Evolutionary Genetics from Molecules to Morphology

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Evolutionary Genetics from Molecules to Morphology P1: AKA/FKA P2: SDL CB208-FM April 27, 2000 Evolutionary Genetics From Molecules to Morphology Edited by R. S. SINGH McMaster University C. B. KRIMBAS University of Athens v P1: AKA/FKA P2: SDL CB208-FM April 27, 2000 PUBLISHED BY THE PRESS SYNDICATE OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CAMBRIDGE The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 2RU, UK www.cup.cam.ac.uk 40 West 20th Street, New York, NY 10011-4211, USA www.cup.org 10 Stamford Road, Oakleigh, Melbourne 3166, Australia Ruiz de Alarc´on 13, 28014 Madrid, Spain C Cambridge University Press 1999 This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published 1999 Printed in the United States of America Typeface New Baskerville 9.75/12 pt. System LATEX2ε [tb] A catalog record for this book is available from the British Library. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Evolutionary genetics : from molecules to morphology / edited by R. S. Singh and C. Krimbas. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-521-57123-5 1. Evolutionary genetics. 2. Lewontin, Richard C., 1929– . I. Singh, R. S. II. Krimbas, Costas B. QH390.E96 1999 576.8–dc21 99-14415 CIP ISBN 0 521 57123 5 hardback vi P1: AKA/FKA P2: SDL CB208-FM April 27, 2000 Contents List of Contributors page xi Preface xv Section A. Population Genetics: Problems, Foundations, and Historical Perspectives Introductory Remarks – Costas Krimbas 1 The Problems of Population Genetics 5 richard lewontin 2 The Mathematical Foundations of Population Genetics 24 warren ewens 3 A Natural Historian’s View of Heterosis and Related Topics 41 bruce wallace 4 The Molecular Foundation of Population Genetics 52 rama s. singh, walter f. eanes, donal a. hickey, lynn m. king, and margaret a. riley Section B. Molecular Variation and Evolution Introductory Remarks – Martin Kreitman 5 The Population and Evolutionary Genetics of Codon Bias 82 martin kreitman and marcos antezana 6 Gene Conversion Is a Major Determinant of Genetic Diversity at the DNA Level 102 andrew berry and antonio barbadilla 7 Evidence for Balancing, Directional, and Background Selection in Molecular Evolution 124 stephen w. schaeffer and montserrat aguad´e vii P1: AKA/FKA P2: SDL CB208-FM April 27, 2000 viii CONTENTS Section C. Selection and Genetic Polymorphism Introductory Remarks – Philip Hedrick and Timothy Prout 8 Aspects of Fitness 146 freddy bugge christiansen and timothy prout 9 How Well Does Opposing Selection Maintain Variation? 157 timothy prout 10 Analysis of Selection in Laboratory and Field Populations 182 einararnason ´ and j. s. f. barker 11 Genetics of Complex Polymorphisms: Parasites and Maintenance of the Major Histocompatibility Complex Variation 204 philip w. hedrick and timothy j. kim 12 The Population Biology of Antibiotic Resistance 235 bruce r. levin Section D. Linkage, Breeding Systems, and Evolution Introductory Remarks – Ian R. Franklin 13 The Equilibrium Theory of One- and Two-Locus Systems 258 ian r. franklin and marcus w. feldman 14 Inversion Polymorphisms in Drosophila 284 costar krimbas and jeffrey powell 15 The Evolution of Breeding Systems 300 marcy k. uyenoyama 16 The Evolution of Sex and Recombination 317 donal a. hickey Section E. Quantitative Genetics and Phenotypic Evolution Introductory Remarks – Richard Frankham 17 Quantitative Genetics and Phenotypic Evolution 335 russell lande 18 Nature of Quantitative Genetic Variation 351 richard frankham and kenneth weber 19 The Maintenance of Genetic Variation in Life-History Traits 369 brian charlesworth and kimberly a. hughes 20 Population Genetics and Life-History Evolution 393 lloyd demetrius P1: AKA/FKA P2: SDL CB208-FM April 27, 2000 CONTENTS ix Section F. Gene Flow, Population Structure, and Evolution Introductory Remarks – Montgomery Slatkin 21 A Coalescent View of Population Structure 418 montgomery slatkin 22 Population Genetics and Evolution of Animal Mitochondrial DNA 430 eleftherios zouros and david m. rand 23 Genetic Structure and Evolution in Parthenogenetic Animals 456 e. davis parker jr. and monica niklasson 24 Genetic Structure of Prokaryotic Populations 475 frederick m. cohan Section G. Population Genetics and Speciation Introductory Remarks – Rama S. Singh 25 Sexual Selection in Populations: The Facts Require a Change in the Genetic Definition of the Species 495 hampton l. carson 26 The Role of Selection in Speciation 513 judith masters 27 The Evolutionary Genetics of Speciation 532 jerry a. coyne and h. allen orr 28 Toward a Unified Theory of Speciation 570 rama s. singh Section H. Behavior, Ecology, and Evolution Introductory Remarks – Subodh Jain 29 From Population Genetics to Evolutionary Genetics: A View through the Trees 609 joseph felsenstein 30 Attitudes to Animal Behavior 628 john maynard smith 31 The Evolution of Social Behavior 641 deborah m. gordon 32 Population Genetics and Evolutionary Ecology: A Progress Re- port 653 subodh jain Publications of R. C. Lewontin 679 Index 691 P1: DBJ CB208-01 June 22, 1999 CHAPTER ONE The Problems of Population Genetics richard lewontin The science of population genetics is the auto mechanics of evolutionary bio- logy. Organic evolution, in the Darwinian scheme, is a consequence of the con- version of variation among members of an ensemble into differences between ensembles in time and space. Classically those ensembles are collections of in- dividual organisms, populations in the usual sense, but the Darwinian scheme can be applied as well to ensembles of organelles within cells or to collections of populations that make up a species. The essential features of the Darwinian scheme that determine both the subject and form of population genetics are that 1. there are processes that produce variation among individuals within a population, 2. there are processes that result in changes in the relative frequencies of the variants within a generation, 3. there is a hereditary process across generations that may result in further change in the relative frequencies of the different variants, but population frequencies are correlated across generational lines so that the frequency distribution of variants in any time interval is some nontrivial function of their distribution in the previous interval of time. It is the relation between the processes of the generation and the modulation of variation within generations in features 1 and 2 and the processes occur- ring between generations in feature 3 that both create the science of pop- ulation genetics and pose its methodological dilemmas and its shape as an inquiry. These relations are most easily understood as the transformations in the state of the population, shown in Fig. 1.1 (from Lewontin, 1974). The population change can be represented both in a genotypic and a phenotypic space, and the complete laws of transformation make use of both these spaces. R. S. Singh and C. B. Krimbas, eds., Evolutionary Genetics: From Molecules to Morphology, vol. 1. c Cambridge University Press 1999. Printed in the United States of America. ISBN 0-521- 57123-5. All rights reserved. 5 P1: DBJ CB208-01 June 22, 1999 6 Richard Lewontin Figure 1.1. Schematic representation of the paths of transformation of population genotype from one generation to the next. G and P are the spaces of genotypic and phenotypic 0 0 description. G1, G , G2, and G are genotypic descriptions at various points in time within 1 0 2 0 successive generations. P1, P1, P2, and P2 are phenotypic descriptions. T1, T2, T3, and T4 are laws of transformation. Details are given in the text. (From Evolutionary Genetics by R. C. Lewontin. Copyright c 1974 by Columbia University Press. Reprinted with permission of the publisher.) G1, G2, P1, and P2 are genotypic and phenotypic descriptions at different points within a generation, while the same quantities with primes are the descriptions of the equivalent states in the next generation. The laws of transformation are T1: a set of epigenetic laws that gives the distribution of phenotypes, including fitness, that results from the development of various genotypes in various environments. T2: the laws of mating, migration, and natural selection including stochastic elements that transform the phenotypic array of potential reproducing units in a population within a generation. T3: the set of reverse epigenetic transformations that allows inferences about the distribution of genotypes G2 corresponding to the distribution of phenotypes P2. P1: DBJ CB208-01 June 22, 1999 THE PROBLEMS OF POPULATION GENETICS 7 T4: the phenomenology of genetics such as segregation, recombination, mu- tation, horizontal transfer, etc., including stochastic elements, that allows us to predict the probability distribution of genotypes in the next generation produced from gametogenesis and fertilization, given an array of parental genotypes. This representation of the structure of population genetic inference points immediately to two major sources of difficulty that have shaped the problems of population from its beginnings and still do so. First there is the problem of development. T4, the complete apparatus of genetics that carries the popula- tion transformation across generations, is operating in the genotypic space to transform genotypic frequencies and cannot be framed in phenotypic terms. But T2 that specifies the transformation of frequencies within generations is a set of physiological, ecological, and behavioral relations that operates in the phenotypic space. In the absence of a knowledge of the epigenetic transfor- mations, the circuit is cut and nothing can be done. Nor can one depend on developmental genetics to provide the missing laws, because the main direction of developmental biology has never been, and shows no promise of ever being, to understand the environmental contingency of variations in development. Much of the past and the present problems of population genetics can be un- derstood only as an attempt to finesse the unsolved problem of an adequate description of development.
Recommended publications
  • Transformations of Lamarckism Vienna Series in Theoretical Biology Gerd B
    Transformations of Lamarckism Vienna Series in Theoretical Biology Gerd B. M ü ller, G ü nter P. Wagner, and Werner Callebaut, editors The Evolution of Cognition , edited by Cecilia Heyes and Ludwig Huber, 2000 Origination of Organismal Form: Beyond the Gene in Development and Evolutionary Biology , edited by Gerd B. M ü ller and Stuart A. Newman, 2003 Environment, Development, and Evolution: Toward a Synthesis , edited by Brian K. Hall, Roy D. Pearson, and Gerd B. M ü ller, 2004 Evolution of Communication Systems: A Comparative Approach , edited by D. Kimbrough Oller and Ulrike Griebel, 2004 Modularity: Understanding the Development and Evolution of Natural Complex Systems , edited by Werner Callebaut and Diego Rasskin-Gutman, 2005 Compositional Evolution: The Impact of Sex, Symbiosis, and Modularity on the Gradualist Framework of Evolution , by Richard A. Watson, 2006 Biological Emergences: Evolution by Natural Experiment , by Robert G. B. Reid, 2007 Modeling Biology: Structure, Behaviors, Evolution , edited by Manfred D. Laubichler and Gerd B. M ü ller, 2007 Evolution of Communicative Flexibility: Complexity, Creativity, and Adaptability in Human and Animal Communication , edited by Kimbrough D. Oller and Ulrike Griebel, 2008 Functions in Biological and Artifi cial Worlds: Comparative Philosophical Perspectives , edited by Ulrich Krohs and Peter Kroes, 2009 Cognitive Biology: Evolutionary and Developmental Perspectives on Mind, Brain, and Behavior , edited by Luca Tommasi, Mary A. Peterson, and Lynn Nadel, 2009 Innovation in Cultural Systems: Contributions from Evolutionary Anthropology , edited by Michael J. O ’ Brien and Stephen J. Shennan, 2010 The Major Transitions in Evolution Revisited , edited by Brett Calcott and Kim Sterelny, 2011 Transformations of Lamarckism: From Subtle Fluids to Molecular Biology , edited by Snait B.
    [Show full text]
  • Uncorrelated Genetic Drift of Gene Frequencies and Linkage
    Genet. Res., Camb. (1974), 24, pp. 281-294 281 Printed in Great Britain Uncorrelated genetic drift of gene frequencies and linkage disequilibrium in some models of linked overdominant polymorphisms BY JOSEPH FELSENSTEIN Department of Genetics, University of Washington, Seattle, Washington 98195 {Received 15 April 1974) SUMMARY For large population sizes, gene frequencies p and q at two linked over- dominant loci and the linkage disequilibrium parameter D will remain close to their equilibrium values. We can treat selection and recombination as approximately linear forces on^J, q and D, and we can treat genetic drift as a multivariate normal perturbation with constant variance-covariance matrix. For the additive-multiplicative family of two-locus models, p, q and D are shown to be (approximately) uncorrelated. Expressions for their variances are obtained. When selection coefficients are small the variances of p and q are those previously given by Robertson for a single locus. For small recombination fractions the variance of D is that obtained for neutral loci by Ohta & Kimura. For larger recombination fractions the result differs from theirs, so that for unlinked loci r2~ 2/(3N) instead of l/(2N). For the Lewontin-Kojima and Bodmer symmetric viability models, and for a model symmetric at only one of the loci, a more exact argument is possible. In the asymptotic conditional distribution in these cases, various of p, q and D are uncorrelated, depending on the type of symmetiy in the model. 1. INTRODUCTION Much of the work on linked genes in the last few years has centred on the deter- ministic theory of natural selection of linked polymorphisms.
    [Show full text]
  • The Spice of Life the Variety of Life: a Survey and a Celebration of All the Creatures Snakes in the Grass That Have Ever Lived by Colin Tudge
    book reviews think that’s a false dichotomy.” She quotes, ating input from new methodologies, this is as this there is much to take issue with. In my but seems far less at home with, Sarah Hrdy’s heroism. Since the author took 10 years over own areas of special interest I found almost flat statement: “I did not come into science the job, he must have been daunted by how more to question and argue with than to and primatology because of a love for non- much the ground changed beneath his feet as agree with; and Tudge inevitably can only human primates. I was first attracted to prob- he progressed. When the world around you afford space for a thin overview of the real lems and to things I wanted to understand … is bursting with new kinds of information issues that excite us today. Indeed, for animal There is really no one way of doing science … that are just beginning to shed fresh light on phylogeny, the book only sparsely applies we need people to stress theory as much as a key question, it is a brave man who decides the information that is now emerging observation.” One of Jahme’s subjects, read- to write about the answer! So why has Colin from ‘evolutionary developmental biology’ ing the section about herself, murmured: Tudge done it? (which is revealing underlying similarities “Oh dear. This is half right and all wrong.” To Tudge’s answer is twofold: to help put tax- between diverse species in the structure of me that sums up the book, including some onomy back at the centre of biology (and the genes that control pattern formation and amazing scientific slip-ups.
    [Show full text]
  • THE DIALECTICAL BIOLOGIST 11 III II I, 11 1 1 Ni1 the DIALECTICAL BIOLOGIST
    THE DIALECTICAL BIOLOGIST 11 III II I, 11 1 1 ni1 THE DIALECTICAL BIOLOGIST Richard Levins and Richard Lewontin AAKAR THE DIALECTICAL BIOLOGIST Richard Levins and Richard Lewontin Harvard University Press, 1985 Aakar Books for South Asia, 2009 Reprinted by arrangement with Harvard University Press, USA for sale only in the Indian Subcontinent (India, Pakistan, Bangladesh, Nepal, Maldives, Bhutan & Sri Lanka) All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without prior permission of the publisher First Published in India, 2009 ISBN 978-81-89833-77-0 (Pb) Published by AAKAR BOOKS 28 E Pocket IV, Mayur Vihar Phase I, Delhi-110 091 Phone : 011-2279 5505 Telefax : 011-2279 5641 [email protected]; www.aakarbooks.com Printed at S.N. Printers, Delhi-110 032 To Frederick Engels, who got it wrong a lot of the time but who got it right where it counted ,, " I 1 1■ 1-0 ■44 pH III lye II I! Preface THIS Bow( has come into existence for both theoretical andpractical reasons. Despite the extraordinary successes of mechanistic reduction- ist molecular biology, there has been a growing discontent in the last twenty years with simple Cartesian reductionism as the universal way to truth. In psychology and anthropology, and especially in ecology, evolution, neurobiology, and developmental biology, where the Carte- sian program has failed to give satisfaction, we hear more and more calls for an alternative epistemological stance. Holistic, structuralist, hierarchical, and systems theories are all offered as alternative modes of explaining the world, as ways out of the cul-de-sacs into which re- ductionism has led us.
    [Show full text]
  • From Fox Keller, Back to Leibniz and on to Darwin
    Leibnizian Analysis in Metaphysics, Mathematics, Physics, Geology and Biology: From Fox Keller, back to Leibniz and on to Darwin Emily R. Grosholz I. Introduction The world of classical physics proposed a view of nature where systems behaved like machines: they were reducible to their parts, governed by universal laws (which were moreover time-reversal invariant), and thus representable by an axiomatized discourse where predictable events could be deduced, given the correct boundary conditions. Thus, the philosophers of science of the early and mid-twentieth century happily offered the Deductive-Nomological Model of Explanation (and Prediction). It fit Newton’s Principia, Book I, Proposition XI pretty well. However, it doesn’t really account for Book III, the development of the theory and practice of differential equations, the n-body problem, electro-magnetic phenomena, thermodynamics, atoms, galaxies or the expanding universe, limitations that even Thomas Kuhn, author of the revolutionary book The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, (University of Chicago Press, 1962) played down. But the philosophers did notice that the Deductive-Nomological Model of Explanation wasn’t a very good fit for biology, as after Darwin it struggled to account for natural history with its attendant one-way temporality, the emergence of novelty, and the intentionality and nested downwards complexity of living things, that seemed so stubbornly un-machine-like. The discovery of DNA and the rise of a new kind of machine, the computer, briefly encouraged philosophers (and scientists) to think that biology might finally look like a real science, populated by tiny robots that lend themselves to axioms and predictions; but, alas.
    [Show full text]
  • How a Generation Was Misled About Natural Selection
    Gabora, L. (2011). How a Generation Was Misled About Natural Selection. Psychology Today (online). http://www.psychologytoday.com/blog/mindbloggling How a Generation Was Misled About Natural Selection Subtitle: Natural Selection: How it Works, How it Applies to Culture Liane Gabora Department of Psychology, University of British Columbia Okanagan Campus, Arts Building, 333 University Way, Kelowna BC, V1V 1V7, CANADA For 'Mindbloggling' column, Psychology Today Abstract This article explains how natural selection works and how it has been inappropriately applied to the description of cultural change. It proposes an alternative evolutionary explanation for cultural evolution that describes it in terms of communal exchange. When science is explained to the general public it is necessary to simplify. Inevitably details get left out, details that some consider important, and the ‘sexy' parts of the story get played up. But so long as the overall picture is more or less right, scientists generally appreciate the efforts of popular science writers, the press, and in some cases their fellow colleagues, to make their work accessible to a wider audience. The public in turn benefits from the opportunity to see the world they live in from a new perspective, and consider questions they might not otherwise have considered. Sometimes, though, the baby gets thrown out with the bathwater. The ‘babyless' version of a scientific story may be a hit nonetheless. Unless one has advanced training in a highly specialized area of a scientific discipline, it may appear to make sense. In most cases, the 1 misrepresentation of science doesn't make much difference; life goes on as normal.
    [Show full text]
  • The Fearless Vampire Conservator: Phillip Kitcher and Genetic Determinism*
    The Fearless Vampire Conservator: Phillip Kitcher and Genetic Determinism* 1. Introduction Genetic determinism is the idea that many significant human characteristics are rendered inevitable by the presence of certain genes; that it is futile to attempt to modify criminal behavior or obesity or alcoholism by any means other than genetic manipulation. Recent discussion of human cloning has revealed how real a possibility genetic determinism seems to many people. Surveying this discussion, developmental biologist Lewis Wolpert was amused to see so many ‘moralists who denied that genes have an important effect on behavior now saying that a cloned individual’s behavior will be entirely determined by their genetic make-up’ (Wolpert, 1998). His observation is accurate, and the vehemence of many attacks on behavioral genetics probably reflects an underlying belief that if genes affect behavior at all, then they must determine it. In fact, genes are very unlikely to be deterministic causes of behavior, for reasons I will come to in a moment. But if genetic determinism is unlikely to be true, why are we as a community so afraid of it? Wolpert seems to think that moral and political commentators on biology are simply ignorant, but the facts of which they are supposedly ignorant have been widely available for a very long time. Perhaps there is more to the strange persistence of genetic determinism. The psychologist Susan Oyama has famously compared arguing against genetic determinism to battling the undead: “But wait,” the exasperated reader cries, “everyone nowadays knows that development is a matter of interaction. You’re beating a dead horse.
    [Show full text]
  • Epigenetics and Its Implications for Psychology
    Psicothema 2013, Vol. 25, No. 1, 3-12 ISSN 0214 - 9915 CODEN PSOTEG Copyright © 2013 Psicothema doi: 10.7334/psicothema2012.327 www.psicothema.com Epigenetics and its implications for Psychology Héctor González-Pardo and Marino Pérez Álvarez Universidad de Oviedo Abstract Resumen Background: Epigenetics is changing the widely accepted linear La epigenética y sus implicaciones para la Psicología. Antecedentes: conception of genome function by explaining how environmental and la epigenética está cambiando la concepción lineal que se suele tener de psychological factors regulate the activity of our genome without involving la genética al mostrar cómo eventos ambientales y psicológicos regulan changes in the DNA sequence. Research has identifi ed epigenetic la actividad de nuestro genoma sin implicar modifi cación en la secuencia mechanisms mediating between environmental and psychological factors de ADN. La investigación ha identifi cado mecanismos epigenéticos que that contribute to normal and abnormal behavioral development. Method: juegan un papel mediador entre eventos ambientales y psicológicos y el the emerging fi eld of epigenetics as related to psychology is reviewed. desarrollo normal y alterado. Método: el artículo revisa el campo emergente Results: the relationship between genes and behavior is reconsidered in de la epigenética y sus implicaciones para la psicología. Resultados: terms of epigenetic mechanisms acting after birth and not only prenatally, entre sus implicaciones destacan la reconsideración de la relación entre as traditionally held. Behavioral epigenetics shows that our behavior genes y conducta en términos de procesos epigenéticos que acontecen a lo could have long-term effects on the regulation of the genome function. largo de la vida y no solo prenatalmente como se asumía.
    [Show full text]
  • Workshop on Molecular Evolution (Extended Special Topics Session July 27-August 8,2003 August 8-August 15,2003) Course Director
    Workshop on Molecular Evolution July 27-August 8,2003 (Extended Special Topics Session August 8-August 15,2003) Course Director: Michael P. Cummings, University of Maryland and Marine Biological Laboratory Molecular evolution has become the nexus of many areas of biological research. It both brings together and enriches such areas as biochemistry, molecular biology, microbiology, population genetics, systematics, developmental biology, genomics, bioinformatics, in vitro evolution, and molecular ecology. The Workshop provides an important contribution to these fields in that it promotes interdisciplinary research and interaction, and thus provides a glue that sticks together disparate fields. Due to the wide range of fields addressed by the study of molecular evolution, it is difficult to offer a comprehensive course in a university setting. It is rare for a single institution to maintain expertise in all necessary areas. In contrast, the Workshop is uniquely able to provide necessary breadth and depth by utilizing a large number of faculty with appropriate expertise. Furthermore, the flexible nature of the Workshop allows for rapid adaptation to changes in the dynamic field of molecular evolution. For example, the 2003 Workshop included recently emergent research areas of molecular evolution of development and genomics. The interest in the Workshop remains very strong and is increasing. The number of applications for the 2003 course was 143, continuing the trend of increased applications since 2000. In 2003 there were 60 students participating in the Workshop, which was taught by 19 faculty and 4 teaching assistants. The students came from all over the world (1 7 countries), and represented several career stages: graduate students (57%), postdoctoral researchers (1 3%), faculty/principal investigators (27%), and other (3%).
    [Show full text]
  • Darwin & Progress
    Darwin & Progress Robert J. Richards, reply by Richard C. Lewontin December 15, 2005 Issue New York Review of Books In response to: The Wars Over Evolution from the October 20, 2005 issue To the Editors: In his review of Michael Ruse’s Evolution– Creation Struggle and Peter Richerson and Robert Boyd’s Not by Genes Alone [NYR, October 20], Richard Lewontin offers typically insightful analyses of the conflict that has arisen between creationists and IDers on the one hand and evolutionary biologists on the other. As well, he offers salutary cautions about the application of general models of cultural change based on evolutionary theory. He may be quite right that a deep fear of meaninglessness urges many individuals to fly to higher, governing powers and to reject the Darwinian slough of chance. Though Lewontin seems to agree with Ruse that some scientists mount the pulpit in trying to extend evolutionary considerations into all corners of human life, he yet chides him for locating the nub of the dispute in two different notions of progress, that characterizing Darwinism and that endemic to the old-time religion—the one leading nowhere in particular, the other to the ultimate transformation. Lewontin supposes that Darwin kept the ideology of progress from sullying his own theory. He offers as an index of Darwin’s freedom from taint the presumed fact that the word “evolution” (which in the embryological domain had been used to describe a predetermined unfolding) is absent from the first edition of the Origin. Well, not exactly. Rather famously the last sentence of the book hits the rhetorical high mark with “endless forms most beautiful and wonderful have been and are being evolved.” Later editions do not shy from use of the noun form of the word, nor does the Descent of Man.
    [Show full text]
  • Adaptationism
    Adaptationism Peter Godfrey-Smith and Jon F. Wilkins For the Blackwell Companion to the Philosophy of Biology [Draft K, Final. July 2006] 1. Introduction 2. The Development of the Debate 3. Varieties of Adaptationism 4. The Role of Zoom and Grain 1. Introduction The "adaptationism" debate is about the role of natural selection in relation to other evolutionary factors. The term "adaptationist" is used for views that assert or assume the primacy, or central importance, of natural selection in the project of explaining evolutionary change. This "central importance," however, can take a variety of forms. The debate can also involve questions about how natural selection operates, and what sorts of outcomes it tends to produce. But most discussion of adaptationism is about the relative significance of selection, in comparison with the various other factors that affect evolution. The term "adaptationism" is only a few decades old, but the debate itself is an extension of long-running debates that reach back to the early days of evolutionary theory in the late 19th century. Darwin himself constantly fine-tuned his claims about the relations between natural selection and other evolutionary factors, especially in successive editions of the Origin of Species. Many of the topics covered in recent debates can also be recognized in debates about gradualism, the role of mutation, and the significance of 1 Mendelism to evolutionary theory in the early 20th century (Provine 1971). During the early years of the "evolutionary synthesis," the debate between R. A. Fisher and Sewall Wright was in large part a debate about the role of subtle non-selective factors such as population structure and random drift (Fisher 1930, Wright 1932).
    [Show full text]
  • Richard C. Lewontin
    Obituary Richard C. Lewontin (1929–2021) Pioneer of molecular evolution who campaigned against biological racism. ichard Lewontin was a groundbreak- ecologist Dick Levins and support from the ing geneticist, best known for bringing Ford Foundation, he assembled a group to molecular tools into evolutionary investigate the role of capital in agricultural biology and for his advocacy against research, such as the development of hybrid the use of science to rationalize struc- crop plants. Lewontin and Levins’s collabora- Rtural inequity. Lewontin and his collaborators tion also led to a series of essays on biology revealed how natural selection acts to shape and society from a Marxist perspective, pub- variation, exploring its effect on genes, groups lished later as The Dialectical Biologist (1985) and individuals. Moving between mathemat- and Biology Under the Influence (2007). Like ical and statistical analysis, fieldwork and his critiques of sociobiology, many of these laboratory experiment, they set the course essays treated science as politics, arguing of molecular population genetics. Lewontin against reductionism and determinism that saw no place for his discipline in attempts to favoured biological explanations of complex explain why “the children of oil magnates tend biosocial phenomena. to become bankers, while the children of oil Lewontin also spoke up against biological workers tend to be in debt to banks”. racism. His landmark paper ‘The Apportion- Lewontin’s sometimes controversial ment of Human Diversity’ (in Evolutionary Biol- critiques of science, often from a Marxist ogy Vol. 6 (eds T. Dobzhansky et al.) Springer, ERNST MAYR LIBRARY AND ARCHIVES OF THE MUSEUM OF COMPARATIVE ZOOLOGY, HARVARD UNIV.
    [Show full text]