On the Minkowski Measure 2
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Measure Theory and Probability Theory
Measure Theory and Probability Theory Stéphane Dupraz In this chapter, we aim at building a theory of probabilities that extends to any set the theory of probability we have for finite sets (with which you are assumed to be familiar). For a finite set with N elements Ω = {ω1, ..., ωN }, a probability P takes any n positive numbers p1, ..., pN that sum to one, and attributes to any subset S of Ω the number (S) = P p . Extending this definition to infinitely countable sets such as P i/ωi∈S i N poses no difficulty: we can in the same way assign a positive number to each integer n ∈ N and require that P∞ 1 P n=1 pn = 1. We can then define the probability of a subset S ⊆ N as P(S) = n∈S pn. Things get more complicated when we move to uncountable sets such as the real line R. To be sure, it is possible to assign a positive number to each real number. But how to get from these positive numbers to the probability of any subset of R?2 To get a definition of a probability that applies without a hitch to uncountable sets, we give in the strategy we used for finite and countable sets and start from scratch. The definition of a probability we are going to use was borrowed from measure theory by Kolmogorov in 1933, which explains the title of this chapter. What do probabilities have to do with measurement? Simple: assigning a probability to an event is measuring the likeliness of this event. -
Results Real Analysis I and II, MATH 5453-5463, 2006-2007
Main results Real Analysis I and II, MATH 5453-5463, 2006-2007 Section Homework Introduction. 1.3 Operations with sets. DeMorgan Laws. 1.4 Proposition 1. Existence of the smallest algebra containing C. 2.5 Open and closed sets. 2.6 Continuous functions. Proposition 18. Hw #1. p.16 #9, 11, 17, 18; p.19 #19. 2.7 Borel sets. p.49 #40, 42, 43; p.53 #53*. 3.2 Outer measure. Proposition 1. Outer measure of an interval. Proposition 2. Subadditivity of the outer measure. Proposition 5. Approximation by open sets. 3.3 Measurable sets. Lemma 6. Measurability of sets of outer measure zero. Lemma 7. Measurability of the union. Hw #2. p.55 #1-4; p.58 # 7, 8. Theorem 10. Measurable sets form a sigma-algebra. Lemma 11. Interval is measurable. Theorem 12. Borel sets are measurable. Proposition 13. Sigma additivity of the measure. Proposition 14. Continuity of the measure. Proposition 15. Approximation by open and closed sets. Hw #3. p.64 #9-11, 13, 14. 3.4 A nonmeasurable set. 3.5 Measurable functions. Proposition 18. Equivalent definitions of measurability. Proposition 19. Sums and products of measurable functions. Theorem 20. Infima and suprema of measurable functions. Hw #4. p.70 #18-22. 3.6 Littlewood's three principles. Egoroff's theorem. Lusin's theorem. 4.2 Prop.2. Lebesgue's integral of a simple function and its props. Lebesgue's integral of a bounded measurable function. Proposition 3. Criterion of integrability. Proposition 5. Properties of integrals of bounded functions. Proposition 6. Bounded convergence theorem. 4.3 Lebesgue integral of a nonnegative function and its properties. -
Bolles E.B. Einstein Defiant.. Genius Versus Genius in the Quantum
Selected other titles by Edmund Blair Bolles The Ice Finders: How a Poet, a Professor, and a Politician Discovered the Ice Age A Second Way of Knowing: The Riddle of Human Perception Remembering and Forgetting: Inquiries into the Nature of Memory So Much to Say: How to Help Your Child Learn Galileo’s Commandment: An Anthology of Great Science Writing (editor) Edmund Blair Bolles Joseph Henry Press Washington, DC Joseph Henry Press • 500 Fifth Street, NW • Washington, DC 20001 The Joseph Henry Press, an imprint of the National Academies Press, was created with the goal of making books on science, technology, and health more widely available to professionals and the public. Joseph Henry was one of the founders of the National Academy of Sciences and a leader in early American science. Any opinions, findings, conclusions, or recommendations expressed in this volume are those of the author and do not necessarily reflect the views of the National Academy of Sciences or its affiliated institutions. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Bolles, Edmund Blair, 1942- Einstein defiant : genius versus genius in the quantum revolution / by Edmund Blair Bolles. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references. ISBN 0-309-08998-0 (hbk.) 1. Quantum theory—History—20th century. 2. Physics—Europe—History— 20th century. 3. Einstein, Albert, 1879-1955. 4. Bohr, Niels Henrik David, 1885-1962. I. Title. QC173.98.B65 2004 530.12′09—dc22 2003023735 Copyright 2004 by Edmund Blair Bolles. All rights reserved. Printed in the United States of America. To Kelso Walker and the rest of the crew, volunteers all. -
Chao-Dyn/9402001 7 Feb 94
chao-dyn/9402001 7 Feb 94 DESY ISSN Quantum Chaos January Einsteins Problem of The study of quantum chaos in complex systems constitutes a very fascinating and active branch of presentday physics chemistry and mathematics It is not wellknown however that this eld of research was initiated by a question rst p osed by Einstein during a talk delivered in Berlin on May concerning Quantum Chaos the relation b etween classical and quantum mechanics of strongly chaotic systems This seems historically almost imp ossible since quantum mechanics was not yet invented and the phenomenon of chaos was hardly acknowledged by physicists in While we are celebrating the seventyfth anniversary of our alma mater the Frank Steiner Hamburgische Universitat which was inaugurated on May it is interesting to have a lo ok up on the situation in physics in those days Most I I Institut f urTheoretische Physik UniversitatHamburg physicists will probably characterize that time as the age of the old quantum Lurup er Chaussee D Hamburg Germany theory which started with Planck in and was dominated then by Bohrs ingenious but paradoxical mo del of the atom and the BohrSommerfeld quanti zation rules for simple quantum systems Some will asso ciate those years with Einsteins greatest contribution the creation of general relativity culminating in the generally covariant form of the eld equations of gravitation which were found by Einstein in the year and indep endently by the mathematician Hilb ert at the same time In his talk in May Einstein studied the -
Abelian Group, 521, 526 Absolute Value, 190 Accumulation, Point Of
Index Abelian group, 521, 526 A-set. SeeAnalytic set Absolutevalue, 190 Asymptoticallyequal. 479 Accumulation, point of, 196 Atlas , 231; of holomorphically related Adjoint differentialform, 157, 167 charts, 245 Adjoint operator, 403 Atomic theory, 415 Adjoint space, 397 Automorphism group, 510, 511 Algebra, 524; Boolean, 91, 92; Axiomatic method, in geometry, 507-508 fundamentaltheorem of, 195-196; homo logical, 519-520; normed, 516 BAIREclasses, 460; first, 460, 462, 463; Almost all, 479 of functions, 448 Almost continuous, 460 BAIREcondition, 464 Almost equal, 479 BAIREfunction, 464, 473; non-, 474 Almost everywhere, 70 BAIREspace, 464 Almost linear equation, 321, 323 BAIREsystem, of functions, 459, 460 Alternating differentialform, 185; BAIREtheorem, 448, 460, 462 differentialoperations for, 159-165; BANACH, S., 516 theory of, vi, 143 BANACHfixed point theorem, 423 Alternative theorem, 296, 413 BANACHspace, 338, 340, 393, 399, 432, Analysis, v, 1; axiomaticmethod in, 435,437, 516; adjoint, 400; 512-518; complex, vi ; functional, conjugate, 400; dual, 400; theory of, vi 391; harmonic, 518; and number BANACHtheorem, 446, 447 theory, 500-501 Band spectra, 418 Analytic function, definedby function BAYES theorem, 109 element, 242 BELTRAMIdifferential equation, 325 Analytic numbertheory, 480 BERNOULLI, DANIEL, 23 Analytic operation, 468 BERNOULLI, JACOB, 89, 360 Analytic set, 448, 458, 465, 468, 469; BERNOULLI, JOHANN, 23 linear, 466 BERNOULLIdistribution, 96 Angle-preservingtransformation, 194 BERNOULLIlaw, of large numbers, 116 a-points, -
2.1.3 Outer Measures and Construction of Measures Recall the Construction of Lebesgue Measure on the Real Line
CHAPTER 2. THE LEBESGUE INTEGRAL I 11 2.1.3 Outer measures and construction of measures Recall the construction of Lebesgue measure on the real line. There are various approaches to construct the Lebesgue measure on the real line. For example, consider the collection of finite union of sets of the form ]a; b]; ] − 1; b]; ]a; 1[ R: This collection is an algebra A but not a sigma-algebra (this has been discussed on p.7). A natural measure on A is given by the length of an interval. One attempts to measure the size of any subset S of R covering it by countably many intervals (recall also that R can be covered by countably many intervals) and we define this quantity by 1 1 X [ m∗(S) = inff jAkj : Ak 2 A;S ⊂ Akg (2.7) k=1 k=1 where jAkj denotes the length of the interval Ak. However, m∗(S) is not a measure since it is not additive, which we do not prove here. It is only sigma- subadditive, that is k k [ X m∗ Sn ≤ m∗(Sn) n=1 n=1 for any countable collection (Sn) of subsets of R. Alternatively one could choose coverings by open intervals (see the exercises, see also B.Dacorogna, Analyse avanc´eepour math´ematiciens)Note that the quantity m∗ coincides with the length for any set in A, that is the measure on A (this is surprisingly the more difficult part!). Also note that the sigma-subadditivity implies that m∗(A) = 0 for any countable set since m∗(fpg) = 0 for any p 2 R. -
Front Matter
Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-88508-9 - New Directions in Linear Acoustics and Vibration: Quantum Chaos, Random Matrix Theory, and Complexity Edited by Matthew Wright and Richard Weaver Frontmatter More information NEW DIRECTIONS IN LINEAR ACOUSTICS AND VIBRATION The field of acoustics is of immense industrial and scientific importance. The subject is built on the foundations of linear acoustics, which is widely re- garded as so mature that it is fully encapsulated in the physics texts of the 1950s. This view was changed by developments in physics such as the study of quantum chaos. Developments in physics throughout the last four decades, often equally applicable to both quantum and linear acoustic problems but overwhelmingly more often expressed in the language of the former, have explored this. There is a significant new amount of theory that can be used to address problems in linear acoustics and vibration, but only a small amount of reported work does so. This book is an attempt to bridge the gap be- tween theoreticians and practitioners, as well as the gap between quantum and acoustic. Tutorial chapters provide introductions to each of the major aspects of the physical theory and are written using the appropriate termi- nology of the acoustical community. The book will act as a quick-start guide to the new methods while providing a wide-ranging introduction to the phys- ical concepts. Matthew Wright is a senior lecturer in Acoustics at the Institute of Sound and Vibration Research (ISVR). His B.Eng. was in engineering acoustics and vibration, and his Ph.D. -
Lecture Notes for Data and Uncertainty (First Part)
Lecture Notes for Data and Uncertainty (first part) Jochen Bröcker December 29, 2020 1 Introduction Sections 1 to 10 will cover probability theory, integration, and a bit of statis- tics (roughly in that order). The second part (Sect. 11-13) –not part of these notes– will explain an important technique in statistics called Monte Carlo simulations. This introduction will motivate probability theory and statistics a little bit, and in particular why we need concepts from measure theory and integration, which is often perceived as abstract and complicated. Probability It is not easy to explain what probability theory is about without sounding tautological. One might say that it allows to quantify uncertainty or chance, but then what do we mean by “uncertainty” or “chance”? De Moivre’s seminal textbook “The Doctrine of Chances” [dM67] is widely considered as the first textbook on probability theory, and the theory has undergone enormous developments since then. In particular, there is an ax- iomatic framework which has been universally adopted and which we will discuss in this course. But even though De Moivre’s book was first published in 1718, there is still some debate as to the interpretation of probability theory, or in other words, to what this nice axiomatic framework actually pertains. Different interpretations of probability have been put forward, but somewhat fortunately to the student, the differences matter little as far as the mathematics is concerned. Nonetheless, we will briefly mention the most prominent interpretations of probability -
Measure Theory
Appendix A Measure theory In this appendix we collect some important notions from measure theory. The goal is not to present a self-contained presentation, but rather to establish the basic definitions and theorems from the theory for reference in the main text. As such, the presentation omits certain existence theorems and many of the proofs of other theorems (although references are given). The focus is strongly on finite (e.g. probability-) measures, in places at the expense of generality. Some background in elementary set-theory and analysis is required. As a comprehensive reference, we note Kingman and Taylor (1966) [52], alternatives being Dudley (1989) [29] and Billingsley (1986) [15]. A.1 Sets and sigma-algebras Rough setup: set operations, monotony of sequences of subsets, set-limits, sigma-algebra’s, measurable spaces, set-functions, product spaces. Definition A.1.1. A measurable space (Ω, F ) consists of a set Ω and a σ-algebra F of subsets of Ω. A.2 Measures Rough setup: set-functions, (signed) measures, probability measures, sigma-additivity, sigma- finiteness Theorem A.2.1. Let (Ω, F ) be a measurable space with measure µ : F [0, ]. Then, → ∞ (i) for any monotone decreasing sequence (Fn)n 1 in F such that µ(Fn) < for some n, ≥ ∞ ∞ lim µ(Fn)=µ Fn , (A.1) n →∞ n=1 91 92 Measure theory (ii) for any monotone increasing sequence (Gn)n 1 in F , ≥ ∞ lim µ(Gn)=µ Gn , (A.2) n →∞ n=1 Theorem A.2.1) is sometimes referred to as the continuity theorem for measures, because if we view F as the monotone limit lim F , (A.1) can be read as lim µ(F )=µ(lim F ), ∩n n n n n n n expressing continuity from below. -
Geometry of Chaos
Part I Geometry of chaos e start out with a recapitulation of the basic notions of dynamics. Our aim is narrow; we keep the exposition focused on prerequisites to the applications to W be developed in this text. We assume that the reader is familiar with dynamics on the level of the introductory texts mentioned in remark 1.1, and concentrate here on developing intuition about what a dynamical system can do. It will be a broad stroke description, since describing all possible behaviors of dynamical systems is beyond human ken. While for a novice there is no shortcut through this lengthy detour, a sophisticated traveler might bravely skip this well-trodden territory and embark upon the journey at chapter 18. The fate has handed you a law of nature. What are you to do with it? 1. Define your dynamical system (M; f ): the space M of its possible states, and the law f t of their evolution in time. 2. Pin it down locally–is there anything about it that is stationary? Try to determine its equilibria / fixed points (chapter2). 3. Cut across it, represent as a return map from a section to a section (chapter3). 4. Explore the neighborhood by linearizing the flow; check the linear stability of its equilibria / fixed points, their stability eigen-directions (chapters4 and5). 5. Does your system have a symmetry? If so, you must use it (chapters 10 to 12). Slice & dice it (chapter 13). 6. Go global: train by partitioning the state space of 1-dimensional maps. Label the regions by symbolic dynamics (chapter 14). -
PAC Learnability Under Non-Atomic Measures: a Problem by Vidyasagar
PAC learnability under non-atomic measures: a problem by Vidyasagar Vladimir Pestov Departamento de Matem´atica, Universidade Federal de Santa Catarina, Campus Universit´ario Trindade, CEP 88.040-900 Florian´opolis-SC, Brasil 1 Department of Mathematics and Statistics, University of Ottawa, 585 King Edward Avenue, Ottawa, Ontario, K1N6N5 Canada 2 Abstract In response to a 1997 problem of M. Vidyasagar, we state a criterion for PAC learnability of a concept class C under the family of all non-atomic (diffuse) measures on the domain Ω. The uniform Glivenko– Cantelli property with respect to non-atomic measures is no longer a necessary condition, and consistent learnability cannot in general be expected. Our criterion is stated in terms of a combinatorial parameter VC(C mod ω1) which we call the VC dimension of C modulo countable sets. The new parameter is obtained by “thickening up” single points in the definition of VC dimension to uncountable “clusters”. Equivalently, VC(C mod ω1) d if and only if every countable subclass of C has VC dimension d outside a countable subset of Ω. The≤ new parameter can be also expressed as the classical VC dimension≤ of C calculated on a suitable subset of a compactification of Ω. We do not make any measurability assumptions on C , assuming instead the validity of Martin’s Axiom (MA). Similar results are obtained for function learning in terms of fat-shattering dimension modulo countable sets, but, just like in the classical distribution-free case, the finiteness of this parameter is sufficient but not necessary for PAC learnability under non-atomic measures. -
Sigma-Algebra from Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia Chapter 1
Sigma-algebra From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Chapter 1 Algebra of sets The algebra of sets defines the properties and laws of sets, the set-theoretic operations of union, intersection, and complementation and the relations of set equality and set inclusion. It also provides systematic procedures for evalu- ating expressions, and performing calculations, involving these operations and relations. Any set of sets closed under the set-theoretic operations forms a Boolean algebra with the join operator being union, the meet operator being intersection, and the complement operator being set complement. 1.1 Fundamentals The algebra of sets is the set-theoretic analogue of the algebra of numbers. Just as arithmetic addition and multiplication are associative and commutative, so are set union and intersection; just as the arithmetic relation “less than or equal” is reflexive, antisymmetric and transitive, so is the set relation of “subset”. It is the algebra of the set-theoretic operations of union, intersection and complementation, and the relations of equality and inclusion. For a basic introduction to sets see the article on sets, for a fuller account see naive set theory, and for a full rigorous axiomatic treatment see axiomatic set theory. 1.2 The fundamental laws of set algebra The binary operations of set union ( [ ) and intersection ( \ ) satisfy many identities. Several of these identities or “laws” have well established names. Commutative laws: • A [ B = B [ A • A \ B = B \ A Associative laws: • (A [ B) [ C = A [ (B [ C) • (A \ B) \ C = A \ (B \ C) Distributive laws: • A [ (B \ C) = (A [ B) \ (A [ C) • A \ (B [ C) = (A \ B) [ (A \ C) The analogy between unions and intersections of sets, and addition and multiplication of numbers, is quite striking.