Falsity, Insincerity, and the Freedom of Expression

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Falsity, Insincerity, and the Freedom of Expression William & Mary Bill of Rights Journal Volume 16 (2007-2008) Issue 4 Article 10 April 2008 Falsity, Insincerity, and the Freedom of Expression Mark Spottswood Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmborj Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, and the First Amendment Commons Repository Citation Mark Spottswood, Falsity, Insincerity, and the Freedom of Expression, 16 Wm. & Mary Bill Rts. J. 1203 (2008), https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmborj/vol16/iss4/10 Copyright c 2008 by the authors. This article is brought to you by the William & Mary Law School Scholarship Repository. https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmborj FALSITY, INSINCERITY, AND THE FREEDOM OF EXPRESSION Mark Spottswood* ABSTRACT Three decades ago, the Supreme Court announced that false statements of fact are devoid of constitutional value, without providing either a reasoned explanation for that principle or any supporting citations. This assertion has become one of the most frequently repeated dogmas of First Amendment law and theory, endlessly repeated and never challenged. Disturbingly, this idea has provided the theoretic foundation for a regime in which some speakers can be penalized for even honestly- believed factual errors. Even worse, this dogma is flat wrong. False statements often have value in themselves, and we should protect them even in some situations where we are not concerned with chilling truthful speech. When false statements are spoken sincerely, they are a useful and necessary part of argumentation, which is a powerful means of increasing human knowledge. When confronted with honest errors, proponents of competing beliefs have a natural impulse to contest them; in so doing, they unearth and disseminate facts that deepen the under- standing of both speakers and listeners. False speech, therefore, is valuable because it is an essential part of a larger system that works to increase society's knowledge. The benefits of false speech evaporate, however, when we move from honest errors to deliberate lies. Insincere speech tends to corrode, rather than further, argument. It is associated with a number of practices that deprive argument of its knowledge-promoting features. We may sometimes wish to protect insincere speech to avoid chilling truthful speech, but we should always do so cautiously. After providing a summary of the existing law and scholarship concerning false speech, this Article analyzes the harms and benefits of false, insincere, and misleading speech. This question will be approached from the perspective of social veritistic epistemology, which will permit a detailed assessment of the consequences of various types of deceptive speech for the state of societal knowledge. I will conclude by suggesting some ways in which existing First Amendment doctrine * Law Clerk to the Honorable Rebecca R. Pallmeyer, United States District Court for the Northern District of Illinois. The author wishes to thank Professor Martin Redish for his invaluable guidance and advice in the preparation of this Article; thanks also to Micah Schwartzmann for his insight on the concept of sincerity. © 2008 by the Author. Permission is hereby granted to duplicate this Article for scholarly or teaching purposes, including permission to reproduce multiple copoies or post on the Internet for classroom use, subject to the inclusion of this copyright notice, the title, and the name of the author. 1203 1204 WILLIAM & MARY BILL OF RIGHTS JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1203 could be reformed in order to better account for the constitutional value of false speech. Ultimately, it is insincerity, not falsity, which has "no essential part of any exposition of ideas," and is of "slight social value as a step to truth." Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.S. 568, 572 (1942). Even a false statement may be deemed to make a valuable contribution to public debate, since it brings about "the clearer perception and livelier impression of truth, produced by its collision with error." -New York Times Co. v. Sullivan (quoting J.S. Mill) (1964)' [T]here is no constitutional value in false statements of fact. Neither the intentional lie nor the careless error materially advances society's interest in "uninhibited, robust and wide-open" debate on public issues. -- Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc. (1974)2 INTRODUCTION The two quotations above illustrate the confusion of the Supreme Court when it has applied the Speech and Press Clauses3 to speech that is false, insincere, or misleading. Sometimes the Court is willing to give quite strong protections to speech that is false, as in the public official defamation context,4 while in other contexts, such as restrictions on commercial speech, the Court has suggested that it would not protect even innocent errors in public discourse.5 The most persistent theme of the Court's decisions in this area, however, is a reluctance to proceed beyond such superficial pronouncements and explain why the First Amendment should, or should not, value speech that is untrue or insincere. The confusion in the Court's treatment is mirrored in the scattered scholarship on this issue. Although John Stuart Mill devoted considerable attention to the relation- ship between a free speech principle and the social value of false speech,6 other scholars noted the defects in his treatment almost immediately, especially the fact that he examined examples of false speech in religious and political contexts to the exclusion of examining discourse about "facts."7 376 U.S. 254, 279 n.19 (1964) (quoting JOHN STUART MILL, On Liberty, in ON LIIERTY AND OTHER WRrriNGs 5, 20 (Stefan Collini ed., Cambridge Univ. Press 1989)). 2 418 U.S. 323, 340 (1974) (citations omitted). 3 U.S. CONST. amend. I. 4 See, e.g., Sullivan, 376 U.S. at 271-86. ' See, e.g., Va. State Bd. of Pharm. v. Va. Citizens Consumer Council, 425 U.S. 748 (1976). 6 See MILL, supra note 1, at 19-55. 7 See JAMEs FIT7JAMES STEPHEN, LIBERTY, EQUALITY, FRATERNrrY 74-77 (R.J. White ed., Cambridge Univ. Press 1967) (2d ed. 1874); see also discussion infra Part I.B.1. 2008] FALSITY, INSINCERITY, AND THE FREEDOM OF EXPRESSION 1205 Strikingly, Mill's project was never taken up where he left off; rather, modem scholarly treatments of the relationship between free expression and falsity have tended to whistle their way past important assumptions about the values of falsity and insincerity in public discourse, rarely spending any time trying to justify or assess the degree to which falsity in speech is detrimental to free speech values.8 As a result, both modem case law and scholarship on the relationship between free speech, falsity, and insincerity tend to be "casual, almost offhand," as Justice Douglas once characterized the arbitrary decision to exclude all commercial speech from First Amendment protection. 9 Thus, it is quite possible that these shallow 0 treatments, like the old rule on commercial speech, "[will] not survive[] reflection."' It is the purpose of this Article to analyze the degree to which this might be the case. This Article will, for the first time, undertake a detailed analysis of the harms and benefits that can flow from the various types of deceptive speech, including false speech (speech which does not accurately describe the world), insincere speech (speech which misrepresents a speaker's belief), and misleading speech (speech which may be literally true but which carries false or insincere implications). In this analysis, I will employ the tools of social veritistic epistemology" in order to assess when these types of speech are likely to increase the total number of false beliefs held by speakers and listeners. This epistemological approach has the capacity to illuminate questions that have remained obscure for some time. The thesis of this Article is that speech that is false but sincerely believed by its utterer is generally protected by the First Amendment because such speech generally promotes the growth of social knowledge. Insincere speech, however, is excluded from First Amendment protection in almost all cases because it tends to inhibit, rather than promote, the increase of knowledge. Finally, misleading speech receives constitu- tional protection to the degree that its implied meanings represent what a speaker believes, whether or not those beliefs are false; it is only the insincere use of implied meanings that excludes speech from protection. However, this type of exception should only exist when the implied meaning of the speech is insincere, not merely when inferences might be drawn from a statement that would not be believed by the speaker. The common theory tying all of these claims together is that the practice of good-faith argumentation by proponents of competing views is generally more conducive to the increase of knowledge than a regime that suppresses views that are probably false (when certain supporting conditions are met).' 2 In other words, the 8 See discussion infra Parts I.B.2-3. 9 Cammarano v. United States, 358 U.S. 498, 514 (1959) (Douglas, J., concurring). 10 Id. " See ALvIN I. GOLDMAN, KNOWLEDGE IN A SocLAL WORLD 4-5 (1999) (defining and discussing this term). 12 See discussion infra Part II.C (discussing the Truth-in-Evidence Principle and its relationship with defeater argumentation). 1206 WILLIAM & MARY BILL OF RIGHTS JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1203 best way to arrive at true judgments is to listen to argument by proponents of opposing beliefs, rather than making an initial judgment on the validity of the question and suppressing contrary viewpoints. To the degree we believe that the First Amendment is designed to promote the growth of human knowledge, 3 such considerations point towards recognizing constitutional value in all sincere speech, whether or not it is false. But even if we reject such a view, an assessment of the degree to which false speech can advance our knowledge is critical if we wish to accurately compare the harm of protecting false speech with the harm of prohibiting it.
Recommended publications
  • Falsity and the First Amendment G
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Southern Methodist University SMU Law Review Volume 72 | Issue 3 Article 10 2019 Falsity and the First Amendment G. Edward White University of Virginia School of Law, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.smu.edu/smulr Part of the First Amendment Commons, Jurisprudence Commons, and the Supreme Court of the United States Commons Recommended Citation G. Edward White, Falsity and the First Amendment, 72 SMU L. Rev. 513 (2019) https://scholar.smu.edu/smulr/vol72/iss3/10 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Journals at SMU Scholar. It has been accepted for inclusion in SMU Law Review by an authorized administrator of SMU Scholar. For more information, please visit http://digitalrepository.smu.edu. FALSITY AND THE FIRST AMENDMENT G. Edward White* ABSTRACT This Article considers the extent to which the exclusion of forms of speech from the coverage of the First Amendment has turned on the falsity of statements within the excluded categories. It does so, first, by reviewing the Supreme Court’s early and mid-twentieth century free speech decisions, to demonstrate that none of the principal cases in which the Court swept a particular category of expression within the First Amendment’s coverage involved speech that was false; and, second, by suggesting that when the Court first announced that some “breathing space” was required for factu- ally inaccurate statements about public officials or private citizens associ- ated with matters of public concern, it was less concerned with protecting false speech than with shielding inaccurate comments from being punished because they were provocative.
    [Show full text]
  • WASHLITE Answer to Fox News Reply
    81512-1 81512-1 FILED Court of Appeals Division I State of Washington 12lll2020 3:57 PM Docket No. 81512-1 IN THE WASHINGTON COURT OF APPEALS DIVISION ONE WASHINGTON LEAGUE FOR INCREASED TRANSPARENCY & ETHICS, a Washington non-profit corporation, JOHN & JANE DOES 1-1000 Plaintiffs/Appellants v. FOX CORPORATION, a Delaware corporation; FOX NEWS NETWORK, LLC, a Delaware corporation d/b/a FOX NEWS CHANNEL; FOX BUSINESS NETWORK, a for profit company d/b/a/ FOX BUSINESS; JOHN MOE and JANE MOE, 1-100 Defendants/Respondents. APPPELLANT’S REPLY BRIEF Catherine C. Clark THE LAW OFFICE OF CATHERINE C. CLARK PLLC 2200 Sixth Avenue, Suite 1250 Phone: (206) 838-2528 Fax: (206) 374-3003 Email: cat@loccc. com Attorneys for Washington League For Increased Transparency & Ethics Table of Contents I. INTRODUCTION .................................................................. 1 II. AUTHORITIES AND ARGUMENT ....................................... 2 A. THIS CASE IS ABOUT SPREADING FALSEHOODS, NOT ABOUT COMMENTARY OR OPINION ............ 2 B. THE DOCTRINE OF PRIOR RESTRAINT HAS NOT BEEN TRIGGERED .................................................. 8 C. FOX’S ARGUMENT THAT WASHLITE HAS NOT PROVEN ITS CASE IGNORES THE STANDARD OF REVIEW UNDER CR 12(B)(6) ................................ 10 D. THERE IS NO WASHINGTON AUTHORITY FOR INCLUDING ELECTRONIC WORKING COPY FEES WITHIN FILING FEES UNDER RCW 4. 84. 010 ..... 11 E. FOX IS NOT ENTITLED TO FEES ......................... 13 III. CONCLUSION ................................................................... 15 i Table of Authorities Cases Auburn Police Union v. Carpenter, 8 F.3d 886 (1st Cir. 1993) ........................................................... 9 Balboa Island Village Inn, Inc. v. Lemen, 40 Cal. 4th 1141, 57 Cal. Rptr. 3d 320, 156 P. 3d 339 (Cal. 2007)............................................................................................... 9 Bauman v. Turpen, 139 Wn.
    [Show full text]
  • Finding the Lost Involuntary Public Figure Jeffrey Omar Usman Belmont University School of Law
    Utah Law Review Volume 2014 | Number 5 Article 1 8-2014 Finding the Lost Involuntary Public Figure Jeffrey Omar Usman Belmont University School of Law Follow this and additional works at: https://dc.law.utah.edu/ulr Part of the Communications Law Commons, Constitutional Law Commons, and the First Amendment Commons Recommended Citation Usman, Jeffrey Omar (2014) "Finding the Lost Involuntary Public Figure," Utah Law Review: Vol. 2014 : No. 5 , Article 1. Available at: https://dc.law.utah.edu/ulr/vol2014/iss5/1 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Utah Law Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Utah Law Review by an authorized editor of Utah Law Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. FINDING THE LOST INVOLUNTARY PUBLIC FIGURE Jeffrey Omar Usman∗ Though their quarry is shrouded in mystery,1 and indeed sometimes thought to be only a creature of myth or legend,2 a number of judges, both those acting alone3 and those concentrated in groups,4 claim to have seen an involuntary public figure cross their paths. Descriptions have been offered, and those descriptions have been dutifully reported.5 It is not clear though that the judges saw either the same thing or the same thing from the same angle.6 ∗ © 2014 Jeffrey Omar Usman. Assistant Professor of Law, Belmont University School of Law. L.L.M., Harvard Law School; J.D., Vanderbilt University Law School; B.A., Georgetown University. I offer my appreciation to Christine Davis, Brett Knight, and Nate Lykins for their excellent assistance and for the able and skillful editorial aide provided by the members of the Utah Law Review most especially Mark Capone, Larissa Lee, and Christopher Mitchell.
    [Show full text]
  • Declaring the Law Unconstitutional Last Year
    FOR PUBLICATION UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE NINTH CIRCUIT UNITED STATES OF AMERICA, No.08-50345 Plaintiff-Appellee, D.C. No. v. 2:07-cr-01035- XAVIER ALVAREZ, AKA Javier RGK-1 Alvarez, OPINION Defendant-Appellant. Appeal from the United States District Court for the Central District of California R. Gary Klausner, District Judge, Presiding Argued and Submitted November 4, 2009—Pasadena, California Filed August 17, 2010 Before: Thomas G. Nelson, Jay S. Bybee, and Milan D. Smith, Jr., Circuit Judges. Opinion by Judge Milan D. Smith, Jr.; Dissent by Judge Bybee 11845 UNITED STATES v. ALVAREZ 11849 COUNSEL Jonathan D. Libby, Deputy Federal Public Defender, Los Angeles, California, for the defendant-appellant. Craig H. Missakian, Assistant U.S. Attorney, Cyber and Intel- lectual Property Section, Los Angeles, California, for the plaintiff-appellee. OPINION M. SMITH, Circuit Judge: Defendant-Appellant Xavier Alvarez conditionally pleaded guilty to one count of falsely verbally claiming to have received the Congressional Medal of Honor, in violation of the Stolen Valor Act (the Act), 18 U.S.C. § 704(b), (c),1 reserving his right to appeal the Act’s constitutionality. 1Although predecessor versions have existed since 1948, the current form of the Act was passed in 2006. In that year, Congress found that “[f]raudulent claims surrounding the receipt of the Medal of Honor [and other Congressionally authorized military medals, decorations, and awards] damage the reputation and meaning of such decorations and med- als,” and that “[l]egislative action is necessary to permit law enforcement officers to protect the reputation and meaning of military decorations and medals.” Stolen Valor Act of 2005, Pub.
    [Show full text]
  • 11-210 United States V. Alvarez (06/28/2012)
    (Slip Opinion) OCTOBER TERM, 2011 1 Syllabus NOTE: Where it is feasible, a syllabus (headnote) will be released, as is being done in connection with this case, at the time the opinion is issued. The syllabus constitutes no part of the opinion of the Court but has been prepared by the Reporter of Decisions for the convenience of the reader. See United States v. Detroit Timber & Lumber Co., 200 U. S. 321, 337. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES Syllabus UNITED STATES v. ALVAREZ CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE NINTH CIRCUIT No. 11–210. Argued February 22, 2012—Decided June 28, 2012 The Stolen Valor Act makes it a crime to falsely claim receipt of mili- tary decorations or medals and provides an enhanced penalty if the Congressional Medal of Honor is involved. 18 U. S. C. §§704 (b), (c). Respondent pleaded guilty to a charge of falsely claiming that he had received the Medal of Honor, but reserved his right to appeal his claim that the Act is unconstitutional. The Ninth Circuit reversed, finding the Act invalid under the First Amendment. Held: The judgment is affirmed. Pp. 3−18. 617 F. 3d 1198, affirmed. JUSTICE KENNEDY, joined by THE CHIEF JUSTICE, JUSTICE GINSBURG, and JUSTICE SOTOMAYOR, concluded that the Act infringes upon speech protected by the First Amendment. Pp. 3–18. (a) The Constitution “demands that content-based restrictions on speech be presumed invalid . and that the Government bear the burden of showing their constitutionality.” Ashcroft v. American Civ- il Liberties Union, 542 U.
    [Show full text]
  • Free Speech and Guilty Minds
    ESSAY FREE SPEECH AND GUILTY MINDS Leslie Kendrick* It is axiomatic that whether speech is protected turns on whether it poses a serious risk of harm—in Holmes’s formulation, a “clear and present danger.” If this is correct, then the state of mind, or intent, of the speaker should be irrelevant. Yet First Amendment law makes speaker’s intent a factor in the protection of many different kinds of speech. This Essay offers an account of why and how speaker’s intent matters for speech protection. It argues that strong intuitions work against imposing strict liability for speech. These intuitions are best explained by an interest in speaker’s intent. An autonomy-based account of free speech provides reasons for this interest. Such an account also suggests what kind of intent is necessary before a given speaker may be subject to regulation. Elucidating speaker’s intent thus explains a mysterious aspect of First Amendment law and uncovers a new argument for autonomy theories of free speech. INTRODUCTION ........................................................................................1256 I. THE PROBLEM OF SPEAKER’S INTENT ....................................................1260 II. THE CASE FOR SPEAKER’S INTENT ........................................................1265 A. Intent and Harm .........................................................................1268 B. On Criminal Law and Tort .........................................................1269 C. On the Chilling Effect ................................................................1277
    [Show full text]
  • Prior Restraint and Censorship: Acknowledged Occupational Hazards for Government Scientists
    William & Mary Environmental Law and Policy Review Volume 31 (2006-2007) Issue 3 Article 4 April 2007 Prior Restraint and Censorship: Acknowledged Occupational Hazards for Government Scientists Todd Stedeford Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmelpr Part of the Constitutional Law Commons Repository Citation Todd Stedeford, Prior Restraint and Censorship: Acknowledged Occupational Hazards for Government Scientists, 31 Wm. & Mary Envtl. L. & Pol'y Rev. 725 (2007), https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmelpr/vol31/iss3/4 Copyright c 2007 by the authors. This article is brought to you by the William & Mary Law School Scholarship Repository. https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmelpr PRIOR RESTRAINT AND CENSORSHIP: ACKNOWLEDGED OCCUPATIONAL HAZARDS FOR GOVERNMENT SCIENTISTS TODD STEDEFORD* INTRODUCTION Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion, or prohibiting the free exercise thereof; or abridg- ing the freedom of speech, or of the press; or the right of the people peaceably to assemble, and to petition the Govern- ment for a redress of grievances. -U.S. CONST. AMEND. I The Founders designed the First Amendment to the United States Constitution as retaliation against the requirement of prepublication clearance by the government.' Although the government may still impose a level of restriction on speech, the courts determine the level of scrutiny to be imparted on those restrictions.2 Based on the communicative con- tent, content-based restrictions imposed by the government may remove speech from
    [Show full text]
  • The Supreme Court from Snyder to Alvarez
    2012] 1 A MARINE’S HONOR: THE SUPREME COURT FROM SNYDER TO ALVAREZ Michael I. Krauss* INTRODUCTION In the last two years, the Supreme Court has dealt with two cases where the honor of servicemembers and their loved ones has been im- pugned. One case, Snyder v. Phelps,1 involved private law (a common law suit);2 the other, United States v. Alvarez,3 involved public law (a federal criminal statute).4 In both, the Supreme Court ruled that the First Amend- ment precluded efforts to protect military honor. I submit that the Supreme Court got both cases wrong. In its erroneous decisions, it betrayed a misun- derstanding of tort law and exacerbated a misuse of the First Amendment. I. PRIVATE V. PUBLIC LEGAL ORDERING My background perspective is one I have written about at some length.5 Private ordering regulates (horizontal) relationships among indi- viduals; public ordering regulates (vertical) state-citizen relationships. Tort law, like contract and property law, is a tool of private ordering intended to rectify individual wrongs that damage unwilling victims, not a means of public ordering. Criminal law, on the other hand, as part of public ordering, punishes individuals for wrongfully harming the collectivity. A totalitarian state, for instance, has no private ordering, while an anarcho-capitalistic society would have no public ordering. Tort regulates our interaction through private ordering. The state is not a party to a tort suit, except of course in its capacity as a private actor.6 The * Professor of Law, George Mason University School of Law, and father of 1st Lt.
    [Show full text]
  • The Freedom of Speech and Bad Purposes Eugene Volokh E W VI RE AW Abstract
    W The Freedom of Speech E VI and Bad Purposes RE Eugene Volokh AW AW L ABSTRACT A Can otherwise constitutionally protected speech lose its protection because of the UCL speaker’s supposedly improper purpose? The Supreme Court has sometimes said “no”—but sometimes it has endorsed tests (such as the incitement test) that do turn on a speaker’s purpose. Some lower courts have likewise rejected purpose tests. But others hold that, for instance, a purpose to annoy or distress can turn otherwise protected speech into criminal “harassment,” or that a selfish purpose can strip protection from otherwise protected government employee speech. This Article analyzes purpose tests in First Amendment law, and concludes that such tests are on balance unsound; the protection of speech should not turn on what a factfinder concludes about the speaker’s purposes. AUTHOR Gary T. Schwartz Professor of Law, UCLA School of Law ([email protected]). Many thanks to Samuel Bray, Claire Hill, Leslie Kendrick, Steven Lubet, Herb Morris, and Seana Shiffrin for their comments. TABLE OF CONTENts Introduction...........................................................................................................1368 I. Knowledge vs. Purpose .................................................................................1371 A. Negligence, Recklessness, and Knowledge Requirements in Other Areas of First Amendment Law..............................................................1371 B. Purpose Requirements .............................................................................1373
    [Show full text]
  • Funeral Picketing, Public Discourse, and the First Amendment
    University of Connecticut OpenCommons@UConn Connecticut Law Review School of Law 2012 To Drink the Cup of Fury: Funeral Picketing, Public Discourse, and the First Amendment Steven J. Heyman Follow this and additional works at: https://opencommons.uconn.edu/law_review Recommended Citation Heyman, Steven J., "To Drink the Cup of Fury: Funeral Picketing, Public Discourse, and the First Amendment" (2012). Connecticut Law Review. 174. https://opencommons.uconn.edu/law_review/174 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW VOLUME 45 NOVEMBER 2012 NUMBER 1 Article To Drink the Cup of Fury: Funeral Picketing, Public Discourse, and the First Amendment STEVEN J. HEYMAN In Snyder v. Phelps, the Supreme Court ruled that the Westboro Baptist Church had a First Amendment right to picket the funeral of a young soldier killed in Iraq. This decision reinforces a view that has become increasingly dominant in First Amendment jurisprudence—the view that the state may not regulate public discourse to protect individuals from emotional or dignitary injury. This Article contends that this view not only sacrifices the law’s protections for individual personality but also undermines the normative foundations of public discourse itself. The Article then presents an alternative theory of the First Amendment which holds that the same values of human dignity and autonomy that support free speech also give rise to other fundamental rights. Thus, speakers should have a duty to respect the personality and rights of others. Drawing extensively on the record in Snyder as well as on other materials, the Article argues that Westboro’s funeral picketing should not receive First Amendment protection, for the picketing is intended to condemn the deceased and to inflict severe distress on the mourners in violation of their rights to privacy, dignity, emotional well-being, and religious liberty.
    [Show full text]
  • In the Supreme Court of the United States
    No. 11-210 In the Supreme Court of the United States UNITED STATES OF AMERICA, PETITIONER, V. XAVIER ALVAREZ, RESPONDENT. ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE NINTH CIRCUIT BRIEF OF THE FIRST AMENDMENT LAWYERS ASSOCIATION AS AMICUS CURIAE IN SUPPORT OF RESPONDENT REED LEE ALLEN LICHTENSTEIN Counsel of Record Allen Lichtenstein, Ltd. J.D. Obenberger & Assoc. 3315 Russell Road 70 West Madison Street Suite 222 Chicago, Illinois 60602 Las Vegas, Nevada 89120 (312) 558-6427 (702) 433-2666 [email protected] Counsel for Amicus Curiae LEGAL PRINTERS LLC, Washington DC ! 202-747-2400 ! legalprinters.com i TABLE OF CONTENTS TABLE OF CONTENTS............................................i TABLE OF AUTHORITIES.....................................iv INTEREST OF AMICUS...........................................1 CONSENT OF THE PARTIES.................................1 ARGUMENT IN SUPPORT OF RESPONDENT....1 I. First Amendment Analysis, as this Court Has Articulated It for Decades, Is Properly Hostile to the Sort of Approach Which The Government Urges Here.............................................................1 A. Chaplinsky’s Categorical Approach to Speech Protection Questions Has Served the First Amendment Well Principally Because this Court Has Wisely Kept the “Exceptions” Indi- vidually Small and Collectively Few...............2 B. Most of Chaplinsky’s “Exceptions” Arise from Free Expression Principles Themselves, Not Because Other Considerations Overcome Such Constitutional Concerns...................................5
    [Show full text]
  • Professors Eugene Volokh and James Weinstein As Amici Curiae in Support of Petitioner
    No. 11-210 In the Supreme Court of the United States UNITED STATES OF AMERICA, Petitioner, v. XAVIER ALVAREZ, Respondent. ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE NINTH CIRCUIT BRIEF OF PROFESSORS EUGENE VOLOKH AND JAMES WEINSTEIN AS AMICI CURIAE IN SUPPORT OF PETITIONER JAMES WEINSTEIN EUGENE VOLOKH ARIZONA STATE UNIVERSITY, Counsel of Record SANDRA DAY O’CONNOR UCLA SCHOOL OF LAW COLLEGE OF LAW 405 Hilgard Ave. Tempe, AZ 85287 Los Angeles, CA 90095 (480) 965-1305 (310) 206-3926 [email protected] [email protected] Counsel for Amici Curiae I QUESTION PRESENTED Section 704(b) of Title 18, United States Code, makes it a crime when anyone “falsely represents himself or herself, verbally or in writing, to have been awarded any decoration or medal authorized by Congress for the Armed Forces of the United States.” The question presented is whether 18 U.S.C. § 704(b) is facially invalid under the Free Speech Clause of the First Amendment. II TABLE OF CONTENTS Question Presented ....................................................... I Table of Contents ..........................................................II Table of Authorities .................................................... III Interest of Amici Curiae ...............................................1 Summary of Argument .................................................1 Argument .......................................................................2 I. State and Federal Laws Criminalize or Impose Civil Liability for Many Categories of Knowingly
    [Show full text]