Xerox University Microfilms

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Xerox University Microfilms INFORMATION TO USERS This material was produced from a microfilm copy of the orignal document. While the most advanced technological means to photograph and reproduce this document have been used, the quality is heavily dependent upon the quality of the original submitted. The following explanation of techniques is provided to help you understand markings or patterns which may appear on this reproduction. 1. The sign or "target" for pages apparently lacking from the document photographed is "Missing Page(s)". If it was possible to obtain the missing page(s) or section, they are spliced into the film along with adjacent pages. This may have necessitated cutting thru an image and duplicating adjacent pages to insure you complete continuity. 2. When an image on the film is obliterated with a large round black mark, it is an indication that the photographer suspected that the copy may have moved during exposure and thus cause a blurred image. You will find a good image of the page in the adjacent frame. 3. When a map, drawing or chart, etc., was part of the material being photographed the photographer followed a definite method in "sectioning" the material. It is customary to begin photoing at the upper left hand comer of a large sheet and to continue photoing from left to riÿrt in equal sections with a small overlap. If necessary, sectioning is . continued again — beginning below the first row and continuing on until 4. The majority of users indicate that tiie textual content is of greatest value, however, a somewhat higher quality reproduction could be made from "photographs" if essential to the understanding of the dissertation. Silver prints of "photographs" may be ordered at additional charge by writing the Order Department, gving the ca^oq number, title, author and specific pages you wish reproduced. 5. PLEASE NOTE: Some pages may have indistinct print. Filmed as received. Xerox University Microfilms 300 North Zeeb Road Ann Arbor, Michigan 48106 74-24,324 FOSTER, Thomas Rowland, 1942- THE RUSSELL-LEIBNIZ DEFINITION OF IDENTITY: SOME PROBLEMS. The Ohio State University, Ph.D., 1974 Philosophy University Microfilms, A XEROX Company, Ann Arbor, Michigan © Copyright by Thomas Eowland Poster 1974 THIS DISSERTATION HAS BEEN MICROFILMED EXACTLY AS RECEIVED. THE HUSSELL-LEIBHIZ DEFIIîITIOH OE IDEHTITT: SOME PROBLEMS DISSEETÂTIOH Presented in Partial Pulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Thomas Rowland Poster, B.A. The Ohio State University 1974 Reading Committee: Approved By Robert Turnbull Lee Brown Adviser Department of Philosophy ACKJJOWLEDGMENTS I wish, to make my acknowledgments brief. Alain Hausman of Ohio State, advisor and co-author of the last chapter, has carefully read and helpfully criticized severail drafts of this thesis. Silvano Miracchi of Ball State, friend and colleague, has discussed many of the issues involved. Lastly, I wish to thank my wife, my friends, and the Department of Philosophy at Ball State for their patience during the completion of this task. 7 I T A July 21, 194-2 . Born— jBvanston, Illinois 1955 ........... B.A., Oberlin College, Oberlin, Ohio 1957-1971 ....... Teaching Assistant, Department of Philosophy, The Ohio State University, Columbus, Ohio 1958 ........... National Defense Education Act Fellowship, Title IV 1971-1974-....... Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, Ball State University, Munci e, Indiana FIELDS OF STUDY Major Fields: Metaphysics and Logic TART. t; 0? COMJENTS Page ACKITOWLEDGMENTS................................ ii 7 I T A ......................................... iii Cliapter I. INTEODUCÎDIOII TO THE P R O B L E M .............. 1 I. The Definition of Identity II. The Notion of Adequacy III. Challenges to the Definition II. THE PRINCIPLE OF SDBSTÜTIVITY............. 18 III. SYMMETRICAL DNI7ER8E8..................... 30 f: I. On Possibility II. The Distinguishing Property III. Weak and Strong Symmetry IV. Logically Proper Names V. Other Distinguishing Properties VI. On Showing the II True VII. The Property Difference IV. THE NECESSITY OF THE I I ................... 66 I. Unreasonable Demands II. Different Senses of Difference III. Arguments Attempting to Establish the Non-Necessity of the II IV. Differing Senses of Individuation V. The Notion of Property Difference V. THE IDENTITY OF INDISCERNIBLES AND KINDS OF T H I N G S ................................ 103 I. Criteria of Difference II. Cartwright's Argument III. A Distinction Between Classes and Attributes BIBLIOGRAPHY .................................. 159 INTEODUCTIOIî TO THE PHOBLEM This chapter will introduce and provide a back­ ground for the problems to which the next four chapters address themselves. This chapter, then, serves as an introduction to the facets of identity and difference that this dissertation will discuss in detail. In general, the aim of this thesis is to provide a defense of Russell's definition of identity.^ For the Russellian definition has come under attack from various quarters. The purpose of this chapter is to outline several of these attacks on Russell's definition, while the following chapters serve to answer each of the attacks in detail. In preparation for both the outline of the alleged problems and the defense of Russell's definition, I will, first, introduce Russell's definition and consider some of its important consequences, and how such consequences are related to the identity of indiscernibles as well as some other principles which involve identity. The question about the Russellian definition is over its adequacy. Bertrand Russell and Alfred North Whitehead, Principia Mathematica (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1914), p. 158. 2 Since this notion is crucial, the second section of this chapter shall he devoted to a brief discussion of the notion of what it is for a definition to be adequate, as well as some demands that are too restrictive. The last and most important section of this chapter will be an outline of several problems which will be discussed in detail in later chapters. I. The Definition of Identity One may introduce the sign into a formalism either as defined or as primitive. If the sign is introduced as a defined sign— in the manner that Russell does— then certain crucial sentences, such as (x) (y) (x/y=(3f) (fx--fy) ) are rendered necessary or analytic. They are necessary by virtue of the definition. In a system where the notion of sameness or difference is introduced as a primitive or undefined, similar sentences are not necessary or analytic. Often, however, the introduction of the "=” sign as primi­ tive in a formalism is accompanied by a set of rules and/or axioms. These axioms, such as ”(x)(x=x)," are derivable from the Russellian definition. The reluctance to intro­ duce "=” as defined probably stems from a desire to avoid quantifying over predicate variables, thereby avoiding commitment to properties. 3 Irrespective of whether the "='* sign is introduced as primitive or defined, questions may he raised as to the adequacy of the rules and/or axioms in the one case, and the definition in the other. Since the charges of inade­ quacy in either case are the same sort of charges, I shall introduce the "=" sign as defined in the Eussellian manner. Suppose, then, one does introduce the '*=” sign in the manner of Russell, namely, (1) x=y=df(f)(fx2fy) The motivation for defining identity in such a fashion is that one often thinks of x and y as being the same if, and only if, "they” share all properties in common. Conversely, one thinks of x and y as different, if, and only if, one has a property that the other lacks. The range of "f" in the definition is meant to include at least undefined predicates. It has been the subject of much debate as to whether the "f" of the definition should range over rela­ tional predicates such as "being-to-the-left-of-a," modal predicates such as "being-necessarily-f," metalinguistic predicates such as "being-designated-by-'a'" and predicates which involve identity, such as "...=a." 1 shall discuss neither modal predicates nor ones involving identity. 1 shall take relational predicates as within the range of "f" of the Eussellian definition. There will also be occasion to ^eak of "metalinguistic" predicates. 4 To begin with, it follows from the above definition that (2) (x) (y) (x=ys(f ) (f xsfy) ) Prom (2) it follows that both (3) (x)(y)(x=7 »(f)(fx=fy)) as well as (4) (x) (y) ( (f ) (fx=fy)^x=y) Equivalent to (5) and (4) respectively are: (5) (x)(y)((3f)(fx*-fy>x/y) and (5) (x)(y)(x?^y3(af)(fx--fy)) Notice that (2) - (6) all follow from the definition of "=" and are thus trivially true. Notice, further, that there is a rule which seems to be the metalinguistic counterpart of (3), namely, (7) x=y In questioning the adequacy of the Eussellian definition, the crucial sentences and/or rules under consideration will be (5), (5), and (7), respectively. The sorts of questions raised about the adequacy of (3) and (5), on the one hand, and (7) on the other will differ. Eor (7) is a rule of inference, while (3) and (6) are sentences. Rules are either valid or invalid, but neither true nor false as sentences are. 5 Notice that corresponding to sentence (3)? which is within the Eussellian formalism, there is another sen­ tence, not within the Eussellian formalism, as follows: (5)' If "two” things are one and the same, then "they" share all properties in common. Further, corresponding to sentence (6), there is the sentence (6)' For any pair of things, one has a property that the other lacks. Call (5)' and (6)' the principle of identity (PI) and the identity of indiscernibles (II) respectively. There is also an English counterpart of (7) which will be called the principle of substutivity (PS).
Recommended publications
  • Atheists' Challenges to Cosmological Arguments
    ATHEISTS’ CHALLENGES TO COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENTS PAUL CLAVIER Ecole Normale Supérieure, Paris Abstract. In this paper I intend to identify some points of disagreement between theism and atheism. I will try to point out three epistemological clashes occurring in the controversial treatment of cosmological arguments. I am not assessing the arguments pro and contra, which have been thoroughly studied and discussed, but just trying to understand the misunderstanding. By a cosmological argument, I will understand any argument to a first generating and sustaining cause of the universe. Suppose that, up to the present day, every purported cosmological argument has been defeated. This would not disprove theism. Would this provide a good presupposition in favour of agnosticism? Probably yes (except if the relevant God of theism was not creator, or if God’s existence could be accessed without implying the dependence of the world on God’s creative power). But of course, this would not preclude the success of further attempts to make a positive case for a creator. A more conclusive strategy would consist in finding out a flaw that generally dismisses every attempt to make a sound argument to a creator. A first flaw could be found in the very concept of creation out of nothing. A second flaw could be about which are the standards and which the right stopping point of a causal explanation of the world. And, finally, there could be Hume’s argument against the necessity of a cause to every new existence. For, if even a new existence is not crying out for an explanation, a fortiori the mere existence of anything at all will not.
    [Show full text]
  • The 13Th Annual ISNA-CISNA Education Forum Welcomes You!
    13th Annual ISNA Education Forum April 6th -8th, 2011 The 13th Annual ISNA-CISNA Education Forum Welcomes You! The ISNA-CISNA Education Forum, which has fostered professional growth and development and provided support to many Islamic schools, is celebrating its 13-year milestone this April. We have seen accredited schools sprout from grassroots efforts across North America; and we credit Allah, subhanna wa ta‘alla, for empowering the many men and women who have made the dreams for our schools a reality. Today the United States is home to over one thousand weekend Islamic schools and several hundred full-time Islamic schools. Having survived the initial challenge of galvanizing community support to form a school, Islamic schools are now attempting to find the most effective means to build curriculum and programs that will strengthen the Islamic faith and academic excellence of their students. These schools continue to build quality on every level to enable their students to succeed in a competitive and increasingly multicultural and interdependent world. The ISNA Education Forum has striven to be a major platform for this critical endeavor from its inception. The Annual Education Forum has been influential in supporting Islamic schools and Muslim communities to carry out various activities such as developing weekend schools; refining Qur‘anic/Arabic/Islamic Studies instruction; attaining accreditation; improving board structures and policies; and implementing training programs for principals, administrators, and teachers. Thus, the significance of the forum lies in uniting our community in working towards a common goal for our youth. Specific Goals 1. Provide sessions based on attendees‘ needs, determined by surveys.
    [Show full text]
  • Thomas Aquinas's Summa Theologiae
    Thomas Aquinas’s Summa Theologiae Thomas Aquinas’s Summa Theologiae A Guide and Commentary z BRIAN DAVIES 1 1 Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford New York Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi New Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto With o!ces in Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and certain other countries. Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press 198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016 © Oxford University Press 2014 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by license, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reproduction rights organization. Inquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above. You must not circulate this work in any other form and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Davies, Brian, 1951– Thomas Aquinas’s Summa theologiae : a guide and commentary / Brian Davies. pages cm Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-0-19-938062-6 (cloth : alk.
    [Show full text]
  • Formal Fallacies
    First Steps in Formal Logic Handout 16 Formal Fallacies A formal fallacy is an invalid argument grounded in logical form. Validity, again: an argument is valid iff the premises could not all be true yet the conclusion false; or, a rule of inference is valid iff it cannot lead from truth to falsehood, i.e. if the infer- ence preserves truth. The semantic turnstile ‘⊧’ indicates validity, so where P is the set of premises and C is the conclusion, P ⊧ C. We can also say that C is a ‘logical consequence’ of, or follows from, P. In a fallacious argument, this may seem to be the case, but P ⊭ C. There are also many informal fallacies (e.g., begging the question: petitio principii) that do not preserve truth either, but these are not grounded in logical form. Fallacies of Propositional Logic (PL) (1) Affirming the Consequent: φ ⊃ ψ, ψ ⊦ φ Examples: (a) ‘If Hume is an atheist, then Spinoza is an atheist too. Spinoza is an atheist. So, Hume is an atheist.’ (b) ‘If it rains, the street is wet. The street is wet. So it rains.’ (2) Denying the Antecedent: φ ⊃ ψ, ~φ ⊦ ~ψ Examples: (a) ‘If Locke is a rationalist, then Spinoza grinds lenses for a living. But Locke is not a rationalist. So, Spinoza does not grind lenses for a living.’ (b) ‘If it rains, the street it wet. It does not rain. So the street is not wet.’ Affirming the consequent and denying the antecedent are quite common fallacies. They ignore that the material implication lacks an intrinsic connection between antecedent and consequent.
    [Show full text]
  • Denying the Antecedent - Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia
    Denying the antecedent - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Help us provide free content to the world by • LearnLog more in /about create using Wikipediaaccount for research donating today ! • Article Discussion EditDenying this page History the antecedent From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Denying the antecedent is a formal fallacy, committed by reasoning in the form: If P , then Q . Navigation Not P . ● Main Page Therefore, not Q . ● Contents Arguments of this form are invalid (except in the rare cases where such an argument also ● Featured content instantiates some other, valid, form). Informally, this means that arguments of this form do ● Current events ● Random article not give good reason to establish their conclusions, even if their premises are true. Interaction The name denying the ● About Wikipedia antecedent derives from the premise "not P ", which denies the 9, 2008 ● Community portal "if" clause of the conditional premise.Lehman, v. on June ● Recent changes Carver One way into demonstrate archivedthe invalidity of this argument form is with a counterexample with ● Contact Wikipedia Cited true premises06-35176 but an obviously false conclusion. For example: ● Donate to No. If Queen Elizabeth is an American citizen, then she is a human being. Wikipedia ● Help Queen Elizabeth is not an American citizen. Therefore, Queen Elizabeth is not a human being. Search That argument is obviously bad, but arguments of the same form can sometimes seem superficially convincing, as in the following example imagined by Alan Turing in the article "Computing Machinery and Intelligence": “ If each man had a definite set of rules of conduct by which he regulated his life he would be no better than a machine.
    [Show full text]
  • Observations on Sick Mathematics Andrew Aberdein
    ESSAY 1 Observations on Sick Mathematics Andrew Aberdein And you claim to have discovered this . from observations on sick people? (Freud 1990: 13) This paper argues that new light may be shed on mathematical reason- ing in its non-pathological forms by careful observation of its patholo- gies. The first section explores the application to mathematics of recent work on fallacy theory, specifically the concept of an ‘argumentation scheme’: a characteristic pattern under which many similar inferential steps may be subsumed. Fallacies may then be understood as argumen- tation schemes used inappropriately. The next section demonstrates how some specific mathematical fallacies may be characterized in terms · Andrew Aberdein of argumentation schemes. The third section considers the phenomenon of correct answers which result from incorrect methods. This turns out to pose some deep questions concerning the nature of mathematical knowledge. In particular, it is argued that a satisfactory epistemology for mathematical practice must address the role of luck. Otherwise, we risk being unable to distinguish successful informal mathematical rea- soning from chance. We shall see that argumentation schemes may play a role in resolving this problem too.1 Mathematical errors occur in many different forms. In his classic short treatment of the topic, E.A. Maxwell distinguished the simple mistake, which may be caused by ‘a momentary aberration, a slip in writing, or the misreading of earlier work,’ from the howler, ‘an error which leads innocently to a correct result,’ and the fallacy, which ‘leads by guile to a wrong but plausible conclusion’ (Maxwell 1959: 9). We might gloss this preliminary typology of mathematical error as correlating the (in)correctness of the result to the (un)soundness of the method, as in Table 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Forall X: Calgary. an Introduction to Formal Logic
    forallx CALGARY An Introduction to Formal Logic P. D. Magnus Tim Button with additions by J. Robert Loftis Robert Trueman remixed and revised by Aaron Thomas-Bolduc Richard Zach Fall 2021 forall x: Calgary An Introduction to Formal Logic By P. D. Magnus Tim Button with additions by J. Robert Loftis Robert Trueman remixed and revised by Aaron Thomas-Bolduc Richard Zach Fall 2021 This book is based on forallx: Cambridge, by Tim Button (University College London), used under a CC BY 4.0 license, which is based in turn on forallx, by P.D. Magnus (University at Albany, State Univer- sity of New York), used under a CC BY 4.0 license, and was remixed, revised, & expanded by Aaron Thomas-Bolduc & Richard Zach (Uni- versity of Calgary). It includes additional material from forallx by P.D. Magnus and Metatheory by Tim Button, used under a CC BY 4.0 license, from forallx: Lorain County Remix, by Cathal Woods and J. Robert Loftis, and from A Modal Logic Primer by Robert Trueman, used with permission. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 license. You are free to copy and redistribute the material in any medium or format, and remix, transform, and build upon the material for any purpose, even commer- cially, under the following terms: ⊲ You must give appropriate credit, provide a link to the license, and indicate if changes were made. You may do so in any reasonable manner, but not in any way that suggests the licensor endorses you or your use. ⊲ You may not apply legal terms or technological measures that legally restrict others from doing anything the license permits.
    [Show full text]
  • Education, Professionalism, and the Quest for Accountability: Hitting The
    Education, Professionalism, and the Quest for Accountability Routledge International Studies in the Philosophy of Education 1. Education and Work in Great 11. Education, Work and Britain, Germany and Italy Social Capital Edited by A. Jobert, C. Marry, Towards a New Conception of L. Tanguy and H. Rainbird Vocational Education Christopher Winch 2. Education, Autonomy and Democratic Citizenship 12. Philosophical Discussion in Philosophy in a Changing World Moral Education Edited by David Bridges The Community of Ethical Inquiry Tim Sprod 3. The Philosophy of Human Learning Christopher Winch 13. Methods in the Philosophy of Education 4. Education, Knowledge and Truth Frieda Heyting, Dieter Lenzen and Beyond the Postmodern Impasse John White Edited by David Carr 14. Life, Work and Learning 5. Virtue Ethics and Moral Education Practice in Postmoderniity Edited by David Carr and Jan Steutel David Beckett and Paul Hager 6. Durkheim and Modern Education 15. Education, Autonomy and Edited by Geoffrey Walford and Critical Thinking W. S. F. Pickering Christopher Winch 7. The Aims of Education 16. Anarchism and Education Edited by Roger Marples A Philosophical Perspective Judith Suissa 8. Education in Morality J. Mark Halstead and 17. Cultural Diversity, Liberal Terence H. McLaughlin Pluralism and Schools Isaiah Berlin and Education 9. Lyotard: Just Education Neil Burtonwood Edited by Pradeep A. Dhillon and Paul Standish 18. Levinas and Education At the Intersection of Faith and Reason 10. Derrida & Education Edited by Denise Egéa-Kuehne Edited by Gert J J Biesta and Denise Egéa-Kuehne 19. Moral Responsibility, Authenticity, and Education Ishtiyaque Haji and Stefaan E. Cuypers 20. Education, Science and Truth Rasoul Nejadmehr 21.
    [Show full text]
  • Sin: a Thomistic Psychology Was Designed in Adobe Jenson and Composed by Kachergis Book Design of Pittsboro, North Carolina
    Sin Sin A ThomisTic Psychology StSineven J. Jensen The Catholic UniversiTy of AmericA Press Washington, D.C. Copyright © 2018 The Catholic University of America Press All rights reserved The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of American National Standards for Information Science—Permanence of Paper for Printed Library Materials, ANSI Z39.48-1984. ∞ Cataloging-in-Publication Data available from the Library of Congress isbn 978-0-8132-3033-7 � For Roy Lepak En soledad vivía, y en soledad ha puesto ya su nido, y en soledad la guía a solas su querido, también en soledad de amor herido. Juan de la Cruz � In memoriam James Stromberg 1926–2017 A la tarde te examinarán en el amor. Juan de la Cruz ConTenTs Acknowledgments ix 1. The Enigma of an Evil Will 1 2. The Order of Actions to the Ultimate End 15 3. The Satisfaction of Desire 41 4. Venial Sin 66 5. The First Moral Act 84 6. The Shared Good 103 7. Sins of Passion 124 8. Weakness of Will 142 9. Sins from an Evil Will 158 10. Sins of Ignorance 185 11. Omissions 194 12. The First Cause of Moral Evil 212 13. Compatibilism or Libertarianism 238 14. Free Decision 260 15. Choose Life 285 Bibliography 293 Index 301 vii AcknowledgmenTs I would like to thank all those who have helped with this book. Michael Torre, as well as an anonymous reviewer, provided many valuable suggestions. My wife, Christine, whose love supports me in all of my work, supplied careful reading and correction. I would also like to thank Louise A.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Philosophical Logic for Practitioners
    04-Fulford-Chap05.qxd 08/06/2006 10:44 AM Page 90 OUP Copyrigh t CHAPTER 5 Arguments good and bad: an introduction to philosophical logic for practitioners Chapter contents Session 1 An introduction to deductive reasoning and formal logic 92 Session 2 An introduction to the philosophy of logic: what underpins deductive logic? 98 Session 3 Conclusions: implication and entailment 105 Appendix Some of the more common forms of invalid argument 107 Reading guide 109 References 110 OUP Copyrigh t 04-Fulford-Chap05.qxd 08/06/2006 10:44 AM Page 91 CHAPTER 5 an introduction to philosophical logic for practitioners 91 AchillesOUP joyfully exclaimed, as he ran the pencilCopyrigh into its sheath. psychiatrists and clinical psychologists have to bet able use current ‘And at last we’ve got to the end of this ideal race-course! Now diagnostic classifications, so professional philosophers have to be that you accept A and B and C and D, of course you accept Z.’ able to use logic. ‘Do I?’ said the Tortoise innocently. ‘Let’s make that quite clear. The second aim of this chapter is in a sense the opposite of the Iaccept A and B and C and D. Suppose I still refuse to accept Z?’ corresponding aim of Chapter 3. In setting out the details of ‘Then Logic would take you by the throat, and force you to do it!’ descriptive psychopathology, we aimed to get across to philoso- Achilles triumphantly replied. phers that if they want to work in this area, there is a good deal of detail with which they have to be prepared to get up to speed— What The Tortoise Said To Achilles detail derived not just from professional but also lay (narrative) Lewis Carroll, originally published in Mind sources.
    [Show full text]
  • False Persuasion, Superficial Heuristics, and the Power of Logical Form to Test the Integrity of Legal Argument
    Pace Law Review Volume 34 Issue 1 Winter 2014 Article 3 January 2014 False Persuasion, Superficial Heuristics, and the Power of Logical Form to Test the Integrity of Legal Argument Stephen M. Rice Liberty University School of Law Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.pace.edu/plr Part of the Legal Education Commons, and the Legal History Commons Recommended Citation Stephen M. Rice, False Persuasion, Superficial Heuristics, and the owerP of Logical Form to Test the Integrity of Legal Argument, 34 Pace L. Rev. 76 (2014) Available at: https://digitalcommons.pace.edu/plr/vol34/iss1/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the School of Law at DigitalCommons@Pace. It has been accepted for inclusion in Pace Law Review by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@Pace. For more information, please contact [email protected]. False Persuasion, Superficial Heuristics, and the Power of Logical Form to Test the Integrity of Legal Argument Stephen M. Rice* “[A]rguments, like men, are often pretenders.” Plato1 I. An Introduction to the Practical Problem of Illogic in Legal Argument Lawyers hold themselves out to be masters of persuasion but often fail to study two topics that are important to the art of legal advocacy: logic2 and psychology.3 These topics are not part of the mainstream law school curriculum. They are not required topics on any state’s bar examination. While there are justifications for the absence of these topics in the law school curriculum, this absence seems strange considering that lawyers study as specifically and intentionally as any other group in our society to offer and scrutinize arguments designed * Stephen M.
    [Show full text]
  • Deletion and Logical Form
    DELETION AND LOGICAL FORM by IVAN ANDREW SAG B.A., University of Rochester 1971 M.A., University of Pennsylvania 1973 SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY at the MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY June, 1976 Signature of Author.../.. a Dep r n9fFrg Literatures and y .inguist cs Certified by....... ................. Thesis Supervisor Accepted by........ ...-.. ..................... Chairman, Departmental Committee on Graduate Students JUN 25 1976 2 Deletion and Logical Form Ivan Andrew Sag Submitted to the Department of Foreign Literatures and Linguistics on June 22, 1976 in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. ABSTRACT This thesis incorporates a detailed study of two deletion rules in English: Verb Phrase Deletion and Gapping. It establishes a fundamental connection between the familiar notion of the recoverability of deletion and matters of logical form. Chapter One is an investigation of the syntax of Verb Phrase Deletion. Previous proposals for the constituent structure of VP and AUX are examined and rejected in favor of one that accommodates a proper formulation of that rule. In the second chapter, it is argued that logical considerations play an important role in determining the applicability of such rules as Verb Phrase Deletion. A theory of logical form is sketched, as well as a theory of the recoverability of deletion. Those theories are justified on the basis of many new facts about the interaction of deletion and quantifier interpretation and certain well-known facts such as the problem of "sloppy identity". Chapter Three concerns the rule of Gapping. A reformulation of that rule is offered in light of various inadequacies of previous proposals that are observed.
    [Show full text]