Reflective Equilibrium

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Reflective Equilibrium eophil_R 10/25/05 8:40 AM Page 290 REFLECTIVE EQUILIBRIUM MINIMALISM. Traditional theorizing about reference is Bibliography ambitious; the possibility of a broad and deep theory Almog, J., J. Perry, and H. Wettstein, eds. Themes from Kaplan. such as it seeks has been questioned by Richard Rorty, New York: Oxford University Press, 1989. Robert Brandom, Paul Horwich, and others. The follow- Brandom, R. “Reference Explained Away: Anaphoric Reference and Indirect Description.” Journal of Philosophy 81 (1984): ing schema constitutes a minimal account of reference 469–492. (“a” is replaceable by singular terms): Devitt, M. Designation. New York: Columbia University Press, 1981. (R) For any x, “a” refers to x if and only if x = a. Evans, G. The Varieties of Reference. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982. “London” refers to London and nothing else. A minimal- Fodor, J. Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the ist account adds to (R) the claim that (R) exhausts the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987. nature of reference. French, P., T. Uehling, and H. Wettstein, eds. Contemporary Perspectives in the Philosophy of Language. Midwest Studies Some qualifications are necessary. First, if anything in Philosophy, Vol. 5. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota but a singular term replaces “a” in (R), the result is ill Press, 1979. formed, for only singular terms should flank the identity Horwich, P. Truth. Oxford: Blackwell, 1990. sign. If expressions of other syntactic categories refer, Kripke, S. Naming and Necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard those categories will require their own schemas. The University Press, 1980. schema for predicates might be: Lewis, D. “Putnam’s Paradox.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 62 (1984): 221–236. (R') For any x, “F” refers to x if and only if x = Fness. Neale, S. Descriptions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1990. Putnam, H. Philosophical Papers, Vol. 2: Mind, Language, and Second, the notion of a singular term must be explained Reality. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 1975. (can “my sake” replace “a”?). Third, (R) does not say Récanati, F. Direct Reference: From Language to Thought. which singular terms refer. When “a” does not refer, (R) Oxford: Blackwell, 1993. Rorty, R. Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Princeton, NJ: may not express a proposition. Fourth, (R) cannot be Princeton University Press, 1979. generalized by the prefix “In all contexts”: “today” used Schwartz, S., ed. Naming, Necessity, and Natural Kinds. Ithaca, tomorrow does not refer to today. Rather, (R) should be NY: Cornell University Press, 1977. understood as instantiated by sentences in different con- Timothy Williamson (1996) texts (for instance, uttered tomorrow with “today” for “a”). Fifth, when one cannot understand the term “a,” one cannot understand (R). Thus, one will find many instances of (R) unintelligible. reflective equilibrium One’s grasp of the minimal theory is not a grasp of Reflective equilibrium is a coherence method of philo- each of many propositions; it is more like one’s grasp of a sophical justification or inquiry. Nelson Goodman (1955) general pattern of inference. For (R) the pattern is in the introduced reflective equilibrium, although not under sentences that express the propositions, not in the propo- that name, to contemporary philosophy in a discussion of sitions themselves (it is not preserved when a synonym deductive and inductive logic. It is arguable, however, that replaces the unquoted occurrence of “a”). This generality philosophers have employed something such as reflective does not satisfy all philosophers. Many accept the mini- equilibrium to inquire into a wide range of topics since mal theory but reject minimalism, because they postulate ancient times. a deeper (for instance, causal) theory of reference that explains (R) and (R'). Although the reductionist demand Goodman maintained that we justify an inference by for strictly necessary and sufficient conditions for refer- showing that it conforms to the rules of either deduction ence in more fundamental terms may be overambitious, or induction. But for the inferences to be justified, these a good picture of reference might still reveal more than rules must be valid. Goodman held that we justify rules of (R) and (R') without meeting that demand. inference by showing that they accord with judgments we make about which particular inferences are acceptable See also Frege, Gottlob; Indexicals; Kaplan, David; and which are unacceptable. Goodman addressed the Kripke, Saul; Marcus, Ruth Barcan; Philosophy of Lan- obvious objection to such a procedure as follows: guage; Proper Names and Descriptions; Putnam, This looks flagrantly circular. I have said that Hilary; Rorty, Richard; Russell, Bertrand Arthur deductive inferences are justified by their con- William; Sense; Strawson, Peter Frederick. formity to valid general rules, and that general ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY 290 • 2nd edition eophil_R 10/25/05 8:40 AM Page 291 REFLECTIVE EQUILIBRIUM rules are justified by their conformity to valid cognitively spontaneous; they might concern proposi- inferences. But this circle is a virtuous one. A tions that are either particular or general. The first step on rule is amended if it yields an inference we are the road to reflective equilibrium, according to Rawls, is unwilling to accept; an inference is rejected if it for S to eliminate certain initial moral judgments. For violates a rule we are unwilling to amend. The example, judgments that are not stable over time or in process of justification is the delicate one of which S has little confidence should be dropped, as making mutual adjustments between rules and should judgments formed when S is emotionally dis- accepted inferences; and in the agreement thus traught. In general, S eliminates those judgments formed achieved lies the only justification needed for in circumstances where there is some obvious reason for either. suspecting error. The remaining judgments will be S’s (GOODMAN 1955, P. 67) considered moral judgments. It is possible to read Goodman’s proposal as purely S’s next task is to formulate a moral theory, that is, a methodological or as more epistemological. According to set of moral principles that accounts for S’s considered the epistemological reading, when we complete the moral judgments. The coherence element of the method process of mutual adjustment Goodman describes, comes into play at this stage because S will grant neither thereby bringing our judgments regarding the particular considered moral judgments nor moral theory a privi- inferences and the rules of inference we accept into a state leged status. S will make revisions on both sides in the of reflective equilibrium, these rules and particular judg- attempt to forge a coherent system of moral beliefs. When ments are by definition justified. According to this read- the emerging theory is found to conflict with central, very ing, being justified consists in being part of a system of confidently made considered judgments, S must revise beliefs, including rules and particular judgments, that has the theory. But if a well-confirmed element of the theory the sort of coherence that reflective equilibrium repre- that is independently plausible is found to conflict with sents. less firmly held considered judgments, then S will revise these judgments. S’s decision regarding what to revise is The methodological understanding of reflective made for each case on the basis of what seems most likely equilibrium accepts that a philosophical inquiry into to be true or correct to S upon due consideration (there inductive or deductive inference is properly conducted by are various other ways of expressing this idea: We might, a process of mutual adjustment of the kind Goodman for example, say that S is to decide on the basis of S’s describes; it agrees that this is the best we can do in an degrees of belief or commitment or on the basis of what attempt to justify the inferences we make and the rules of seems most plausible or acceptable to S). inference we accept. But the methodological reading is not definite about the epistemic status of the particular To this point, Rawls’s method corresponds with and general judgments we manage to bring into reflective Goodman’s, but Rawls does not allow S to stop here, at a equilibrium. It leaves open what positive epistemic status, point of narrow reflective equilibrium. According to if any, principles and judgments that are in reflective Rawls, S must next consider alternatives to the moral the- equilibrium might have. In addition, whereas the episte- ory that S accepts in narrow equilibrium along with mological reading is committed to a coherentist account philosophical arguments for and against S’s own theory of justification, the methodological reading leaves open and the various alternatives S is considering. In his how best to account for the precise epistemic status (or important work on reflective equilibrium, Norman statuses) attained by judgments that are in reflective equi- Daniels (1979) argues that we can think of this as an librium. Although Goodman probably intended an epis- attempt to attain coherence between the considered temological reading, let us adopt a methodological moral judgments and theory that S accepts in narrow understanding of reflective equilibrium in order to keep reflective equilibrium and the background theories S as many epistemological options open as possible. accepts. The idea is that the philosophical arguments that We owe the term reflective equilibrium to John S constructs will use premises drawn from among S’s Rawls (1971), who developed the method further and broader background beliefs, which might include such applied it to moral inquiry. If we think of the method as things as sociological views regarding the role of morality something to be applied in a stepwise fashion, which is in society and philosophical or psychological theories useful even if not entirely accurate, then an inquirer, S, regarding rational decision or the nature of persons.
Recommended publications
  • Beyond Skepticism Foundationalism and the New Fuzziness: the Role of Wide Reflective Equilibrium in Legal Theory Robert Justin Lipkin
    Cornell Law Review Volume 75 Article 2 Issue 4 May 1990 Beyond Skepticism Foundationalism and the New Fuzziness: The Role of Wide Reflective Equilibrium in Legal Theory Robert Justin Lipkin Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/clr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Robert Justin Lipkin, Beyond Skepticism Foundationalism and the New Fuzziness: The Role of Wide Reflective Equilibrium in Legal Theory , 75 Cornell L. Rev. 810 (1990) Available at: http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/clr/vol75/iss4/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Cornell Law Review by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. BEYOND SKEPTICISM, FOUNDATIONALISM AND THE NEW FUZZINESS: THE ROLE OF WIDE REFLECTIVE EQUILIBRIUM IN LEGAL THEORY Robert Justin Liphint TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION .............................................. 812 I. FOUNDATIONALISM AND SKEPTICISM ..................... 816 A. The Problem of Skepticism ........................ 816 B. Skepticism and Nihilism ........................... 819 1. Theoretical and PracticalSkepticism ................ 820 2. Subjectivism and Relativism ....................... 821 3. Epistemic and Conceptual Skepticism ................ 821 4. Radical Skepticism ............................... 822 C. Modified Skepticism ............................... 824 II. NEW FOUNDATIONALISM
    [Show full text]
  • Reliable Reasoning: Induction and Statistical Learning Theory
    Reliable Reasoning: Induction and Statistical Learning Theory Gilbert Harman and Sanjeev Kulkarni March 14, 2006 ii Reliable Reasoning Contents Series Forward v Introduction vii 1 The Problem of Induction 1 1.1 The Problem . 1 1.2 Inference and Implication . 3 1.3 Reflective Equilibrium . 7 1.4 Worries about Reflective Equilibrium . 9 1.5 Reliability . 14 1.6 A Look Ahead . 15 1.7 Conclusion . 18 2 Induction and VC-Dimension 21 2.1 Pattern Recognition . 21 2.1.1 Pattern Classfication . 22 2.1.2 Function Estimation . 23 2.2 Background Probability Distribution . 24 2.3 Reliability of Rules of Classification and Function Estimation 26 2.3.1 Reliability of a Classification Rule . 26 2.3.2 Reliability of a Rule of Function Estimation . 27 2.4 Inductive Learning . 28 2.4.1 Linear Classification and Estimation Rules . 29 2.5 Conditions for Satisfactory Enumerative Induction . 32 2.6 Popper . 35 2.7 Summary . 36 3 Induction and “Simplicity” 39 3.1 Introduction . 39 3.2 Empirical Error Minimization . 39 iii iv Reliable Reasoning 3.3 Universal Consistency . 40 3.3.1 Nearest Neighbor Rules . 41 3.4 Structural Risk Minimization . 43 3.5 Minimum Description Length . 44 3.6 Simplicity . 45 3.7 Function Estimation and Curve Fitting . 45 3.8 Goodman’s New Riddle . 46 3.9 Popper on Simplicity . 49 3.10 Empirically Equivalent Rules . 52 3.11 Important Ideas from Statistical Learning Theory . 53 3.12 Summary . 54 4 Neural Networks, Support Vector Machines, and Transduction 55 4.1 Introduction . 55 4.2 Machine Learning: Perceptrons .
    [Show full text]
  • The Reflective Equilibrium in Rawls' Theory of Justice: the Perspective
    META: Research in Hermeneutics, Phenomenology, and Practical Philosophy – VII (2) / 2015 META: RESEARCH IN HERMENEUTICS, PHENOMENOLOGY, AND PRACTICAL PHILOSOPHY VOL. VII, NO. 2 / DECEMBER 2015: 336-356, ISSN 2067-3655, www.metajournal.org The Reflective Equilibrium in Rawls’ Theory of Justice: The Perspective of Holistic Pragmatism Mihai Burlacu Transylvania University of Brasov Abstract Interpreting John Rawls’ ‘reflective equilibrium’ method from the perspective of Morton White’s holistic pragmatism entails both an epistemological and a methodological dimension. In this article, I reconsider White’s perspective regarding Rawls’ ‘reflective equilibrium’. This requires a critical examination of the method’s origins and development, with an emphasis on Nelson Goodman’s process of justification and the Duhem-Quine thesis. In order to examine the origins and development of the ‘reflective equilibrium’ method, I also draw upon the writings of Pierre Duhem, Willard Van Orman Quine, Nelson Goodman, Stephen P. Stich and Donald Gillies, among others. Subsequently, I interpret the criticisms that have been formulated against the process of justification elaborated by Goodman and adapted by Rawls. Afterwards, I explain the conceptual links between the ‘Duhem-Quine thesis’ and the ‘reflective equilibrium’ method. In the last chapter, I analyse White’s assertion that Rawls’ theory of justice is a variant of holistic pragmatism. I emphasize how White’s holistic theses coincide to a significant extent with the ideas devised by Rawls regarding the method of ‘reflective equilibrium’ in social justice, and in a more general sense, in ethics. Also, I expound why White’s doctrine is epistemologically holistic and methodologically monistic. Keywords: reflective equilibrium, holistic pragmatism, considered judgment, principles of justice, conjunction of statements, Duhem-Quine thesis, Duhemian conjunction 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Five the METHOD of WIDE REFLECTIVE EQUILIBRIUM IN
    Five THE METHOD OF WIDE REFLECTIVE EQUILIBRIUM IN BIOETHICS Juha Räikkä 1. What Is Wide Reflective Equilibrium? The method of wide reflective equilibrium has been widely applied in practical ethics and especially in bioethics. In what follows I would like to say few words on the nature of this method. The method of wide reflective equilibrium (WRE) is a coherence method of justification in ethics. WRE was first introduced by John Rawls in his “The Independence of Moral Theory,” and one of WRE’s strongest proponents has been another American philosopher Norman Daniels.1 As Daniels describes WRE, it is a method which attempts to produce coherence in an ordered triple of sets of beliefs held by a particular person, namely (a) a set of considered moral judgments, (b) a set of moral principles, and (c) a set of relevant (scien- tific and philosophical) background theories.2 When using WRE, a person begins by collecting moral judgments (such as “abortion should be allowed”) which she finds intuitively plausible. Then she proposes alternative sets of moral principles (such as “killing human be- ings is wrong”) that have varying degree of fit with the moral judgments. Fi- nally, she seeks support for those moral judgments and moral principles from background theories (such as “a fetus is not a human being”) that are, in her view, acceptable. As Daniels writes, we can imagine the agent working back and forth, making adjustments to her considered moral judgments, her moral principles and her background theories. Finally, she arrives at an equilibrium point that consists of the ordered triple (a), (b) and (c).
    [Show full text]
  • A Methodological Turn in Political Philosophy: Making Political Philosophy More Scientific?1 Tereza Křepelová Masaryk University, Brno
    Public Reason 10 (2) - Public Reason 11 (1): 77-92 © 2019 by Public Reason A Methodological Turn in Political Philosophy: Making Political Philosophy More Scientific?1 Tereza Křepelová Masaryk University, Brno Abstract: The emergence of the first literature concerning the methodology of political philosophy, which we have witnessed over the last decade, indicates a general methodological shift within the discipline. This shift can be interpreted as a sign of the ongoing adjustment of political philosophy to the domain of science that had already begun when analytical political philosophy incorporated from logical positivism the premise of the unity of method of science and philosophy. The urge to have an epistemic source of justification for normative political theories lead analytical political philosophy to the development of various methodological frameworks from among which reflective equilibrium became the most influential one and nowadays it is being considered as the most widely used method in the contemporary political philosophy overall. Reflective equilibrium aims to provide knowledge that falls into the same category as scientific knowledge; however, it can also lead to various normative distortions resulting in the elimination of metaphysics, meta-ethics and religious claims from the normative part of political philosophical theorising. These normative distortions not only can result in epistemically wrong conclusions; above all, they implicitly affirm the normative propositions of political conceptions of liberalism. Hence, the prevalence and uncritical use of reflective equilibrium might narrow the topical scope and undermine the reflective and critical role of the discipline of political philosophy itself. Key words: political science, political philosophy, methodology, analytical political philosophy, logical positivism, political liberalism, epistemic value, epistemic justification, reflective equilibrium, philosophy of science.
    [Show full text]
  • The Methodological Irrelevance of Reflective Equilibrium* Tristram Mcpherson Virginia Tech [email protected]
    The methodological irrelevance of reflective equilibrium* Tristram McPherson Virginia Tech [email protected] Penultimate Ms.: the official version will be published in the Palgrave Handbook of Philosophical Methodology Introduction John Rawls’ method of reflective equilibrium is the most influential methodology in contemporary ethics. This paper argues that this influence is undeserved. Rawls’ method is highly implausible. Worse, it is also incapable of performing the work that motivates the search for a moral methodology in the first place. These are bold charges, and I dedicate the bulk of the paper to substantiating them (§§3-5). Several of the objections that I offer have been pressed before. However, when such objections are pressed in isolation from each other, it can seem easy to salvage the spirit (if not the letter) of the method, by judicious adjustment. It is much more difficult to do this once the inadequacies of the method are systematically displayed. I illustrate this point by exploring salient attempts to salvage the spirit of reflective equilibrium by abandoning elements of Rawls’ approach (§6). I argue that none of these attempts succeed. I conclude that appeal to the method of reflective equilibrium is not a helpful means of addressing pressing methodological questions in ethics. In a slogan, reflective equilibrium is methodologically irrelevant. * I am indebted to an audience at Virginia Tech, to participants in Sarah McGrath’s Systematic Ethics seminar at Princeton, and to Chris Daly for helpful comments on this project. I also benefited from comments on a distant ancestor of this paper in the Dissertation Seminar at Princeton.
    [Show full text]
  • Wide Reflective Equilibrium and Theory Acceptance in Ethics Author(S): Norman Daniels Source: the Journal of Philosophy, Vol
    Journal of Philosophy, Inc. Wide Reflective Equilibrium and Theory Acceptance in Ethics Author(s): Norman Daniels Source: The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 76, No. 5 (May, 1979), pp. 256-282 Published by: Journal of Philosophy, Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2025881 Accessed: 11/08/2009 07:08 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=jphil. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Journal of Philosophy, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Philosophy. http://www.jstor.org 256 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY did so indirectly (say, by swallowing a placebo); his belief in this false causal efficacy does not alter the fact that he performed the basic action.
    [Show full text]
  • Moorean Arguments and Moral Revisionism
    MOOREAN ARGUMENTS AND MORAL REVISIONISM BY TRISTRAM MCPHERSON JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY VOL. 3, NO. 2 | JUNE 2009 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT © TRISTRAM MCPHERSON 2009 JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY | VOL. 3, NO. 2 MOOREAN ARGUMENTS AND MORAL REVISIONISM Tristram McPherson Moorean Arguments and Moral Revisionism Tristram McPherson And how on earth is it to be decided which of the two things it is rational to be most certain of? G. E. Moore, Four Forms of Scepticism (emphasis his) Introduction E. MOORE’S LEGACY TO MORAL philosophy has been both profound and controversial. Most notably, his Principia Ethi- G.ca is often treated as a crucial starting point for work in what is now typically called “metaethics,” and metaethicists have returned again and again to defend, debunk or diagnose the appeal of his Open Question argu- ment. This paper examines the implications for moral philosophy of one of Moore’s other famous (or, depending upon your tastes, infamous) forms of argument: the table-turning maneuver that he deployed against the epistemo- logical skeptic and the metaphysical idealist. Against such revisionary metaphysical and epistemological views, Moore claimed that the following constitutes a proof of the existence of his hands, and thereby of the external world: I can prove now, for instance, that two human hands exist. How? By holding up my two hands and saying, as I make a gesture with the right hand, “Here is one hand,” and adding as I make a certain gesture with the left, “and here is another.” (1959, 145-6) The (implicit) remainder of the proof can be represented as follows: HANDS 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Reflective Equilibrium. In: Blau, A
    Knight, C. (2017) Reflective equilibrium. In: Blau, A. (ed.) Methods in Analytical Political Theory. Cambridge University Press, pp. 46-64. ISBN 9781316162576 (doi:10.1017/9781316162576.005) This is the author’s final accepted version. There may be differences between this version and the published version. You are advised to consult the publisher’s version if you wish to cite from it. This material has been published in Methods in Analytical Political Theory by / edited by Adrian Blau. This version is free to view and download for personal use only. Not for re-distribution, re-sale or use in derivative works. © Cambridge University Press http://eprints.gla.ac.uk/153138/ Deposited on: 06 December 2017 Enlighten – Research publications by members of the University of Glasgow http://eprints.gla.ac.uk Reflective Equilibrium* Carl Knight, University of Glasgow 1. Introduction The method of reflective equilibrium focuses on the relationship between principles and judgments. Principles are relatively general rules for comprehending the area of enquiry. Judgments are our intuitions or commitments, ‘at all levels of generality’ (Rawls 1975: 8), regarding the subject matter. The basic idea of reflective equilibrium is to bring principles and judgments into accord. This can be achieved by revising the principles and/or the judgments. For instance, if I am considering the principle that it is always wrong to lie, but have the judgment that it would not be wrong to lie in order to save a life, I can reach equilibrium by either revising the principle or revising the judgment. Reflective equilibrium is the most widely used methodology in contemporary moral and political philosophy (Sinnot-Armstrong et al 2010: 246; Varner 2012: 11).
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 12 Reflective Equilibrium
    Chapter 12 Reflective Equilibrium Yuri Cath H. Cappelen, T. Gendler, and J. Hawthorne (eds.) Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Methodology, Oxford University Press (2016). [Preprint, please cite the published version] 1 Introduction The method of reflective equilibrium is a method for figuring out what to believe about some target domain of philosophical interest like, say, justice, morality, or knowledge. This method is most closely associated with John Rawls who introduced the term ‘reflective equilibrium’ into the philosophical lexicon in A Theory of Justice (1971), where he appealed to this method in arguing for his famous theory of justice as fairness. However, Rawls had already advocated essentially the same method (without calling it ‘reflective equilibrium’) in an earlier paper (Rawls 1951), and Goodman (1954) is widely identified (including by Rawls himself) as being the first clear advocate of this kind of method, albeit with respect to a different normative domain, namely, logic. Due to Rawls’ influence, there has been a great deal of discussion of reflective equilibrium (or ‘RE’) in moral philosophy, and many philosophers have suggested that this method is uniquely suited to theorizing about morality or normativity more generally. However, the method of RE has also been claimed to be a method that plays a central role in all areas of philosophical inquiry, including those that are concerned with non-normative subjects, like metaphysics. This idea that the method of RE is employed in all areas of philosophy has been endorsed not only by proponents of this method (see e.g. Lewis 1983, pp. x-xi), but also by 1 critics who agree that this method is used in this way but who argue that this is a practice that needs to be abandoned or reformed (see e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • Verification and Validation of Ethical Decision-Making in Autonomous Systems
    VERIFICATION AND VALIDATION OF ETHICAL DECISION-MAKING IN AUTONOMOUS SYSTEMS Levent Yilmaz Department of Computer Science and Software Engineering Auburn University 3101 Shelby Center Auburn, AL, USA [email protected] ABSTRACT Autonomous systems are increasingly becoming part of both the cyber and physical infrastructures that sus- tain our daily lives. Immersing these technologies into our technical and social infrastructures has profound implications and hence requires instilling confidence in their behavior to avoid potential harm. This paper examines the characteristics of autonomous behavior in relation to ethical decision-making and highlights the roles of cognitive computing and science of complexity toward addressing the identified verification and validation challenges. A framework influenced by the social intuitionist theory is discussed, and wide reflec- tive equilibrium model of coherence is posited as a formal computational strategy for its implementation. Keywords: ethical decision-making, autonomy, verification, cognitive system, complexity 1 INTRODUCTION The increased reliance on cyber-human interactions in dynamic environments makes ethical decision- making become more pronounced with outcomes that have serious consequences. As autonomous cars transition into use (Grogan 2012) and drones are deployed to conduct remote missions, there is an increas- ing concern over civilian casualties (Tucker 2014). As millions of vehicles are expected to be endowed with autonomy, taking algorithmic morality seriously has never been more urgent. Increased levels of autonomy can be justified if and only if trust is instilled in the moral decision-making capacity of autonomous sys- tems. Ethical dilemmas that emerge due to conflicts among duties, consequences (e.g., non-maleficence, beneficence), individuals’ rights, and efficiency should be effectively resolved, for the acceptability ofau- tonomous systems relies on their ability to reason within the context of rights, fairness, and norms.
    [Show full text]
  • Rawls' Concept of Reflective Equilibrium and Its Original Function in a Theory of Justice
    Washington University Jurisprudence Review Volume 3 | Issue 1 2011 Rawls’ Concept of Reflective Equilibrium and Its Original Function in A Theory of Justice John Mikhail Follow this and additional works at: https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/law_jurisprudence Part of the Jurisprudence Commons Recommended Citation John Mikhail, Rawls’ Concept of Reflective Equilibrium and Its Original Function in A Theory of Justice, 3 Wash. U. Jur. Rev. 1 (2011). Available at: https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/law_jurisprudence/vol3/iss1/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law School at Washington University Open Scholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Washington University Jurisprudence Review by an authorized administrator of Washington University Open Scholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. RAWLS' CONCEPT OF REFLECTIVE EQUILIBRIUM AND ITS ORIGINAL FUNCTION IN A THEORY OF JUSTICE JOHN MIKHAIL* John Rawls' concept of reflective equilibrium' has been the subject of considerable interest and debate. Its use in moral philosophy has drawn criticism from many philosophers and legal scholars2 and has been resourcefully defended by others.3 Rawls' concept originally derived from an influential account of the philosophical method of justifying principles of inductive inference.4 As such, many commentators have assumed that the concept implies a close nexus between the methods of ethics and empirical science, and thus may shed light on the nature of moral truth, justification, and objectivity.5 Reflective equilibrium also plays a significant role in the analogy Rawls draws in A Theory of * Professor of Law, Georgetown University Law Center. This Essay is a slightly modified and expanded version of the discussion of reflective equilibrium that appears in my doctoral dissertation on Rawls' linguistic analogy.
    [Show full text]