University of Groningen Rafts, Boats, and Cruise Ships Verhaegh, Sander

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

University of Groningen Rafts, Boats, and Cruise Ships Verhaegh, Sander University of Groningen Rafts, Boats, and Cruise Ships Verhaegh, Sander IMPORTANT NOTE: You are advised to consult the publisher's version (publisher's PDF) if you wish to cite from it. Please check the document version below. Document Version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Publication date: 2015 Link to publication in University of Groningen/UMCG research database Citation for published version (APA): Verhaegh, S. (2015). Rafts, Boats, and Cruise Ships: Naturalism and holism in Quine’s philosophy [Groningen]: University of Groningen Copyright Other than for strictly personal use, it is not permitted to download or to forward/distribute the text or part of it without the consent of the author(s) and/or copyright holder(s), unless the work is under an open content license (like Creative Commons). Take-down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Downloaded from the University of Groningen/UMCG research database (Pure): http://www.rug.nl/research/portal. For technical reasons the number of authors shown on this cover page is limited to 10 maximum. Download date: 11-02-2018 RAFTS, BOATS, AND CRUISE SHIPS Naturalism and Holism in Quine’s Philosophy SANDER VERHAEGH RAFTS,BOATS,ANDCRUISESHIPS © Sander Verhaegh, Groningen, 2015 Cover design: Anne Jansen. Typesetting: This document was typeset using (a modified ver- sion of) classicthesis, a style developed by André Miede and inspired by Robert Bringhurst’s The Elements of Typographic Style. Printed by *studio Michał Sławi´nski. This research was funded by the Netherlands Organisation for Scientific Research (NWO), Grant 322-20-001. ISBN: 978-90-367-8255-5 ISBN: 978-90-367-8254-8 (e-book) Rafts, Boats, and Cruise Ships Naturalism and Holism in Quine’s Philosophy Proefschrift ter verkrijging van de graad van doctor aan de Rijksuniversiteit Groningen op gezag van de rector magnificus prof. dr. E. Sterken en volgens besluit van het College voor Promoties. De openbare verdediging zal plaatsvinden op donderdag 19 november 2015 om 16.15 uur door Alexander Alfons Verhaegh geboren op 18 maart 1986 te Helden Promotor Prof. dr. A.J.M. Peijnenburg Copromotor Dr. A.M. Tamminga Beoordelingscommissie Prof. dr. G. Ebbs Prof. dr. H.J. Glock Prof. dr. L.B. Decock CONTENTS list of abbrevations xiii acknowledgments xxiii list of publications xxvii 1 introduction1 1.1 Historical background . 1 1.2 Naturalism and holism . 10 1.3 Reading Quine in context . 11 1.4 Plan . 14 i immanent and transcendent 19 2 quine’s argument from despair 21 2.1 Introduction . 21 2.2 From certainty to straight psychology . 26 2.3 Two strategies . 35 2.4 Self-sufficient sensory languages . 37 2.5 Quine’s response to the sceptic . 42 2.6 Taking holism seriously . 45 2.7 Theory vs. evidence . 48 2.8 Reinterpreting “Epistemology Naturalized” . 52 3 internal and external questions 57 3.1 Introduction . 58 3.2 Internal and external existence claims . 62 3.3 Two distinctions . 68 3.4 Quine on metaphysical existence claims . 74 3.5 Rabbits and complement-rabbits . 80 3.6 The ideal of pure reason . 85 3.7 Conclusion . 89 ix x contents 4 boarding neurath’s boat 91 4.1 Introduction . 91 4.2 Quinean naturalism decomposed . 93 4.3 Commitment 1: empiricism . 95 4.4 Commitment 2: holism . 98 4.5 Commitment 3: realism . 100 4.6 Early empiricism and bold behaviorism . 102 4.7 Quine’s naturalism in the early 1940s . 105 4.8 Narrow and wide holism . 111 4.9 Unregenerate realism . 119 4.10 From nominalism to realism . 121 4.11 From phenomenalism to realism . 125 4.12 Conclusion . 130 ii naturalism and holism 133 5 varieties of holism 135 5.1 Introduction: the ‘discovery’ of Vulcan . 135 5.2 Evidential holism . 142 5.3 Falsification and scientific practice . 144 5.4 Grünbaum’s argument . 148 5.5 The whole of science? . 151 5.6 Universal revisability . 157 5.7 Meaning holism . 164 5.8 Conclusion . 170 6 science, scientism, and sets 173 6.1 Introduction . 173 6.2 Justifying the axioms of set theory . 176 6.3 Realism and naturalism . 180 6.4 Pure mathematics vs. pure astrology . 185 6.5 Mad mathematics . 189 6.6 Open-minded naturalism . 195 6.7 Haack’s argument . 196 6.8 Aposteriorism vs. scientism . 199 contents xi 6.9 Quine’s replies . 205 6.10 SCIENCE vs. science .................. 208 6.11 A deflationary theory of justification . 211 6.12 ‘Traditional epistemology’ revisited . 213 7 conclusion 219 bibliography 225 samenvatting 269 index 273 LISTOFABBREVIATIONS This section provides a list of abbreviations used in this disserta- tion to refer to W. V. Quine’s (published and unpublished) work. Detailed references can be found in the Bibliography. A com- plete list of Quine’s publications up to 1993 (including reprints and translations) can be found in Yeghiayan( 2009). For an over- view of papers, books, reprints, and translations after 1993, see Douglas B. Quine’s website http://wvquine.org. The unpub- lished papers, letters, lectures, and notebooks listed below (marked with an asterisk) are stored at the Harvard Deposi- tory and can be accessed at Houghton Library. The documents’ call numbers, box numbers, and item numbers are provided in the Bibliography. A catalogue of much of Quine’s unpublished work is provided by Houghton Library at http://oasis.lib. harvard.edu/oasis/deliver/~hou01800. ANM Animadversion on the Notion of Meaning (1949) AT* Afterthoughts (1987) AWVQ Autobiography of W.V. Quine (1986) BTJ* The Behavioristic Treatment of James’ Theory of Perception (1930) CA Carnap (1987) CB Comment on Berger (1990) CCE Confessions of a Confirmed Extensionalist and Other Essays (2008) xiii xiv abbreviations CD Contextual Definition (1995) CGC A Comment on Grünbaum’s Claim (1962) CH Comment on Haack (1990) CK Comment on Koppelberg (1990) CLT Carnap and Logical Truth (1954) CP Comment on Parsons (1990) CPT Carnap’s Positivistic Travail (1984) CNT Comments on Neil Tennant’s “Carnap and Quine” (1994) CVO Carnap’s Views on Ontology (1951) CWH* Concepts and Working Hypotheses (1931) DE Designation and Existence (1939) EBDQ Exchange Between Donald Davidson and W. V. Quine Following Davidson’s Lecture (1994) EESW On Empirically Equivalent Systems of the World (1975) EJ* Early Jottings on Philosophy of Language (1937-1944) EN Epistemology Naturalized (1969) ENP* Epistemology Naturalized; or, the case for psychologism (1968) EQ Existence and Quantification (1969) FLM* Foundations of a Linguistic Theory of Meaning (1943) abbreviations xv FLPV From a Logical Point of View (1953/1961) FM Facts of the Matter (1977) FME Five Milestones of Empiricism (1975) FSS From Stimulus to Science (1995) GML The Growth of Mind and Language (1997) GQW Nelson Goodman, W. V. Quine and Morton White: A Triangular Correspondence (1947) GT Grades of Theoreticity (1970) HO* Holism (1987) ICQ* In Conversation: Professor W. V. Quine. Interviews by R. Fara (1993) IKL* The Immanuel Kant Lectures: Science and Sensibilia (1980) ILP The Importance of Logic for Philosophy (1950) IOH Identity, Ostension, Hypostasis (1946) IPOS In Praise of Observation Sentences (1993) IQJ* Interview with Quine for “La Janguardia” (1990) IV Immanence and Validity (1991) IWVQ Interview with Willard Van Orman Quine. Interview by L. Bergström and D. Føllesdal (1994) LAOP A Logistical Approach to the Ontological Problem (1939) xvi abbreviations LC Lectures on Carnap (1934) LDHP Lectures on David Hume’s Philosophy (1946) LMAP Let Me Accentuate the Positive (1990) LSQ* Levine Seminar Questions for Quine (1982) ME* Mathematical Entities (1950) ML1 Methods of Logic. First edition (1950) ML4 Methods of Logic. Fourth edition (1982) MMT* Mathematics as a Mode of Thought (1930) MSLT Mr. Strawson on Logical Theory (1953) MVD Mind and Verbal Dispositions (1975) N1* Nominalism (1937) N2 Nominalism (1946) NDL* The Notre Dame Lectures (1970) NEN Notes on Existence and Necessity (1943) NK Natural Kinds (1969) NLOM Naturalism; Or, Living within One’s Means (1995) NNK The Nature of Natural Knowledge (1975) NR* Notes on Reading (undated) OAM On Austin’s Method (1969) OE* Ontology and Epistemology (1944) OK* On the Organization of Knowledge (1927) abbreviations xvii OLPL* Oxford Lecture: Philosophy of Logic (1953) OM* Ontology, Metaphysics, etc... (1944-1951) OME On Mental Entities (1953) ON* Ontology Notes (1944) ONAS On the Notion of an Analytic Statement (1946) OR Ontological Relativity (1968) OR67* Ontological Relativity (1967) ORE Ontological Relativity and other essays (1969) ORWN Ontological Reduction and the World of Numbers (1964) OW Otherworldly (1978) OWTI On What There Is (1948) PIP* A Pragmatic Interpretation of Posivitism (1937) PL Philosophy of Logic (1970/1986) PML The Problem of Meaning in Linguistics (1953) PPE The Pragmatists’ Place in Empiricism (1975) PPLT Philosophical Progress in Language Theory (1970) PR Posits and Reality (1955) PT Pursuit of Truth (1990/1992) PTE* The Place of a Theory of Evidence (1952) PTF Progress on Two Fronts (1996) xviii abbreviations QBC* The Quine-Bergström Correspondence (1988-1996) QCC The Quine-Carnap Correspondence (1932-1970) QCC* The Quine-Church Correspondence (1935-1994) QD Quine in Dialogue (2008) QGC* The Quine-Goodman Correspondence (1935-1994) QHC* The Quine-Haack Correspondence (1975-1997) QHWC* The Quine-Hookway Correspondence (1988) QKC* The Quine-Koppelberg Correspondence (1981-1994) QQN* Questions for Quine by Stephen Neale (1986) QSM Quine Speaks His Mind. An interview by E. Pivcevic (1988) QU Quiddities (1987)
Recommended publications
  • Willard Van Orman Quine
    WILLARD VAN ORMAN QUINE Te philosopher’s task differs from the others’…in detail, but in no such drastic way as those suppose who imagine for the philosopher a vantage point outside the conceptual scheme he takes in charge. Tere is no such cosmic exile. He cannot study and revise the fundamental conceptual scheme of science and common sense without having some conceptual scheme, whether the same or another no less in need of philosophical scrutiny, in which to work. He can scrutinize and improve the system from within, appealing to coherence and simplicity, but this is the theoretician’s method generally. Quine, Word & Object, pp.275–6 Quine’s “Two Dogmas” 1. The analytic/synthetic distinction 2.The idea that everything reduces to sense-data. Quine thinks both are bogus. Two kinds of meaningful sentences: • Synthetic sentences (It passes the verifiability test: some possible experiences would either confirm it or disconfirm it.) e.g.: statements about physical things, other people, their minds, the self, my own sensations • Analytic sentences (Its truth or falsity are guaranteed by the rules of language alone. It is true in virtue of its meaning.) e.g.: propositions of logic, math, and definitions for translating empirical sentences into sentences about sense-data. “The problem of giving an actual rule for translating sentences about a material thing into sentences about sense-contents, which may be called the problem of the ‘reduction’ of material things to sense- contents, is the main philosophical part of the traditional problem of perception.” —Ayer, Language, Truth, and Logic, Ch.3 Theoretical Statements The table is beige.
    [Show full text]
  • Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association
    September 2007 Volume 81, Issue 1 Proceedings and Addresses of The American Philosophical Association apa THE AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL ASSOCIATION Eastern Division Program University of Delaware Newark, DE 19716 www.apaonline.org The American Philosophical Association Eastern Division One Hundred Fourth Annual Meeting Marriott Waterfront Hotel Baltimore, MD December 27 - 30, 2007 Proceedings and Addresses of The American Philosophical Association Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association (ISSN 0065-972X) is published five times each year and is distributed to members of the APA as a benefit of membership and to libraries, departments, and institutions for $75 per year. It is published by The American Philosophical Association, 31 Amstel Ave., University of Delaware, Newark, DE 19716. Second-Class Postage Paid at Newark, DE and additional mailing offices. POSTMASTER: Send address changes to Proceedings and Addresses, The American Philosophical Association, University of Delaware, Newark, DE 19716. Editor: David E. Schrader Phone: (302) 831-1112 Publications Coordinator: Erin Shepherd Fax: (302) 831-8690 Associate Editor: Richard Bett Web: www.apaonline.org Meeting Coordinator: Linda Smallbrook Proceedings and Addresses of The American Philosophical Association, the major publication of The American Philosophical Association, is published five times each academic year in the months of September, November, January, February, and May. Each annual volume contains the programs for the meetings of the three Divisions; the membership list; Presidential Addresses; news of the Association, its Divisions and Committees, and announcements of interest to philosophers. Other items of interest to the community of philosophers may be included by decision of the Editor or the APA Board of Officers.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Quine Is Not a Postmodernist
    University of Chicago Law School Chicago Unbound Journal Articles Faculty Scholarship 1997 Why Quine Is Not a Postmodernist Brian Leiter Follow this and additional works at: https://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/journal_articles Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Brian Leiter, "Why Quine Is Not a Postmodernist," 50 SMU Law Review 1739 (1997). This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at Chicago Unbound. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal Articles by an authorized administrator of Chicago Unbound. For more information, please contact [email protected]. WHY QUINE Is NOT A POSTMODERNIST Brian Leiter* TABLE OF CONTENTS I. INTRODUCTION ........................................ 1739 II. LEGITIMACY IN ADJUDICATION, TRUTH IN LAW. 1740 IL. PATFERSON'S QUINE VERSUS QUINE THE NATU RA LIST ........................................... 1746 I. INTRODUCTION ENNIS Patterson's wide-ranging book Law and Truth' has the great virtue of locating questions of legal theory within their broader (and rightful) philosophical context-that is, as special instances of more general problems in metaphysics and the philosophy of language. The book also sets out a position in jurisprudence that has some undeniable attractions.2 Although I have a number of disagree- ments with Patterson's treatment of the substantive philosophical issues at stake, there can be no doubt that he has performed a useful service in forcing legal philosophers to think seriously about the distinctively philo- sophical problems that define the discipline of jurisprudence. I organize my discussion around one topic in particular-namely, Pat- terson's identification of the great American philosopher Willard van Or- man Quine (born 1908) as a pivotal figure in the transition from "modernity" to "postmodernity."'3 This characterization, I will argue, in- volves an important misunderstanding of Quine's thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Necessity Necessity 161
    160 Metaphysics Chapter 17 Chapter Necessity Necessity 161 Necessity (or Contingency) Physical necessity is the ancient idea that everything that has ever happened and ever will happen is necessary, and can not be otherwise. It is also known as actualism. The only thing that can possibly happen is what actually happens. Necessity is often opposed to chance and contingency. In a necessary world there is no chance. Everything that happens is necessitated, determined by the laws of nature. There is only one possible (necessary?) future. The great atomist Leucippus stated the first dogma of determinism, an absolute necessity. “Nothing occurs at random, but everything for a reason and by necessity.” Contingency is the idea that many things or events are neither necessary nor impossible. Possibility is normally understood to include necessity. If something is necessary, it is a fortiori pos- sible. Contingency must be defined as the subset of possibility that excludes necessity. Chapter 17 Chapter Information philosophy claims that there is no physical necessity. The world is irreducibly contingent. Necessity is a logical concept, an idea that is an important part of a formal logical or mathematical system that is a human invention. Like certainty, analyticity, and the a priori, necessity and neces- sary truths are useful concepts for logicians and mathematicians, but not for a metaphysicist exploring the fundamental nature of reality, which includes irreducible contingency. The Logical Necessity of the Analytic and the A Priori Consider the simple analytically true proposition, “A is A.” Or perhaps the logical and mathematical statement that “1 = 1.” Most philosophers cannot imagine denying these true state- ments.
    [Show full text]
  • 9:30 - 11:00 SZB, Room 240
    PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE Department of Philosophy, UT, Austin Phil 332, Spring 2013 Unique Number 42755 T/TH: 9:30 - 11:00 SZB, Room 240 INSTRUCTOR Lawrence Ray Buchanan E-mail: [email protected] Phone: (512) 471-7396 Office: Waggener Hall 4th Floor Room # 416B Office hours: Tuesdays 11:30 – 12:30 COURSE SUMMARY The course focuses on various philosophical issues concerning language. Topics to be discussed include, but are not limited to, the following: speaker-meaning, conversational implicature, sentence/expression-meaning, reference, modality, and propositional attitude ascriptions. COURSE REQUIREMENTS Assignments: • Two 6-7 page papers on topics selected from a list of prompts given by instructor. The first of these papers will be worth 20% of the student’s final grade for the course; the second will be worth 25% of the grade for the course. • One in-class midterm worth 25% of the student’s final grade. • A take-home final exam worth 25% of the grade. • Class participation and attendance (5%). Regarding the *participation* component of your grade: I expect regular attendance and participation in our course. Moreover, I expect you to have read the material for lecture carefully in advance. However, should my expectations on either front fail to be met, I reserve the right to assign (short) in-class written assignments regarding the required reading for the day that will then be counted towards the participation component of your grade. Late work: I do not accept work after the due date without a valid documented excuse. Please Note: One of the principal aims of this course is to give students experience with writing in an academic discipline.
    [Show full text]
  • Willard Van Orman Quine: the Analytic/Synthetic Distinction
    Willard Van Orman Quine: The Analytic/Synthetic Distinction Willard Van Orman Quine was one of the most well-known American “analytic” philosophers of the twentieth century. He made significant contributions to many areas of philosophy, including philosophy of language, logic, epistemology, philosophy of science, and philosophy of mind/psychology (behaviorism). However, he is best known for his rejection of the analytic/synthetic distinction. Technically, this is the distinction between statements true in virtue of the meanings of their terms (like “a bachelor is an unmarried man”) and statements whose truth is a function not simply of the meanings of terms, but of the way the world is (such as, “That bachelor is wearing a grey suit”). Although a contentious thesis, analyticity has been a popular explanation, especially among empiricists, both for the necessity of necessary truths and for the a priori knowability of some truths. Thus, in some contexts “analytic truth,” “necessary truth,” and “a priori truth” have been used interchangeably, and the analytic/synthetic distinction has been treated as equivalent to the distinctions between necessary and contingent truths, and between a priori and a posteriori (or empirical) truths. Empirical truths can be known only by empirical verification, rather than by “unpacking” the meanings of the terms involved, and are usually thought to be contingent. Quine wrestled with the analytic/synthetic distinction for years, but he did not make his thoughts public until 1950, when he delivered his paper, “The Two Dogmas of Empiricism” at a meeting of the American Philosophical Association. In this paper, Quine argues that all attempts to define and understand analyticity are circular.
    [Show full text]
  • Getting a Grip: Ontological Commitment, Truthmaking and Aboutness
    Getting a grip: ontological commitment, truthmaking and aboutness Workshop “Ontological Commitment”, IHPST Paris, March 23, 2007 Philipp Keller∗ Abstract I argue that the traditional notion of ontological commitment has two aspects, which are both better accounted for by other theories: a theory of aboutness and a theory of truthmaking. I give a short sketch of both, and try to bring the separate strands together in the project of a general theory of (metaphysical) making. 1 The two strands in Quine’s criterion of ontological com- mitment The champion of ontological commitment is undoubtedly Quine: if “to be assumed as an entity is […] to be reckoned as the value of a variable” (Quine 1948: 13), a theory or body of (putative) truths T commits us to those entities that are assumed to be in the range of variables to make T true. According to Quine, it is the presumed truth of the sentences we use that puts us under ontological obligations and it is our use of first-order quantification in a semi-formalised canonical idiom which makes these obligations explicit. I want to argue, first, that it is not the truth of what we assert but the inferences we are prepared to accept that commit us to entities; second, that this notion of ontological commitment should not be formulated in modal terms and, third, that the intuitive notion of ontological commitment has two aspects which should be separated and are better captured by theories of aboutness and of truthmaking respectively. According to Quine’s criterion, what a sentence commits us to is determined by what its variables range over and hence by how it is formalised.
    [Show full text]
  • Willard Van Orman Quine's Philosophical Development in the 1930S and 1940S Frederique Janssen-Lauret
    W.V. Quine's Philosophical Development, F. Janssen-Lauret, in The Significance of the New Logic, CUP 2018 Willard Van Orman Quine's Philosophical Development in the 1930s and 1940s Frederique Janssen-Lauret Published in The Significance of the New Logic: A Translation of Quine's O Sentido da Nova Lógica (ed. and tr. W. Carnielli, F. Janssen-Lauret, and W. Pickering), Cambridge University Press (2018), pp. xiv-xlvii. 1. History of Analytic Philosophy and Early Quine's Place Within It W.V. Quine (1908-2000), pioneer of mathematical logic, champion of naturalism in philosophy of science and epistemology, atheist, materialist, unifier of an austere physicalism with the truth of logic and mathematics, globetrotter, polyglot, Harvard stalwart and celebrated naval officer, was both an establishment figure and a free-thinking radical. Quine's life began shortly after the emergence of analytic philosophy. He was soon to become one of its towering figures. Taught by A.N. Whitehead, interlocutor to Rudolf Carnap, Alfred Tarski, and Ruth Barcan Marcus, teacher of Donald Davidson and David Lewis, Quine was at the scene of the development of modern set theory, logical positivism, modal logic, truth-conditional semantics, and the metaphysics of possible worlds. Hardly a significant new movement in analytic philosophy passed him by. Yet Quine's relationship to many of these movements is surprisingly ill-understood. Everyone knows that the logical positivists, including Quine's mentor Carnap, sought to place truth and meaning on a proper scientific footing by countenancing only a priori analytic and a posteriori empirically testable statements as properly significant.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Time: a Slightly Opinionated Introduction
    Philosophy of time: A slightly opinionated introduction Florian Fischer There are several intertwined debates in the area of contemporary philos- ophy of time. One field of inquiry is the nature of time itself. Presentists think that only the present moment exists whereas eternalists believe that all of (space-)time exists on a par. The second main field of inquiry is the question of how objects persist through time. The endurantist claims that objects are three-dimensional wholes, which persist by being wholly1 present, whereas the perdurantist thinks that objects are four- dimensional and that their temporal parts are the bearers of properties. The third debate in the field of contemporary philosophy of time is about tense- versus tenseless theory. Tensers are at odds with detensers about the status of the linguistic reference to the present moment. These are only very crude characterizations and it is even disputed by some ad- vocates of the corresponding positions that they are accurate. However this very sketchy picture already reveals a fundamental difference: The eternalism/presentism and endurance/perdurance discussions belong to the field of metaphysics, whereas tense is in the first instance a linguistic phenomenon. Among the many fields of philosophy, there are two that are more intimately interconnected than most but whose practi- tioners have too long pursued relatively independent paths. On the one hand, there are philosophers of language, who have devoted much attention to indexicals (`now', etc.), tem- poral operators (`it has been the case that', etc.), and tensed sentences. On the other hand, there are the philosophers of tensed and tenseless time (also called A-time or B-time, dynamic time or static time, etc.).
    [Show full text]
  • A Trip to the Metaphysical Jungle –How Kripke's Intuitions Revived
    https://doi.org/10.20378/irbo-51675 A Trip to the Metaphysical Jungle – How Kripke’s Intuitions Revived Aristotelian Essentialism Sebastian Krebs (University of Bamberg) Besides his substantial influences on other fields of philosophy, Saul Kripke is famous for smoothing the way for a new type of Aristotelian essentialism. However, Kripke’s comments on essentialism are utterly vague and are built entirely on fundamental intuitions about the use of language and necessity de re in modal logic. He famously disproved Willard Van Orman Quine who, a few decades earlier, had banned necessity de re into the metaphysical jungle of Aristotelian essentialism – a jungle that a true empiricist must not enter. But not only Kripke’s refutation of Quine, but also his own essentialism is based on intuition. Kripke thereby overcomes an anti-essentialist dogma that was established by Kant in his Critique of Pure Reason. But because of its vagueness, one might well call Kripke’s intuitive essentialism a ‘metaphysical jungle’. Nevertheless, a trip to Kripke’s jungle is a promising milestone on the way to a refreshed Aristotelian metaphysics. 1. Travel arrangements: The rejection of Quine’s anti-essentialism In Two dogmas of empiricism, Willard Van Orman Quine rejects the traditional distinction between synthetic and analytic truths. Among others Immanuel Kant suggested this distinction in his Critique of Pure Reason. Quine criticizes it as a relic from metaphysical dogmas which a pure empiricism (as Quine wants to pursue it) has to overcome: [O]ne is tempted to suppose in general that the truth of a statement is somehow analyzable into a linguistic component and a factual component.
    [Show full text]
  • Willard Van Orman Quine Was Spread Upon the Permanent Records of the Faculty
    At a meeting of the FACULTY OF ARTS AND SCIENCES on May 7, 2002, the following tribute to the life and service of the late Willard Van Orman Quine was spread upon the permanent records of the Faculty. WILLARD VAN ORMAN QUINE BORN: June 25, 1908 DIED: December 25, 2000 Willard van Orman Quine, one of the most eminent philosophers of the twentieth century, was born June 25, 1908 in Akron, Ohio. He grew up in Akron and attended Oberlin College, receiving the A.B. in mathematics in 1930, already interested in logic and philosophy. He came to Harvard as a graduate student in 1930 and was affiliated with the University for the rest of his long life. He completed the Ph.D. in two years under A. N. Whitehead, co-author with Bertrand Russell of Principia Mathematica. He spent 1932-33 in Europe as a Sheldon Fellow and encountered the Vienna Circle, Carnap in Prague, and Tarski in Warsaw. These encounters were decisive for his future work. In 1933 he was elected to the first group of Junior Fellows of the Harvard Society of Fellows. He was Faculty Instructor in Philosophy from 1936 to 1941, associate professor from 1941 to 1948, professor from 1948 to 1956, and Edgar Pierce Professor of Philosophy from 1956 until his retirement in 1978. During World War II he worked in a Navy unit that decoded and analyzed coded messages from the German submarine fleet. His earlier research and writing were mainly in logic. His efforts to simplify Russell’s theory of types led to his probably most important contribution to mathematical logic, the set theory NF of his paper “New foundations for mathematical logic” (1937).
    [Show full text]
  • Representation and Deconstruction of Turkish German Stereotypes Through Gegen Die Wand and Kebab Connections
    University of Tennessee, Knoxville TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange Supervised Undergraduate Student Research Chancellor’s Honors Program Projects and Creative Work 5-2011 Representation and Deconstruction of Turkish German Stereotypes through Gegen die Wand and Kebab Connections Charli Celine Kerns [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_chanhonoproj Part of the Other German Language and Literature Commons Recommended Citation Kerns, Charli Celine, "Representation and Deconstruction of Turkish German Stereotypes through Gegen die Wand and Kebab Connections" (2011). Chancellor’s Honors Program Projects. https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_chanhonoproj/1428 This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Supervised Undergraduate Student Research and Creative Work at TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Chancellor’s Honors Program Projects by an authorized administrator of TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Representation and Deconstruction of Turkish German Stereotypes through Gegen die Wand and Kebab Connections Charli Kerns Honors Thesis submitted German Section of the Department Of Modern Foreign Languages and Literatures College of Art and Sciences Introduction: When we as the audience watch a film, we step into a world overtly comprised of plot, climax, and resolution. However, in every film, cultural nuances covertly exist that repossess
    [Show full text]