representation Theorem Boolean Algebras and Topological Spaces Duality and Stone Spaces From Topological Spaces to Boolean Algebras Representation theorems and examples From Boolean Algebras to Topological Spaces Non-trivial dual notions Proof. (S is a contravariant functor) - Part 1. (1) follows from the definition. For (2), given a homomorphism f , we have S(f ): S(B) ! S(A) with S(f )(h) = h ◦ f , and must show S(f ) is continuous. It suffices to show that the inverse image of elements in the subbase of S(A) are clopen in S(B). So consider, for some a 2 A, b 2 B2 : S(f )−1(fh : h(a) = bg) = fg : S(f )(g) 2 h : h(a) = bg = fg : S(f )(g)(a) = bg = fg :(g ◦ f )(a) = bg = fg : g(f (a)) = bg So the inverse image of such a subbase element in S(A) is a subbase element in S(B). Matthew Gwynne Stone Duality and the Representation Theorem Boolean Algebras and Topological Spaces Duality and Stone Spaces From Topological Spaces to Boolean Algebras Representation theorems and examples From Boolean Algebras to Topological Spaces Non-trivial dual notions Proof. (S is a contravariant functor) - Part 2. (3) follows trivially : S(idB )(h) = h ◦ idB = h = idS(B)(h). (4) again follows trivially : S(g ◦ f ) = h ◦ g ◦ f = S(f )(h ◦ g) = S(f )(S(g)(h)) = (S(f ) ◦ S(g))(h). Matthew Gwynne Stone Duality and the Representation Theorem Boolean Algebras and Topological Spaces Duality and Stone Spaces Boolean algebras and dual algebras Representation theorems and examples Stone spaces and the Stone Duality Non-trivial dual notions Duality and Stone Spaces Matthew Gwynne Stone Duality and the Representation Theorem Boolean Algebras and Topological Spaces Duality and Stone Spaces Boolean algebras and dual algebras Representation theorems and examples Stone spaces and the Stone Duality Non-trivial dual notions The question that now arises is : Question Are these functors inverse to each other? Are the boolean algebras and topological spaces dual to each other, i.e is S(B(A)) isomorphic to A, and is S(B(X )) homeomorphic to X ? Matthew Gwynne Stone Duality and the Representation Theorem Boolean Algebras and Topological Spaces Duality and Stone Spaces Boolean algebras and dual algebras Representation theorems and examples Stone spaces and the Stone Duality Non-trivial dual notions Lemma Given a boolean algebra A, B(S(A)) is isomorphic to A. Matthew Gwynne Stone Duality and the Representation Theorem Boolean Algebras and Topological Spaces Duality and Stone Spaces Boolean algebras and dual algebras Representation theorems and examples Stone spaces and the Stone Duality Non-trivial dual notions Proof.
Recommended publications
  • Stone Coalgebras
    Electronic Notes in Theoretical Computer Science 82 No. 1 (2003) URL: http://www.elsevier.nl/locate/entcs/volume82.html 21 pages Stone Coalgebras Clemens Kupke 1 Alexander Kurz 2 Yde Venema 3 Abstract In this paper we argue that the category of Stone spaces forms an interesting base category for coalgebras, in particular, if one considers the Vietoris functor as an analogue to the power set functor. We prove that the so-called descriptive general frames, which play a fundamental role in the semantics of modal logics, can be seen as Stone coalgebras in a natural way. This yields a duality between the category of modal algebras and that of coalgebras over the Vietoris functor. Building on this idea, we introduce the notion of a Vietoris polynomial functor over the category of Stone spaces. For each such functor T we establish a link between the category of T -sorted Boolean algebras with operators and the category of Stone coalgebras over T . Applications include a general theorem providing final coalgebras in the category of T -coalgebras. Key words: coalgebra, Stone spaces, Vietoris topology, modal logic, descriptive general frames, Kripke polynomial functors 1 Introduction Technically, every coalgebra is based on a carrier which itself is an object in the so-called base category. Most of the literature on coalgebras either focuses on Set as the base category, or takes a very general perspective, allowing arbitrary base categories, possibly restricted by some constraints. The aim of this paper is to argue that, besides Set, the category Stone of Stone spaces is of relevance as a base category.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:2101.00942V2 [Math.CT] 31 May 2021 01Ascainfrcmuigmachinery
    Reiterman’s Theorem on Finite Algebras for a Monad JIŘÍ ADÁMEK∗, Czech Technical University in Prague, Czech Recublic, and Technische Universität Braun- schweig, Germany LIANG-TING CHEN, Academia Sinica, Taiwan STEFAN MILIUS†, Friedrich-Alexander-Universität Erlangen-Nürnberg, Germany HENNING URBAT‡, Friedrich-Alexander-Universität Erlangen-Nürnberg, Germany Profinite equations are an indispensable tool for the algebraic classification of formal languages. Reiterman’s theorem states that they precisely specify pseudovarieties, i.e. classes of finite algebras closed under finite products, subalgebras and quotients. In this paper, Reiterman’s theorem is generalized to finite Eilenberg- Moore algebras for a monad T on a category D: we prove that a class of finite T-algebras is a pseudovariety iff it is presentable by profinite equations. As a key technical tool, we introduce the concept of a profinite monad T associated to the monad T, which gives a categorical view of the construction of the space of profinite terms. b CCS Concepts: • Theory of computation → Algebraic language theory. Additional Key Words and Phrases: Monad, Pseudovariety, Profinite Algebras ACM Reference Format: Jiří Adámek, Liang-Ting Chen, Stefan Milius, and Henning Urbat. 2021. Reiterman’s Theorem on Finite Al- gebras for a Monad. 1, 1 (June 2021), 49 pages. https://doi.org/10.1145/nnnnnnn.nnnnnnn 1 INTRODUCTION One of the main principles of both mathematics and computer science is the specification of struc- tures in terms of equational properties. The first systematic study of equations as mathematical objects was pursued by Birkhoff [7] who proved that a class of algebraic structures over a finitary signature Σ can be specified by equations between Σ-terms if and only if it is closed under quo- tient algebras (a.k.a.
    [Show full text]
  • Topological Duality and Lattice Expansions Part I: a Topological Construction of Canonical Extensions
    TOPOLOGICAL DUALITY AND LATTICE EXPANSIONS PART I: A TOPOLOGICAL CONSTRUCTION OF CANONICAL EXTENSIONS M. ANDREW MOSHIER AND PETER JIPSEN 1. INTRODUCTION The two main objectives of this paper are (a) to prove topological duality theorems for semilattices and bounded lattices, and (b) to show that the topological duality from (a) provides a construction of canonical extensions of bounded lattices. The paper is first of two parts. The main objective of the sequel is to establish a characterization of lattice expansions, i.e., lattices with additional operations, in the topological setting built in this paper. Regarding objective (a), consider the following simple question: Is there a subcategory of Top that is dually equivalent to Lat? Here, Top is the category of topological spaces and continuous maps and Lat is the category of bounded lattices and lattice homomorphisms. To date, the question has been answered positively either by specializing Lat or by generalizing Top. The earliest examples are of the former sort. Tarski [Tar29] (treated in English, e.g., in [BD74]) showed that every complete atomic Boolean lattice is represented by a powerset. Taking some historical license, we can say this result shows that the category of complete atomic Boolean lattices with complete lat- tice homomorphisms is dually equivalent to the category of discrete topological spaces. Birkhoff [Bir37] showed that every finite distributive lattice is represented by the lower sets of a finite partial order. Again, we can now say that this shows that the category of finite distributive lattices is dually equivalent to the category of finite T0 spaces and con- tinuous maps.
    [Show full text]
  • The Representation Theorem of Persistence Revisited and Generalized
    Journal of Applied and Computational Topology https://doi.org/10.1007/s41468-018-0015-3 The representation theorem of persistence revisited and generalized René Corbet1 · Michael Kerber1 Received: 9 November 2017 / Accepted: 15 June 2018 © The Author(s) 2018 Abstract The Representation Theorem by Zomorodian and Carlsson has been the starting point of the study of persistent homology under the lens of representation theory. In this work, we give a more accurate statement of the original theorem and provide a complete and self-contained proof. Furthermore, we generalize the statement from the case of linear sequences of R-modules to R-modules indexed over more general monoids. This generalization subsumes the Representation Theorem of multidimen- sional persistence as a special case. Keywords Computational topology · Persistence modules · Persistent homology · Representation theory Mathematics Subject Classifcation 06F25 · 16D90 · 16W50 · 55U99 · 68W30 1 Introduction Persistent homology, introduced by Edelsbrunner et al. (2002), is a multi-scale extension of classical homology theory. The idea is to track how homological fea- tures appear and disappear in a shape when the scale parameter is increasing. This data can be summarized by a barcode where each bar corresponds to a homology class that appears in the process and represents the range of scales where the class is present. The usefulness of this paradigm in the context of real-world data sets has led to the term topological data analysis; see the surveys (Carlsson 2009; Ghrist 2008; Edelsbrunner and Morozov 2012; Vejdemo-Johansson 2014; Kerber 2016) and textbooks (Edelsbrunner and Harer 2010; Oudot 2015) for various use cases. * René Corbet [email protected] Michael Kerber [email protected] 1 Institute of Geometry, Graz University of Technology, Kopernikusgasse 24, 8010 Graz, Austria Vol.:(0123456789)1 3 R.
    [Show full text]
  • Bitopological Duality for Distributive Lattices and Heyting Algebras
    BITOPOLOGICAL DUALITY FOR DISTRIBUTIVE LATTICES AND HEYTING ALGEBRAS GURAM BEZHANISHVILI, NICK BEZHANISHVILI, DAVID GABELAIA, ALEXANDER KURZ Abstract. We introduce pairwise Stone spaces as a natural bitopological generalization of Stone spaces—the duals of Boolean algebras—and show that they are exactly the bitopolog- ical duals of bounded distributive lattices. The category PStone of pairwise Stone spaces is isomorphic to the category Spec of spectral spaces and to the category Pries of Priestley spaces. In fact, the isomorphism of Spec and Pries is most naturally seen through PStone by first establishing that Pries is isomorphic to PStone, and then showing that PStone is isomorphic to Spec. We provide the bitopological and spectral descriptions of many alge- braic concepts important for the study of distributive lattices. We also give new bitopological and spectral dualities for Heyting algebras, co-Heyting algebras, and bi-Heyting algebras, thus providing two new alternatives of Esakia’s duality. 1. Introduction It is widely considered that the beginning of duality theory was Stone’s groundbreaking work in the mid 30ies on the dual equivalence of the category Bool of Boolean algebras and Boolean algebra homomorphism and the category Stone of compact Hausdorff zero- dimensional spaces, which became known as Stone spaces, and continuous functions. In 1937 Stone [28] extended this to the dual equivalence of the category DLat of bounded distributive lattices and bounded lattice homomorphisms and the category Spec of what later became known as spectral spaces and spectral maps. Spectral spaces provide a generalization of Stone 1 spaces. Unlike Stone spaces, spectral spaces are not Hausdorff (not even T1) , and as a result, are more difficult to work with.
    [Show full text]
  • Representations of Direct Products of Finite Groups
    Pacific Journal of Mathematics REPRESENTATIONS OF DIRECT PRODUCTS OF FINITE GROUPS BURTON I. FEIN Vol. 20, No. 1 September 1967 PACIFIC JOURNAL OF MATHEMATICS Vol. 20, No. 1, 1967 REPRESENTATIONS OF DIRECT PRODUCTS OF FINITE GROUPS BURTON FEIN Let G be a finite group and K an arbitrary field. We denote by K(G) the group algebra of G over K. Let G be the direct product of finite groups Gι and G2, G — G1 x G2, and let Mi be an irreducible iΓ(G;)-module, i— 1,2. In this paper we study the structure of Mί9 M2, the outer tensor product of Mi and M2. While Mi, M2 is not necessarily an irreducible K(G)~ module, we prove below that it is completely reducible and give criteria for it to be irreducible. These results are applied to the question of whether the tensor product of division algebras of a type arising from group representation theory is a division algebra. We call a division algebra D over K Z'-derivable if D ~ Hom^s) (Mf M) for some finite group G and irreducible ϋΓ(G)- module M. If B(K) is the Brauer group of K, the set BQ(K) of classes of central simple Z-algebras having division algebra components which are iΓ-derivable forms a subgroup of B(K). We show also that B0(K) has infinite index in B(K) if K is an algebraic number field which is not an abelian extension of the rationale. All iΓ(G)-modules considered are assumed to be unitary finite dimensional left if((τ)-modules.
    [Show full text]
  • Heyting Duality
    Heyting Duality Vikraman Choudhury April, 2018 1 Heyting Duality Pairs of “equivalent” concepts or phenomena are ubiquitous in mathematics, and dualities relate such two different, even opposing concepts. Stone’s Representa- tion theorem (1936), due to Marshall Stone, states the duality between Boolean algebras and topological spaces. It shows that, for classical propositional logic, the Lindenbaum-Tarski algebra of a set of propositions is isomorphic to the clopen subsets of the set of its valuations, thereby exposing an algebraic viewpoint on logic. In this essay, we consider the case for intuitionistic propositional logic, that is, a duality result for Heyting algebras. It borrows heavily from an exposition of Stone and Heyting duality by van Schijndel and Landsman [2017]. 1.1 Preliminaries Definition (Lattice). A lattice is a poset which admits all finite meets and joins. Categorically, it is a (0, 1) − 푐푎푡푒푔표푟푦 (or a thin category) with all finite limits and finite colimits. Alternatively, a lattice is an algebraic structure in the signature (∧, ∨, 0, 1) that satisfies the following axioms. • ∧ and ∨ are each idempotent, commutative, and associative with respective identities 1 and 0. • the absorption laws, 푥 ∨ (푥 ∧ 푦) = 푥, and 푥 ∧ (푥 ∨ 푦) = 푥. Definition (Distributive lattice). A distributive lattice is a lattice in which ∧and ∨ distribute over each other, that is, the following distributivity axioms are satisfied. Categorically, this makes it a distributive category. 1 • 푥 ∨ (푦 ∧ 푧) = (푥 ∨ 푦) ∧ (푥 ∨ 푧) • 푥 ∧ (푦 ∨ 푧) = (푥 ∧ 푦) ∨ (푥 ∧ 푧) Definition (Complements in a lattice). A complement of an element 푥 of a lattice is an element 푦 such that, 푥 ∧ 푦 = 0 and 푥 ∨ 푦 = 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Bitopological Duality for Distributive Lattices and Heyting Algebras Guram Bezhanishvili New Mexico State University
    Chapman University Chapman University Digital Commons Engineering Faculty Articles and Research Fowler School of Engineering 2010 Bitopological Duality for Distributive Lattices and Heyting Algebras Guram Bezhanishvili New Mexico State University Nick Bezhanishvili University of Leicester David Gabelaia Razmadze Mathematical Institute Alexander Kurz Chapman University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.chapman.edu/engineering_articles Part of the Algebra Commons, Logic and Foundations Commons, Other Computer Engineering Commons, Other Computer Sciences Commons, and the Other Mathematics Commons Recommended Citation G. Bezhanishvili, N. Bezhanishvili, D. Gabelaia, and A. Kurz, “Bitopological duality for distributive lattices and Heyting algebras,” Mathematical Structures in Computer Science, vol. 20, no. 03, pp. 359–393, Jun. 2010. DOI: 10.1017/S0960129509990302 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Fowler School of Engineering at Chapman University Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Engineering Faculty Articles and Research by an authorized administrator of Chapman University Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Bitopological Duality for Distributive Lattices and Heyting Algebras Comments This is a pre-copy-editing, author-produced PDF of an article accepted for publication in Mathematical Structures in Computer Science, volume 20, number 3, in 2010 following peer review. The definitive publisher- authenticated
    [Show full text]
  • REVERSIBLE FILTERS 1. Introduction a Topological Space X Is Reversible
    REVERSIBLE FILTERS ALAN DOW AND RODRIGO HERNANDEZ-GUTI´ ERREZ´ Abstract. A space is reversible if every continuous bijection of the space onto itself is a homeomorphism. In this paper we study the question of which countable spaces with a unique non-isolated point are reversible. By Stone duality, these spaces correspond to closed subsets in the Cech-Stoneˇ compact- ification of the natural numbers β!. From this, the following natural problem arises: given a space X that is embeddable in β!, is it possible to embed X in such a way that the associated filter of neighborhoods defines a reversible (or non-reversible) space? We give the solution to this problem in some cases. It is especially interesting whether the image of the required embedding is a weak P -set. 1. Introduction A topological space X is reversible if every time that f : X ! X is a continuous bijection, then f is a homeomorphism. This class of spaces was defined in [10], where some examples of reversible spaces were given. These include compact spaces, Euclidean spaces Rn (by the Brouwer invariance of domain theorem) and the space ! [ fpg, where p is an ultrafilter, as a subset of β!. This last example is of interest to us. Given a filter F ⊂ P(!), consider the space ξ(F) = ! [ fFg, where every point of ! is isolated and every neighborhood of F is of the form fFg [ A with A 2 F. Spaces of the form ξ(F) have been studied before, for example by Garc´ıa-Ferreira and Uzc´ategi([6] and [7]).
    [Show full text]
  • Some Limits of Boolean Algebras
    SOME LIMITS OF BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS FRANKLIN HAIMO 1. Introduction. Inverse systems of topological spaces and direct and inverse systems of Abelian groups and resulting applications thereof to algebraic topology have been studied intensively, and the techniques employed are now standard [2]. (Numbers in brackets refer to the bibliography at the end of the paper.) We shall apply some of these ideas to the treatment of sets of Boolean algebras in order to obtain, in the inverse case, a representation, and, in both cases, some information about the ideals and about the decompositions of certain algebras. For instance, it is well known [l] that the cardinal product B* of a set {Ba} of Boolean algebras, indexed by a class A, is also a Boolean algebra. Moreover, if each Ba is m-complete for some fixed cardinal m [3], then B* is m-complete. When A is a set partly ordered by = and directed thereby, and when the Ba form an inverse system (to be defined below), we shall show that the re- sulting inverse limit set is a Boolean algebra, a subalgebra of B*, and a similar result will hold in the direct case, at least in part.1 For each nonfinite Boolean algebra B, there will be constructed a nontrivial inverse limit representation of B, the inverse limit of all principal ideals [3] of B (with repetitions). In the direct case, ideals in the limit algebra (and the homomorphic algebras which they generate) will turn out to be direct limits of like objects. Direct decomposition into ideals of the direct limit takes place (it will be seen) if there is a similar decomposition in each Ba.
    [Show full text]
  • Representation Theory of Finite Groups
    Representation Theory of Finite Groups Benjamin Steinberg School of Mathematics and Statistics Carleton University [email protected] December 15, 2009 Preface This book arose out of course notes for a fourth year undergraduate/first year graduate course that I taught at Carleton University. The goal was to present group representation theory at a level that is accessible to students who have not yet studied module theory and who are unfamiliar with tensor products. For this reason, the Wedderburn theory of semisimple algebras is completely avoided. Instead, I have opted for a Fourier analysis approach. This sort of approach is normally taken in books with a more analytic flavor; such books, however, invariably contain material on representations of com- pact groups, something that I would also consider beyond the scope of an undergraduate text. So here I have done my best to blend the analytic and the algebraic viewpoints in order to keep things accessible. For example, Frobenius reciprocity is treated from a character point of view to evade use of the tensor product. The only background required for this book is a basic knowledge of linear algebra and group theory, as well as familiarity with the definition of a ring. The proof of Burnside's theorem makes use of a small amount of Galois theory (up to the fundamental theorem) and so should be skipped if used in a course for which Galois theory is not a prerequisite. Many things are proved in more detail than one would normally expect in a textbook; this was done to make things easier on undergraduates trying to learn what is usually considered graduate level material.
    [Show full text]
  • The Algebraic Theory of Semigroups the Algebraic Theory of Semigroups
    http://dx.doi.org/10.1090/surv/007.1 The Algebraic Theory of Semigroups The Algebraic Theory of Semigroups A. H. Clifford G. B. Preston American Mathematical Society Providence, Rhode Island 2000 Mathematics Subject Classification. Primary 20-XX. International Standard Serial Number 0076-5376 International Standard Book Number 0-8218-0271-2 Library of Congress Catalog Card Number: 61-15686 Copying and reprinting. Material in this book may be reproduced by any means for educational and scientific purposes without fee or permission with the exception of reproduction by services that collect fees for delivery of documents and provided that the customary acknowledgment of the source is given. This consent does not extend to other kinds of copying for general distribution, for advertising or promotional purposes, or for resale. Requests for permission for commercial use of material should be addressed to the Assistant to the Publisher, American Mathematical Society, P. O. Box 6248, Providence, Rhode Island 02940-6248. Requests can also be made by e-mail to reprint-permissionQams.org. Excluded from these provisions is material in articles for which the author holds copyright. In such cases, requests for permission to use or reprint should be addressed directly to the author(s). (Copyright ownership is indicated in the notice in the lower right-hand corner of the first page of each article.) © Copyright 1961 by the American Mathematical Society. All rights reserved. Printed in the United States of America. Second Edition, 1964 Reprinted with corrections, 1977. The American Mathematical Society retains all rights except those granted to the United States Government.
    [Show full text]