Charles S. Peirce's Philosophy of Signs

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Charles S. Peirce's Philosophy of Signs Cover Page i Charles S. Peirce’s Philosophy of Signs Page ii Advances in Semiotics Thomas A. Sebeok, General Editor Page iii Charles S. Peirce’s Philosophy of Signs ESSAYS IN COMPARATIVE SEMIOTICS Gérard Deledalle Indiana University Press BLOOMINGTON AND INDIANAPOLIS Page iv This book is a publication of Indiana University Press 601 North Morton Street Bloomington, IN 47404­3797 USA HTTP://WWW.INDIANA.EDU/~IUPRESS Telephone orders 800­842­6796 Fax orders 812­855­7931 Orders by e­mail [email protected] © 2000 by Gérard Deledalle All rights reserved No part of this book may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying and recording, or by any information storage and retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publisher. The Association of American University Presses’ Resolution on Permissions constitutes the only exception to this prohibition. The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of American National Standard for Information Sciences—Permanence of Paper for Printed Library Materials, ANSI Z39.48­1984. MANUFACTURED IN THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA Library of Congress Cataloging­in­Publication Data Deledalle, Gérard. Charles S. Peirce’s philosophy of signs : essays in comparative semiotics / Gérard Deledalle. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0­253­33736­4 (hardcover : alk. paper) 1. Peirce, Charles S. (Charles Sanders), 1839–1914. 2. Semiotics. I. Title: Charles Sanders Peirce’s philosophy of signs. II. Title. B945.P44 D434 2000 121′.68—dc21 00­024320 1 2 3 4 5 05 04 03 02 01 00 Page v this page intentionally left blank Page vi Contents INTRODUCTION Peirce Compared: Directions for Use vii Part One Semeiotic as Philosophy 1 1. Peirce's New Philosophical Paradigms 3 2. Peirce's Philosophy of Semeiotic 14 3. Peirce's First Pragmatic Papers (1877–1878): THE FRENCH VERSION AND THE PARIS COMMUNE 23 Part Two Semeiotic as Semiotics 35 4. Sign: Semiosis and Representamen 37 5. Sign: The Concept and Its Use 54 Part Three Comparative Semiotics 65 6. Semiotics and Logic: A Reply to Jerzy Pelc 67 7. Semeiotic and Greek Logic: Pierce and Philodemus 78 Semeiotic and Significs: Peirce and Lady Welby 87 9. Semeiotic and Semiology: Peirce and Saussure 100 10. Semeiotic and Semiotics: Peirce and Morris 114 11. Semeiotic and Linguistics: Peirce and Jakobson 120 12. Semeiotic and Communication—Peirce and McLuhan: MEDIA BETWEEN BALNIBARBI AND PLATO'S CAVE 127 13. Semeiotic and Epistemology: Peirce, Frege, and Wittgenstein 137 Part Four Comparative Metaphysics 145 14. Gnoseology—Perceiving and Knowing: 147 15. Ontology—Transcendentals of or without Being: PEIRCE VERSUS ARISTOTLE AND THOMAS AQUINAS 155 16. Cosmology—Chaos and Chance within Order and Continuity: PEIRCE BETWEEN PLATO AND DARWIN 162 17. Theology—The Reality of God: PEIRCE'S TRIUNE GOD AND THE CHURCH'S TRINITY 181 Conclusion—Peirce: A LATERAL VIEW 181 BIBLIOGRAPHY 191 INDEX 197 Page vii INTRODUCTION Peirce Compared: Directions for Use Although the present book is a collection of essays written over fifty years, either in French or in English, according to circumstances, my way of approaching Peirce has always followed the same line which allows me to call them Essays in Comparative Semiotics. As to the title, Charles S. Peirce’s Philosophy of Signs, I am not responsible for the fact that Peirce’s theory of signs is philosophical, rather than “ethnological” like that of Claude Lévy­Strauss, or “linguistic” like that of Roman Jakobson. That is why not only philosophy in general, including ideology, but metaphysics in particular, play a part in Peirce’s semiotics, and consequently in my book. In spite of the fact that my papers were written to introduce Peirce to a French public, and perhaps thanks to it, my book has a unity of method which explains itself. First, writing for French readers, I could not refer them to English or American authors whom they were not supposed to know. I could resort only to French authors or French translations of English­speaking authors, dealing with the same semiotic subject matter. Unfortunately, or rather fortunately, their approach was so different that I could stress only the differences and not the resemblances. That is why my “comparative’’ method is differential. Peirce stands alone of his kind. Second, I had to compare Peirce, not only to French authors or foreign authors translated into French, but to himself both chronologically and contextually. As a reader of Peirce myself, I wanted to be fair and read Peirce’s writings chronologically. One cannot reject an argument, developed, let us say in 1906, by quoting a text from 1867 or 1877–1878. Between 1867, when Peirce proposed his new list of categories, or 1877–1878 when he proposed his “pragmatic maxim,” and 1904–1911 when he was corresponding with Lady Welby, he changed his mind. The new logic of relatives which he invented around 1875 led him to abandon the Western “dualistic” way of thinking as promoted from Aristotle to Kant, for a “triadic” and “anti­inductive” way of reasoning which experimental method and evolutive sciences first practiced. That is why I sometimes, when necessary, give the date of my quotations from Peirce. To be fair, one has also to read an author in context. The vocabulary of a philosopher is not the same as that of a mathematician or a biologist. When a philosopher is also a mathematical logician and pragmatist, as was the case with Peirce, one has to specify the public to which a given text (already dated) is addressed. For instance, Peirce uses the concept of “degenerate” when he wants to Page viii be understood by mathematicians or logicians. When he addresses philosophers, he uses other concepts, such as the three phenomenological or rather phaneroscopical categories. In the first instance, he would say that a “proposition” is a degenerate case of “argument” (‘‘argument,” in Peirce’s sense, i.e., any ordered system). In the other instance, he would say that a Third is “vague and empty,” a mere “structure” and that a Second is a single, singular, and unique replica of a Third, the best example being the relation between “type” and “token.” But it would be nonsense to speak here in terms of “degeneracy,” because, as a First, the type is not a “genuine” category, but an “accretive” sign. Let us give another more simple and general case. In a paper published in the Times Literary Supplement on August 23, 1985, Jonathan Cohen insists on what he thinks to be a contradiction in what he calls Peircean “anti­realism”: The Peircean anti­realist “assumes that scientific method […] is sufficient to guarantee the convergence” between scientific consensus and truth, because “he takes such convergence to be an a priori philosophical truth.” “So though the Peircean is a fallibilist in relation to science itself, he is an infallibilist in relation to methodology” (Cohen 1985: 929). Jonathan Cohen is mistaken here because his conception of truth is out of context. “Inquiry” has nothing to do with “truth” and certainly not with “an a priori philosophical truth.” According to Peirce, “inquiry” can give birth only to “warranted assertibility,” to use the expression coined by John Dewey and quoted by Cohen. The same mistake was made by the analytic philosophers when they were orthodox and by the renegades of the next generation, whether they were “realists” or “neo­pragmatists.” Of course, the reader may be tempted to unify Peirce’s thought and may be successful, provided the two conditions of chronology and contextualization are respected. For instance, chronologically and contextually, a concept may have been dealt with by Peirce at one period and in one context. For example, consider the concept of “object” in his correspondence with Lady Welby between 1904 and 1911, and in the context of semiotics. The distinction between the concept of immediate object and the concept of dynamic object applies only to the idea of “semiosis.” The immediate object (Oi) is the name of the object within a given semiosis, the dynamic object (Od) is the name of the same object without the same semiosis. In other words, dynamic object (Od) and immediate object (Oi) can be separated only analytically. The object is existentially one and the same, only, like a coin, with a reverse (Od) and an obverse (Oi). While the nature of Oi is easy to define because it is psychologically apprehended, the nature of Od cannot be with certainty semiotically described. Is it an “essence” or the totality of immediate objects solidified in a transparent ideal object produced by all the interpretants as habits in a given social group for a given individual of this group? Generalization is thus in this case and other similar cases, according to Peirce’s own ethics of terminology, to be limited to their respective proper time and context. But when one wants to systematize a concept which Peirce discussed several times at different periods and in different contexts, it is more risky, because two Page ix cases have to be distinguished: the meaning of the concept may be either changed or enlarged. When the object of the concept is changed, things are relatively easy. It is the case of the new conception of inference we mentioned earlier. The “anti­inductive” attitude that Peirce adopted at the turn of the century rested on the fact that no theory of change could prove that singular, concrete facts by themselves give birth to “universals” or rather “generals” to use Peirce’s term. The abductive process that Peirce advanced instead was that facts can only suggest hypotheses which have to be experimentally tested. In consequence, if this is acknowledged, facts and ideas cannot be thought as opposed as Mill’s empiricism is opposed to Descartes’s idealism.
Recommended publications
  • The Trichotomy of Processes: a Philosophical Basis for Information Systems
    Association for Information Systems AIS Electronic Library (AISeL) Americas Conference on Information Systems AMCIS 2003 Proceedings (AMCIS) December 2003 The rT ichotomy of Processes: A Philosophical Basis for Information Systems George Widmeyer University of Michigan Follow this and additional works at: http://aisel.aisnet.org/amcis2003 Recommended Citation Widmeyer, George, "The rT ichotomy of Processes: A Philosophical Basis for Information Systems" (2003). AMCIS 2003 Proceedings. 362. http://aisel.aisnet.org/amcis2003/362 This material is brought to you by the Americas Conference on Information Systems (AMCIS) at AIS Electronic Library (AISeL). It has been accepted for inclusion in AMCIS 2003 Proceedings by an authorized administrator of AIS Electronic Library (AISeL). For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE TRICHOTOMY OF PROCESSES: A PHILOSOPHICAL BASIS FOR INFORMATION SYSTEMS George R. Widmeyer University of Michigan [email protected] Abstract The principle of trichotomy from the American philosopher Charles S. Peirce can be used to categorize processes into the triad of transactional, informational, and relational. The usefulness of these categories is explicated by a comparison with structuration theory and control theory, and elaborated with a consideration of democracy in a knowledge economy. These three example applications of the process triad show the generality of the conceptual categories and provide a natural way of bringing ideas from social and ethical theories into information systems design. Modeling the world and understanding business applications through the use of the Trichotomy of Processes should facilitate the development of more valuable information systems. Keywords: Business processes, information systems theory, conceptual modeling, ontology, Peirce, open society Introduction Various frameworks for understanding the business processes of an organization have been proposed.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant on Recognizing Our Duties As God's Commands
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by Asbury Theological Seminary Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 17 Issue 4 Article 3 10-1-2000 Kant on Recognizing our Duties as God's Commands John Hare Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Hare, John (2000) "Kant on Recognizing our Duties as God's Commands," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 17 : Iss. 4 , Article 3. Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol17/iss4/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. KANT ON RECOGNIZING OUR DUTIES AS GOD'S COMMANDS John E. Hare Kant both says that we should recognize our duties as God's commands, and objects to the theological version of heteronomy, 'which derives morality from a divine and supremely perfect will'. In this paper I discuss how these two views fit together, and in the process I develop a notion of autonomous submission to divine moral authority. I oppose the 'constitutive' view of autonomy proposed by J. B. Schneewind and Christine Korsgaard. I locate Kant's objection to theological heteronomy against the background of Crusius's divine command theory, and I compare Kant's views about divine authority and human political authority. 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Science and Philosophy of Chemistry
    Philosophy of Science and Philosophy of Chemistry Jaap van Brakel Abstract: In this paper I assess the relation between philosophy of chemistry and (general) philosophy of science, focusing on those themes in the philoso- phy of chemistry that may bring about major revisions or extensions of cur- rent philosophy of science. Three themes can claim to make a unique contri- bution to philosophy of science: first, the variety of materials in the (natural and artificial) world; second, extending the world by making new stuff; and, third, specific features of the relations between chemistry and physics. Keywords : philosophy of science, philosophy of chemistry, interdiscourse relations, making stuff, variety of substances . 1. Introduction Chemistry is unique and distinguishes itself from all other sciences, with respect to three broad issues: • A (variety of) stuff perspective, requiring conceptual analysis of the notion of stuff or material (Sections 4 and 5). • A making stuff perspective: the transformation of stuff by chemical reaction or phase transition (Section 6). • The pivotal role of the relations between chemistry and physics in connection with the question how everything fits together (Section 7). All themes in the philosophy of chemistry can be classified in one of these three clusters or make contributions to general philosophy of science that, as yet , are not particularly different from similar contributions from other sci- ences (Section 3). I do not exclude the possibility of there being more than three clusters of philosophical issues unique to philosophy of chemistry, but I am not aware of any as yet. Moreover, highlighting the issues discussed in Sections 5-7 does not mean that issues reviewed in Section 3 are less im- portant in revising the philosophy of science.
    [Show full text]
  • Encoding/Decoding, the Transmission Model and a Court of Law
    Final Revision: Title: Encoding/Decoding, the Transmission Model and a Court of Law Keyan G. Tomaselli Abstract: Stuart Hall’s encoding/decoding model is discussed in terms of CS Peirce’s theory of the interpreter and interpretant. This historical semiotic window frames an example to which the Hall model was applied in South Africa to oppose a military dirty tricks campaign that involved a Supreme Court case brought against the Minister of Defence by the End Conscription Campaign (ECC) requiring him to cease his disinformation against the ECC. The Minister’s own expert had proposed a transmission model of communication that was defeated by the Peirce-Hall combination. The author argues that the model can be massively strengthened when combined with Peirceian semiotics. Keywords: Stuart Hall, encoding/decoding, CS Peirce, Phaneroscopy, semiotics, reception Media-society relations are best studied within the broader conceptual environment facilitated by the circuit of culture model (Du Gay et al., 1997) that mimics Karl Marx’s circle of capitalist production, distribution and exchange. The model implicitly incorporated Stuart Hall’s (1981) ground-breaking encoding-decoding relationship. My argument will be that Charles Sanders Peirce’s (Hartshorne and Weiss, 1931-5) idea of the ‘interpretant’ – the idea to which the sign gives rise - was a crucial, if unspoken, progenitor of Hall’s model. Working at the same time as Hall, Umberto Eco (1972) had proposed “aberrant decoding” on which Hall must have drawn, as his chapter refers to a semiological article on encoding. The early Stencilled Occasional Paper and Hutchinson book series’ that mapped out the early Birmingham University Centre for Contemporary Cultural Studies (CCCS) project under Stuart Hall’s leadership identified the following semiological/semiotic sources also: Roland Barthes, Jonathan Culler and V.I.
    [Show full text]
  • Hypertext Semiotics in the Commercialized Internet
    Hypertext Semiotics in the Commercialized Internet Moritz Neumüller Wien, Oktober 2001 DOKTORAT DER SOZIAL- UND WIRTSCHAFTSWISSENSCHAFTEN 1. Beurteiler: Univ. Prof. Dipl.-Ing. Dr. Wolfgang Panny, Institut für Informationsver- arbeitung und Informationswirtschaft der Wirtschaftsuniversität Wien, Abteilung für Angewandte Informatik. 2. Beurteiler: Univ. Prof. Dr. Herbert Hrachovec, Institut für Philosophie der Universität Wien. Betreuer: Gastprofessor Univ. Doz. Dipl.-Ing. Dr. Veith Risak Eingereicht am: Hypertext Semiotics in the Commercialized Internet Dissertation zur Erlangung des akademischen Grades eines Doktors der Sozial- und Wirtschaftswissenschaften an der Wirtschaftsuniversität Wien eingereicht bei 1. Beurteiler: Univ. Prof. Dr. Wolfgang Panny, Institut für Informationsverarbeitung und Informationswirtschaft der Wirtschaftsuniversität Wien, Abteilung für Angewandte Informatik 2. Beurteiler: Univ. Prof. Dr. Herbert Hrachovec, Institut für Philosophie der Universität Wien Betreuer: Gastprofessor Univ. Doz. Dipl.-Ing. Dr. Veith Risak Fachgebiet: Informationswirtschaft von MMag. Moritz Neumüller Wien, im Oktober 2001 Ich versichere: 1. daß ich die Dissertation selbständig verfaßt, andere als die angegebenen Quellen und Hilfsmittel nicht benutzt und mich auch sonst keiner unerlaubten Hilfe bedient habe. 2. daß ich diese Dissertation bisher weder im In- noch im Ausland (einer Beurteilerin / einem Beurteiler zur Begutachtung) in irgendeiner Form als Prüfungsarbeit vorgelegt habe. 3. daß dieses Exemplar mit der beurteilten Arbeit überein
    [Show full text]
  • A Diagrammatic Approach to Peirce's Classifications of Signs
    A diagrammatic approach to Peirce’s classifications of signs1 Priscila Farias Graduate Program in Design (SENAC-SP & UFPE) [email protected] João Queiroz Graduate Studies Program on History, Philosophy, and Science Teaching (UFBA/UEFS) Dept. of Computer Engineering and Industrial Automation (DCA/FEEC/UNICAMP) [email protected] © This paper is not for reproduction without permission of the author(s). ABSTRACT Starting from an analysis of two diagrams for 10 classes of signs designed by Peirce in 1903 and 1908 (CP 2.264 and 8.376), this paper sets forth the basis for a diagrammatic understanding of all kinds of classifications based on his triadic model of a sign. Our main argument is that it is possible to observe a common pattern in the arrangement of Peirce’s diagrams of 3-trichotomic classes, and that this pattern should be extended for the design of diagrams for any n-trichotomic classification of signs. Once this is done, it is possible to diagrammatically compare the conflicting claims done by Peircean scholars re- garding the divisions of signs into 28, and specially into 66 classes. We believe that the most important aspect of this research is the proposal of a consolidated tool for the analysis of any kind of sign structure within the context of Peirce’s classifications of signs. Keywords: Peircean semiotics, classifications of signs, diagrammatic reasoning. 1. PEIRCE’S DIAGRAMS FOR 10 CLASSES OF SIGNS In a draft of a letter to Lady Welby composed by the end of December 1908 (dated 24-28 December, L463:132-146, CP 8.342-76, EP2:483-491; we will be referring to this diagram 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Download/ Nwp File/2013/Notes on a Working Hypothesis.Pdf?X-R=Pcfile D
    Psychosemiotics: communication as psychological action Marko Mili Doctor of Philosophy (Psychology) University of Western Sydney November 2008 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I would like to express my gratitude to my wife Juliana Payne for her patience, accessibility for debate on all issues, practical assistance, and help in avoiding clichés like the plague. My parents Petar and Nediljka Mili shared their enthusiasm for learning and balanced their encouragement with flexibility about the direction that their influence took. My sister, Angela Mili, provided moral and practical support. To my extended family—Ante, Maria, Mirko, Lina, Kristina, Anthony, and Nikolas Mili; and Steve and Veronica Harwood—thank you for your support for this project. Thanks to Megan McDonald for helpful grammatical-stylistic suggestions and to Domagoj Veli, who has been an enthusiastic supporter of this project from the beginning. Professor Philip Bell, Professor Theo van Leeuwen, Dr Scott Mann and Dr Phillip Staines provided me with valuable opportunities to assist in teaching their courses in mass media, semiotics, social theory and the philosophy of language. This experience has significantly enhanced the present work. My supervisor, Dr Agnes Petocz, consistently provided detailed and incisive feedback throughout the conception and execution of this work. Her vision of a richer science of psychology has been inspirational for me. As co-supervisor, Professor Philip Bell has been an exemplary mentor and model for post- disciplinary research. ii STATEMENT OF AUTHENTICATION The work presented in this thesis is, to the best of my knowledge and belief, original except as acknowledged in the text. I hereby declare that I have not submitted this material, either in whole or in part, for a degree at this or any other institution.
    [Show full text]
  • Picasso's Cubism: Politics And/Or Semiosis
    MIT 4.602, Modern Art and Mass Culture (HASS-D+CI) Spring 2012 Professor Caroline A. Jones Notes History, Theory and Criticism Section. Department of Architecture Lecture 10 SERIALISM & SEMIOSIS: Lecture 10: Picasso's Cubism: Politics and/or Semiosis 1990: Picasso's primitivism is part of a cultural discourse in which "Africa" conveyed widely accepted meanings that cannot be extricated from allusions to its art and people. - Patricia Leighton, 'The White Peril and I 'art m?gre ... " 1981 /'98: The extraordinary contribution of collage is that it is the first instance within the pictorial arts of anything like a systematic exploration of the conditions of representability entailed by the sign. - Rosalind Krauss, "In the Name of Picasso" I. Picasso's escape via Paris: from paternal academy, and provincialism A. The international "Youth Style" (Jugendstil, Joven Tut, Arte Joven magazines) B. Impressionist modes and motives, Barcelona -> Paris C. "Blue period" 1) the depressed fliineur (harlequin) 2) a "Moorish" Spaniard in France II. Picasso's escape from Paris: The Demoiselles d' A vignon A. Picasso's self-described "exorcism" - of what? B. The way modem abstraction works 1) African sculpture as "raisonnable ,. (conceptual) 2) towards a system of visual signs (away from representing towards signifying) C. Colonialist critique through performing the primitive (how different from Gauguin?) III. Cubism- hermetic language, or popular culture? A. "Braque, c 'est ma femme" - the codes of a private language 1) Georges Braque - wit, conceptualism, pattern, (French) fancypaint traditions 2) Pablo Picasso - weight, sculptural concerns, "modeling," oscillations between depth! surface B. The force of caricature in the portraits C.
    [Show full text]
  • Marketing Semiotics
    Marketing Semiotics Professor Christian Pinson Semiosis, i.e. the process by which things and events come to be recognized as signs, is of particular relevance to marketing scholars and practitioners. The term marketing encompasses those activities involved in identifying the needs and wants of target markets and delivering the desired satisfactions more effectively and efficiently than competitors. Whereas early definitions of marketing focused on the performance of business activities that direct the flow of goods and services from producer to consumer or user, modern definitions stress that marketing activities involve interaction between seller and buyer and not a one- way flow from producer to consumer. As a consequence, the majority of marketers now view marketing in terms of exchange relationships. These relationships entail physical, financial, psychological and social meanings. The broad objective of the semiotics of marketing is to make explicit the conditions under which these meanings are produced and apprehended. Although semioticians have been actively working in the field of marketing since the 1960s, it is only recently that semiotic concepts and approaches have received international attention and recognition (for an overview, see Larsen et al. 1991, Mick, 1986, 1997 Umiker- Sebeok, 1988, Pinson, 1988). Diffusion of semiotic research in marketing has been made difficult by cultural and linguistic barriers as well as by divergence of thought. Whereas Anglo-Saxon researchers base their conceptual framework on Charles Pierce's ideas, Continental scholars tend to refer to the sign theory in Ferdinand de Saussure and to its interpretation by Hjelmslev. 1. The symbolic nature of consumption. Consumer researchers and critics of marketing have long recognized the symbolic nature of consumption and the importance of studying the meanings attached by consumers to the various linguistic and non-linguistic signs available to them in the marketplace.
    [Show full text]
  • The Commutation Test and Chris Bacon's Score for Source Code As
    The Commutation Test and Chris Bacon’s Score for Source Code as a Framework for Film Music Pedagogy Aaron Ziegel, Towson University he cinema, whether experienced at the neighborhood multiplex or streamed at home, is arguably the medium through which today’s col- lege-age Americans are most likely to encounter newly composed sym- Tphonic music. Given the ubiquity of the film-viewing experience, students are often eager to learn the tools and methodologies that can equip them to criti- cally assess and more fully comprehend the function of music in movies. The filmSource Code (2011), directed by Duncan Jones and scored by Chris Bacon, provides a particularly effective starting point through which this process can begin.1 This article will discuss the pedagogical potential found in the film’s main titles and the impact of applying a commutation test to this sequence. Although here I address one specific example, the methodology of the commu- tation test is easily adaptable to other circumstances, as the theoretical foun- dation will make clear. While variations on the commutation test are a regular occurrence in many film music classrooms, this essay aims to present an intro- ductory primer that may be of use to instructors interested in an entry point for incorporating film music studies into their teaching. With that in mind, the appendix presents one suggestion for how to create film clips for classroom use. The value of this classroom activity extends beyond providing students with an engaging and memorable learning experience. By situating this analysis I wish to express my gratitude to the many students at Towson University whose feedback and enthusiastic classroom participation, along with suggestions from the anonymous reviewers, helped me to refine the pedagogical approach described in this essay.
    [Show full text]
  • Postmodern Test Theory
    Postmodern Test Theory ____________ Robert J. Mislevy Educational Testing Service ____________ (Reprinted with permission from Transitions in Work and Learning: Implications for Assessment, 1997, by the National Academy of Sciences, Courtesy of the National Academies Press, Washington, D.C.) Postmodern Test Theory Robert J. Mislevy Good heavens! For more than forty years I have been speaking prose without knowing it. Molière, Le Bourgeois Gentilhomme INTRODUCTION Molière’s Monsieur Jourdan was astonished to learn that he had been speaking prose all his life. I know how he felt. For years I have just been doing my job— trying to improve educational assessment by applying ideas from statistics and psychology. Come to find out, I’ve been advancing “neopragmatic postmodernist test theory” without ever intending to do so. This paper tries to convey some sense of what this rather unwieldy phrase means and offers some thoughts about what it implies for educational assessment, present and future. The goods news is that we can foresee some real improvements: assessments that are more open and flexible, better connected with students’ learning, and more educationally useful. The bad news is that we must stop expecting drop-in-from-the-sky assessment to tell us, in 2 hours and for $10, the truth, plus or minus two standard errors. Gary Minda’s (1995) Postmodern Legal Movements inspired the structure of what follows. Almost every page of his book evokes parallels between issues and new directions in jurisprudence on the one hand and the debates and new developments in educational assessment on the other. Excerpts from Minda’s book frame the sections of this paper.
    [Show full text]
  • Poststructuralism, Cultural Studies, and the Composition Classroom: Postmodern Theory in Practice Author(S): James A
    Poststructuralism, Cultural Studies, and the Composition Classroom: Postmodern Theory in Practice Author(s): James A. Berlin Source: Rhetoric Review, Vol. 11, No. 1 (Autumn, 1992), pp. 16-33 Published by: Taylor & Francis, Ltd. Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/465877 Accessed: 13-02-2019 19:20 UTC REFERENCES Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article: https://www.jstor.org/stable/465877?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms Taylor & Francis, Ltd. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Rhetoric Review This content downloaded from 146.111.138.234 on Wed, 13 Feb 2019 19:20:03 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms JAMES A. BERLIN - ~~~~~~~~~~~~~Purdue University Poststructuralism, Cultural Studies, and the Composition Classroom: Postmodern Theory in Practice The uses of postmodern theory in rhetoric and composition studies have been the object of considerable abuse of late. Figures of some repute in the field-the likes of Maxine Hairston and Peter Elbow-as well as anonymous voices from the Burkean Parlor section of Rhetoric Review-most recently, TS, a graduate student, and KF, a voice speaking for "a general English teacher audience" (192)-have joined the chorus of protest.
    [Show full text]