Hume, Kant, and the Motivation for Morality Paul Guyer 1. Introduction

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Hume, Kant, and the Motivation for Morality Paul Guyer 1. Introduction Passion for Reason 1 Draft 3 Passion for Reason: Hume, Kant, and the Motivation for Morality Paul Guyer 1. Introduction Hume is famous for the assertion that “Reason is, and ought only to be the slave of the passions, and can never pretend to any other office than to serve and obey them,”1 meaning that our ends are set entirely by our feelings and that reason merely figures out the means to those ends. As a member of the “moral sense” tradition established by Shaftesbury and Hutcheson, Hume intends this to apply to moral as well as any other practical reasoning: morally permissible or mandatory ends are likewise supposed to be determined solely by feeling, with reason again confined to the role of figuring out the means to realize those ends. Thus, Hume says, “„tis impossible, that the distinction betwixt moral good and evil, can be made by reason: since that distinction has an influence upon our actions, of which reason alone is incapable. Reason and judgment may, indeed, be the mediate cause of an action, by prompting, or by directing a passion,” but they cannot “bestow those moral qualities on the actions, which are their” immediate or primary “causes.”2 Meanwhile, Kant is equally famous for the assertions that the ground of moral obligation “must not be sought in the nature of the human being or in the circumstances of the world in which he is placed, but a priori simply in concepts of pure reason,”3 from which it is supposed to follow that “an action from duty is to put aside entirely the influence of inclination and with it every object of the will; hence there is left for the will Passion for Reason 2 nothing that could determine it except objectively the law and subjectively pure respect for this practical law, and so the maxim of complying with such a law even if it infringes upon all my inclinations.”4 The contrast could hardly be clearer: for Hume, passion alone determines even our moral goals and the role of reason in the realization of these goals is strictly instrumental, while for Kant reason alone determines the principle of morality and our inclinations or feelings must play no role either in determining what is morally good or motivating us to try to realize that. At least in its first appearance, the “obscure feeling” of respect for the moral law that Kant recognizes is supposed to be “a feeling self-wrought by means of a rational concept and therefore specifically different from all feelings” of any other kind,5 and moreover seems to be a consequence and not a cause of the determination of our will by the moral law. But is the contrast between Hume and Kant as simple as I have just made it seem? I will argue that there is more common ground between the two philosophers than first appears, and suggest that it is only on the ground that is common between them that we could erect a plausible theory of our motivation to be moral. On the one hand, while Hume does stand by his theory that our ends are always determined by our passions, he also supposes that most of us are ultimately motivated by a passion for calm or tranquility, or a passion for freedom, at least in the negative sense of freedom from domination by importunate desires. Thus reason may be the slave of the passions, but we also have a fundamental passion to be reasonable. On the other hand, for Kant the ultimate aim of morality is also freedom, although his understanding of freedom is fuller than Hume‟s. Further, Kant‟s theory of moral motivation, at least at the empirical level, is that we cannot be moral without an original passion for freedom, although that passion must be redirected by reason from our own freedom to the freedom of all without loosing its force. Thus, both authors ground the content and the possibility of morality in our passion for freedom, although for Hume that is equivalent to a passion for reasonableness while for Kant our native passion for freedom must be tempered by reason, and once so tempered Kant himself would no longer call it a passion. Passion for Reason 3 2. Hume: Calm Passion and a Passion for Calm I begin with Hume. My exposition of Hume‟s account of the foundation of morality will proceed in three steps. First I will remind you of Hume‟s well-known argument for his thesis that reason is and ought only to be the slave of the passions. Next, I will remind you of his equally well-known claim that what appears to be more than merely instrumental reason in moral motivation is actually only calm rather than violent passion. But finally I will turn from Hume‟s Treatise of Human Nature to his restatement of his moral theory in his Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals to provide the evidence that he ultimately grounds morality in our underlying passion for calm or tranquility. Hume‟s argument that “moral distinctions” are “not deriv‟d from reason”6 is that reason just reports facts and neither has nor generates preferences of its own, thus is not motivating, while moral principles must be motivating and therefore depend on preferences that do not arise from reason. In summarizing the argument this way I am using the word “facts” broadly, but that fits with Hume‟s own broad usage of the term “reason” in his statement of this argument. For while in his argument in Book I of the Treatise and the first Enquiry that our causal beliefs are not founded on reason Hume had restricted the faculty of reason to the analysis of “relations of ideas” and inferred that all of our beliefs about existence or “matters of fact,”7 including our beliefs about the existence of causal relations, must be grounded on something other than reason, namely repeated experience, in his thesis about moral principles in Books II and III of the Treatise what was previously contrasted with reason, namely experience, is now lumped together with it. Thus Hume argues that neither “demonstration [n]or probability,” neither knowledge of “the abstract relations of our ideas, or those relations of objects of which experience only gives us information,”8 by themselves give us any reason to act. We may know that one sum is greater than another, that some object exists, or that some causal relation between objects or states of affairs holds, but none of that would give us any reason to act unless we also have a preference for a larger or smaller amount of something, for the presence or absence of Passion for Reason 4 something, or for some alteration that we could effect by exploiting the causal connections that obtain in the world. Taking action depends on an “aversion or propensity towards [some] object,” or on “the prospect of pain or pleasure” from it,” and such impulses arise “not from reason” but are only “directed by it,” because “these emotions extend themselves to the causes and effects” of objects “as they are pointed out to us by reason and experience,”9 where the latter is actually part of the former. Specifically, reason can tell us whether the objects of our emotions really exist and whether the means we have chosen for a “design‟d end” are causally sufficient to bring it about,10 but such knowledge has an influence on our action only to the extent that we have desires or aversions, emotions or passions, with regard to the current or possible states of the objects that may affect us and that we can affect. The passions for ends, however, are not themselves established by reason, and it is on that account that Hume says so dramatically that “„Tis not contrary to reason to prefer the destruction of the whole world to the scratching of my finger,” or conversely “to choose my total ruin, to prevent the least uneasiness of [a]...person otherwise unknown to me.”11 Hume then completes his argument in Book III of the Treatise by taking it for granted that “morals” are supposed to “have an influence on the actions and affections,” from which it follows that “they cannot be deriv‟d from reason...because reason alone, as we have already prov‟d, can never have any such influence.”12 Just as any action must originate from some emotion or passion arising independently of reason even if reason‟s knowledge of relations, existence, and causal connections may direct that impulse most effectively toward its object, so too moral actions, including moral appraisals, must originate in a “moral sense,” or in feelings of “pleasure or pain, which arises from characters and actions, of that peculiar kind, which makes us praise or condemn.” Such feelings of pleasure are not functionally different from those in “A good composition of music and a bottle of good wine,” although they are phenomenologically distinct from those and those are phenomenologically distinct from each other.13 Again, the broadly speaking factual knowledge provided by reason may direct our impulses to action that arise from our moral sentiments, but reason does not originate those impulses. Passion for Reason 5 Now all this is well-known, and I have belabored it only to remind you that the conception of reason on which Hume bases his argument about the non-rational foundation of moral principles, although broader than his conception of reason in Book I of the Treatise, is still quite specific. My next point is also well-known.
Recommended publications
  • HUMANISM Religious Practices
    HUMANISM Religious Practices . Required Daily Observances . Required Weekly Observances . Required Occasional Observances/Holy Days Religious Items . Personal Religious Items . Congregate Religious Items . Searches Requirements for Membership . Requirements (Includes Rites of Conversion) . Total Membership Medical Prohibitions Dietary Standards Burial Rituals . Death . Autopsies . Mourning Practices Sacred Writings Organizational Structure . Headquarters Location . Contact Office/Person History Theology 1 Religious Practices Required Daily Observance No required daily observances. Required Weekly Observance No required weekly observances, but many Humanists find fulfillment in congregating with other Humanists on a weekly basis (especially those who characterize themselves as Religious Humanists) or other regular basis for social and intellectual engagement, discussions, book talks, lectures, and similar activities. Required Occasional Observances No required occasional observances, but some Humanists (especially those who characterize themselves as Religious Humanists) celebrate life-cycle events with baby naming, coming of age, and marriage ceremonies as well as memorial services. Even though there are no required observances, there are several days throughout the calendar year that many Humanists consider holidays. They include (but are not limited to) the following: February 12. Darwin Day: This marks the birthday of Charles Darwin, whose research and findings in the field of biology, particularly his theory of evolution by natural selection, represent a breakthrough in human knowledge that Humanists celebrate. First Thursday in May. National Day of Reason: This day acknowledges the importance of reason, as opposed to blind faith, as the best method for determining valid conclusions. June 21 - Summer Solstice. This day is also known as World Humanist Day and is a celebration of the longest day of the year.
    [Show full text]
  • The Star of the Age of Reason. Voltaire 1694-1778
    Camilla Kolstad Danielsen The Star of The Age of Reason. Voltaire 1694-1778 During the 18th century, the French writers, philosophers and scientists were determined to improve the world through reason. Voltaire was the most famous of them all. No other writer was as frequently read and discussed. He was successful with his tragedies and poetry, he disseminated Newton’s philosophy to Europe and he was engaged in individual fates. For us, Voltaire is a symbolic figure, a socially engaged 2013 intellectual writer who fought for freedom of speech and other human rights. Such a Original title: Opplysningens stjerne. Voltaire notion is tinted by our modern viewpoint. But the important position Voltaire NORLA Selection acquired in his time was a result of the independent manner with which he handled his role as writer. FOREIGN RIGHTS This book provides an insight into Voltaire’s extensive and comprehensive authorship HAGEN AGENCY by Eirin Hagen within fiction, history, philosophy and various socially engaged essays. We meet Lindemans gate 3 D Voltaire as both controversial and moderate, radical and conservative, a contentious NO-0267 Oslo Tel: +47 22 46 52 54 man who won many battles, but far from all, and he did his best to fashion his star Mob: +47 93 41 10 56 status within his contemporaries and for future generations. [email protected] www.hagenagency.no English sample translation available Humanist Forlag 2014 231 Pages Praise: “This is a great book, scholastically solid and an exemplary dissemination of research. It is captivating and funny, and at the same time so convincing that I don’t think I have ever read anything better about Voltaire” Ellen Krefting, associate professor at the University of Oslo Camilla Kolstad Danielsen Camilla Kolstad Danielsenhas written articles on the French enlightenment and her PhD thesis about Voltaire’s philosophical narratives, potpourri, as a genre practice in Voltaire’s later philosophical works (2006).
    [Show full text]
  • Descartes' Influence in Shaping the Modern World-View
    R ené Descartes (1596-1650) is generally regarded as the “father of modern philosophy.” He stands as one of the most important figures in Western intellectual history. His work in mathematics and his writings on science proved to be foundational for further development in these fields. Our understanding of “scientific method” can be traced back to the work of Francis Bacon and to Descartes’ Discourse on Method. His groundbreaking approach to philosophy in his Meditations on First Philosophy determine the course of subsequent philosophy. The very problems with which much of modern philosophy has been primarily concerned arise only as a consequence of Descartes’thought. Descartes’ philosophy must be understood in the context of his times. The Medieval world was in the process of disintegration. The authoritarianism that had dominated the Medieval period was called into question by the rise of the Protestant revolt and advances in the development of science. Martin Luther’s emphasis that salvation was a matter of “faith” and not “works” undermined papal authority in asserting that each individual has a channel to God. The Copernican revolution undermined the authority of the Catholic Church in directly contradicting the established church doctrine of a geocentric universe. The rise of the sciences directly challenged the Church and seemed to put science and religion in opposition. A mathematician and scientist as well as a devout Catholic, Descartes was concerned primarily with establishing certain foundations for science and philosophy, and yet also with bridging the gap between the “new science” and religion. Descartes’ Influence in Shaping the Modern World-View 1) Descartes’ disbelief in authoritarianism: Descartes’ belief that all individuals possess the “natural light of reason,” the belief that each individual has the capacity for the discovery of truth, undermined Roman Catholic authoritarianism.
    [Show full text]
  • Shifting Liberal and Conservative Attitudes Using Moral Foundations
    PSPXXX10.1177/0146167214551152Personality and Social Psychology BulletinDay et al. 551152research-article2014 Article Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin Shifting Liberal and Conservative 1 –15 © 2014 by the Society for Personality and Social Psychology, Inc Attitudes Using Moral Reprints and permissions: sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav Foundations Theory DOI: 10.1177/0146167214551152 pspb.sagepub.com Martin V. Day1, Susan T. Fiske1, Emily L. Downing2, and Thomas E. Trail3 Abstract People’s social and political opinions are grounded in their moral concerns about right and wrong. We examine whether five moral foundations—harm, fairness, ingroup, authority, and purity—can influence political attitudes of liberals and conservatives across a variety of issues. Framing issues using moral foundations may change political attitudes in at least two possible ways: (a) Entrenching: Relevant moral foundations will strengthen existing political attitudes when framing pro-attitudinal issues (e.g., conservatives exposed to a free-market economic stance) and (b) Persuasion: Mere presence of relevant moral foundations may also alter political attitudes in counter-attitudinal directions (e.g., conservatives exposed to an economic regulation stance). Studies 1 and 2 support the entrenching hypothesis. Relevant moral foundation-based frames bolstered political attitudes for conservatives (Study 1) and liberals (Study 2). Only Study 2 partially supports the persuasion hypothesis. Conservative-relevant moral frames of liberal issues increased conservatives’ liberal attitudes. Keywords morality, moral foundations, ideology, attitudes, politics Received July 1, 2013; revision accepted August 19, 2014 Our daily lives are steeped in political content, including 2012). Understanding the effectiveness of morally based many attempts to alter our attitudes. These efforts stem from framing may be consequential not only for politics but also a variety of sources, such as political campaigns, presidential for better understanding of everyday shifts in other opinions.
    [Show full text]
  • PRAGMATISM and ITS IMPLICATIONS: Pragmatism Is A
    PRAGMATISM AND ITS IMPLICATIONS: Pragmatism is a philosophy that has had its chief development in the United States, and it bears many of the characteristics of life on the American continent.. It is connected chiefly with the names of William James (1842-1910) and John Dewey. It has appeared under various names, the most prominent being pragmatism, instrumentalism, and experimentalism. While it has had its main development in America, similar ideas have been set forth in England by Arthur Balfour and by F. C. S. Schiller, and in Germany by Hans Vaihingen. WHAT PRAGMATISM IS Pragmatism is an attitude, a method, and a philosophy which places emphasis upon the practical and the useful or upon that which has satisfactory consequences. The term pragmatism comes from a Greek word pragma, meaning "a thing done," a fact, that which is practical or matter-of-fact. Pragmatism uses the practical consequences of ideas and beliefs as a standard for determining their value and truth. William James defined pragmatism as "the attitude of looking away from first things, principles, 'categories,' supposed necessities; and of looking towards last things, fruits, consequences, facts." Pragmatism places greater emphasis upon method and attitude than upon a system of philosophical doctrine. It is the method of experimental inquiry carried into all realms of human experience. Pragmatism is the modern scientific method taken as the basis of a philosophy. Its affinity is with the biological and social sciences, however, rather than with the mathematical and physical sciences. The pragmatists are critical of the systems of philosophy as set forth in the past.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Hutcheson and Kant: Moral Sense and Moral Feeling Published In
    1 Hutcheson and Kant: Moral Sense and Moral Feeling Michael Walschots Published in Kant and the Scottish Enlightenment. Edited by Elizabeth Robinson and Chris W. Surprenant. London: Routledge, 2017. pg. 36 – 54. The eighteenth century is a rich and fascinating period in the history of Germany philosophy for a variety of reasons. Not least among these is the fact that German authors of the period somewhat extensively engaged with the writings of those in other European countries and beyond. The extent to which German philosophers engaged with eighteenth century British philosophy is an excellent example. Describing the reception of British philosophy in eighteenth century Germany, Manfred Kuehn writes that The works of Locke, Shaftsbury, Hutcheson, Hume, Smith, Ferguson, and almost every other British philosopher of note were full of problems that needed solutions and observations that needed to be explained, if German philosophy of the traditional sort was to succeed. (Kuehn 2001, 183-4) Although many German philosophers of the period could read English, the wide reception of these British authors was made possible in large part by the, in some cases rapid, translation of their texts into German. This is certainly true of the Scottish philosopher who will be the focus of this paper: Francis Hutcheson (1694-1747). A translation of Hutcheson’s posthumous System of Moral Philosophy, first published in 1755, was published just one year later in 1756. Translations of Hutcheson’s An Essay on the Nature and Conduct of the Passions (1728) and An Inquiry into the Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue (1725) followed somewhat soon thereafter, appearing in 1760 and 1762 respectively.
    [Show full text]
  • Human Beings and the Moral Law: Moral Precariousness in Kant's Ethical Philosophy
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations 2014 Human Beings and the Moral Law: Moral Precariousness in Kant's Ethical Philosophy Bradley Taylor University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Taylor, Bradley, "Human Beings and the Moral Law: Moral Precariousness in Kant's Ethical Philosophy" (2014). Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations. 1468. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/1468 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/1468 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Human Beings and the Moral Law: Moral Precariousness in Kant's Ethical Philosophy Abstract ABSTRACT HUMAN BEINGS AND THE MORAL LAW: MORAL PRECARIOUSNESS IN KANT'S ETHICAL PHILOSOPHY Bradley M. Taylor Dr. Paul Guyer This dissertation is an examination of human moral precariousness in Kant's ethics. Human beings are in a state of moral precariousness insofar as they are ever-capable of transgressing the moral law and are often uncertain of the moral worth of their actions. Put another way, in this dissertation I argue that the basic relationship between human beings and the moral law, in Kant's moral philosophy, is, most fundamentally, one of tenuousness and vacillation. This relation is the fundamental characteristic of the human moral condition because such a relation is built into Kant's account of human moral agency. We have a tenuous relation to the moral law because we always have at least the possibility of conflict between our desire for happiness (i.e. the satisfaction of our inclinations) and the requirements of the moral law.
    [Show full text]
  • Mature Kantians Mika Lavaque-Manty [email protected]
    Mature Kantians Mika LaVaque-Manty [email protected] Department of Political Science University of Michigan Philip Otto Runge, Hülsenbeck Children, 1805–6. © ARTstor. Prepared for delivery at the 2004 Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association, September 2 – September 5, 2004. © American Political Science Association. Mature Kantians i INTRODUCTION: THE AUTONOMY PROBLEM One of the many problems facing Enlightenment thinkers was the question of how to reconcile their claim that all humans have equal dignity by virtue of their autonomous agency with the fact that many people neither enjoyed the respect their dignity warranted nor acted in ways that would have suggested they were meaningfully autonomous.1 If the 18th century was the age of the Enlightenment, many people didn’t act their age. Part of the problem was political in the institutional sense: absolutism, feudal vestiges and religious authoritarianism made it difficult, even impossible, for people to be autonomous. But these didn’t account for all the problems, and as Kant suggested, another part had to with ordinary people themselves: the people’s “immaturity” was also “self-incurred.” This was a real pickle, both theoretically and practically: If another person’s autonomous agency is your goal, you had better be careful about what and how much you do for her. There is a real tension, if not an outright conflict, between paternalism and respect for autonomy. There is also a risk of elitism in concerning yourself with others’ autonomy. In the absence of a shared summum bonum — and I take it that part of what modernity means is the absence of a shared summum bonum — the apparent end of a person’s action doesn’t always tell you whether she chose the action or the end.
    [Show full text]
  • From Zarathustra to the Wisdom of Salomon Wolfgang Leidhold, Cologne [EVS: Panel 2 — Religious Experience : Eric Voegelin and Beyond]
    DRAFT - Seattle 2011 The Noetic Turn: From Zarathustra to the Wisdom of Salomon Wolfgang Leidhold, Cologne [EVS: Panel 2 — Religious Experience : Eric Voegelin and Beyond] Summary: Taking Eric Voegelin‘s theory of experience as a point of departure, this essay examines more closely the logic of experience (and of religious experience in particular). Voegelin‘s main thesis is that, since all ideas and concepts are based on experience, there is no „history of ideas― as an isolated process that is intelligible in itself but ideas must be studied and can only be understood if based on the founding experiences as their intelligible field. In an attempt to go beyond Voegelin‘s achievements, the paper sets ou by analyzing the structure of experience more closely. The results are applied to historic case-studies, starting with the Gathas of Zarathustra; neolithic myth and paleolithic symbolism are studied next; from here the analysis proceeds to Hindu and Daoist traditions, finally to some Old and New Testament sources. In the end, the findings are summarized as a new theory: the structure of experience varies not only regarding compactness and differentiation; but the experiental field itself is changing in terms of horizon, dimensions, and structure. As a consequence, experience and its symbolization are equivalent only if the structure is similar. The difference between „cultures― does not only regard the varying symbolizations of basically equivalent experiences, they are based on different modes of experience. Therefore we have to go one step beyond Eric Voegelin‘s achievements and study the history of experience. 1. Star Gazer One night as a young boy about twelve years of age I sat at home in the kitchen and looked out of the window at the nocturnal sky.
    [Show full text]
  • The Terrible, Horrible, No Good, Very Bad Truth About Morality and What to Do About It, Doctoral Dissertation of Joshua D
    9/03 Note to readers of The Terrible, Horrible, No Good, Very Bad Truth about Morality and What to Do About it, Doctoral Dissertation of Joshua D. Greene in the Department of Philosophy, Princeton University, June 2002. You are welcome to read this work, pass it on to others, and cite it. I only ask that if you pass on this work to someone else that it be passed on (1) in its entirety, (2) without modification, and (3) along with this note. I consider this a work in progress. It is currently under review in its present form at an academic press. I intend to revise and expand it substantially before publishing it as a book, so much so that the book and the dissertation will probably best be considered separate works. Comments are welcome. You can contact me by email ([email protected]) or by regular mail: Joshua Greene Department of Psychology Princeton University Princeton, NJ 08544 jdg THE TERRIBLE, HORRIBLE, NO GOOD, VERY BAD TRUTH ABOUT MORALITY AND WHAT TO DO ABOUT IT Joshua David Greene A DISSERTATION PRESENTED TO THE FACULTY OF PRINCETON UNIVERSITY IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY RECOMMENDED FOR ACCEPTANCE BY THE DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY NOVEMBER 2002 © Copyright by Joshua David Greene, 2002. All rights reserved. ii Abstract In this essay I argue that ordinary moral thought and language is, while very natural, highly counterproductive and that as a result we would be wise to change the way we think and talk about moral matters. First, I argue on metaphysical grounds against moral realism, the view according to which there are first order moral truths.
    [Show full text]
  • Research in Practical Philosophy
    Research in Practical Philosophy in Sweden: 1998 - 2008, appendix to Report of the International Panel for the Evaluationof Swedish Research in Philosophy to the Swedish Research Council Rabinowicz, Wlodek 2009 Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): Rabinowicz, W. (2009). Research in Practical Philosophy in Sweden: 1998 - 2008, appendix to Report of the International Panel for the Evaluationof Swedish Research in Philosophy to the Swedish Research Council. Swedish Research Council. Total number of authors: 1 General rights Unless other specific re-use rights are stated the following general rights apply: Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal Read more about Creative commons licenses: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/ Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. LUND UNIVERSITY PO Box 117 221 00 Lund +46 46-222 00 00 Wlodek Rabinowicz Research in Practical Philosophy in Sweden: 1998-2008 In this short summary, which is aimed to give a rough picture of the main lines of research in practical philosophy in Sweden during the last decade, I have decided to organize the presentation by universities rather than by particular research subjects.
    [Show full text]
  • The Future of Practical Philosophy
    The Future of Practical Philosophy James Stacey Taylor James Stacey Taylor is an Assistant Professor of philosophy at Louisiana State University, USA. He has published numerous articles on the theory of autonomy, ethics, and applied ethics. He is the editor of Personal Autonomy: New essays (Cambridge University Press, 2005), and the author of Stakes and Kidneys: Why markets in human body parts are morally imperative (Ashgate Press, 2005). ABSTRACT Over the last two decades the practice of applied philosophy has undergone resurgence. It is now common for philosophers to sit on ethics committees in hospitals, or to provide ethical advice to businesses, and many universities and colleges now offer courses in practical philosophy. Despite this, practical philosophy is subject to increasing criticism, with persons charging that (1) it is philosophically shallow, and (2) it has little to offer persons grappling with concrete ethical problems, either because (a) its techniques or too removed from such problems, or (b) because ethical theory is too abstract. In this paper I develop responses to these criticisms, and offer suggestions as to how practical philosophy should be developed. Over the last two decades the practice of applied philosophy has undergone resurgence. It is now common for philosophers to sit on ethics committees in hospitals, or to provide ethical advice to businesses. Many universities and colleges now offer courses in practical philosophy, ranging from courses in bioethics and business ethics to more innovative courses, such as philosophy as conversation. Such courses frequently prove popular. The popularity of practical philosophy is reflected in the demand for people who can teach practical philosophy (especially applied ethics), with this section of the academic job market in philosophy currently being especially strong.1 And it is not only the practice and teaching of practical philosophy that is currently flourishing.
    [Show full text]