Freedom and the Strong State : on German Ordoliberalism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Freedom and the Strong State : on German Ordoliberalism This is a repository copy of Freedom and the Strong State : On German Ordoliberalism. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/67263/ Version: Submitted Version Article: Bonefeld, Werner orcid.org/0000-0001-6709-5313 (2012) Freedom and the Strong State : On German Ordoliberalism. New Political Economy. pp. 633-656. ISSN 1469-9923 https://doi.org/10.1080/13563467.2012.656082 Reuse Items deposited in White Rose Research Online are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved unless indicated otherwise. They may be downloaded and/or printed for private study, or other acts as permitted by national copyright laws. The publisher or other rights holders may allow further reproduction and re-use of the full text version. This is indicated by the licence information on the White Rose Research Online record for the item. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ New Political Economy For Peer Review Only Freedom and the Strong State: On German Ordoliberalism Journal: New Political Economy Manuscript ID: CNPE-2011-0039.R2 Manuscript Typ : Original Articl URL: http:/mc.manuscriptcentral.com/cnpe Page 1 of 22 New Political Economy 1 2 3 4 Abstract 5 Ordo-liberalism is the theory behind the German social market economy. Its theoretical 6 stance developed in the context of the economic crisis and political turmoil of the Weimar 7 Republic in the late 1920s. It is premised on the strong state as the locus of liberal 8 governance, and holds that economic freedom derives from political authority. In the context 9 of the crisis of neoliberal political economy and austerity, and debates about the resurgence of 10 11 the state vis-à-vis the economy, the article introduces the ordoliberal argument that the free 12 economy presupposes the exercise of strong state authority, and that economic liberty is a 13 practice of liberal governance. This practice is fundamentally one of social policy to secure 14 the sociological and ethical preconditions of free markets. The study of ordo-liberalism brings 15 to the fore a tradition of a state-centric neo-liberalism, one that says that economic freedom is 16 ordered freedom,For one thatPeer argues that theReview strong state is the polit Onlyical form of free markets, and 17 one that conceives of competition and enterprise as a political task. 18 19 20 Keywords 21 Ordo-liberalism, Neoliberalism, Strong State, Free Economy, Economic Crisis, Freedom and 22 Authority, Liberal Interventionism, Class, Enterprise, Social Market Economy 23 24 25 26 27 Title 28 Freedom and the Strong State: On German Ordo-liberalism 29 30 31 Werner Bonefeld1 32 33 34 Introduction 35 The German ordoliberal tradition is better known in the Anglo-Saxon world as the Freiburg 36 School, or German neo-liberalism, or indeed as the theoretical foundation of the postwar 37 38 German social market economy. It originated in the late 1920s / early 1930s in a context of 39 financial crisis and economic depression, political violence and austerity, conditions of 40 ungovernability, and entrenched class positions. The founding thinkers of ordo-liberalism 41 were Walter Eucken, Franz Böhm, Alexander Rüstow, Wilhelm Röpke and Alfred Müller- 42 Armack. In the context of the Weimar crisis, they developed a particular account on how to 43 make capitalism work as a liberal economy, or as Foucault (2008) saw it, on how to define or 44 redefine, or rediscover the economic rationality of capitalist social relations. The ordoliberals 45 did not identify neoliberalism with a weak state that is at the mercy of economic forces. They 46 identified it with a strong state – a state that restrains competition and secures the social and 47 ideological preconditions of economic liberty. For these thinkers, the weak state is tantamount 48 to disaster. 49 50 51 The ordoliberal idea of a social market economy has been seen as a progressive alternative 52 beyond left and right (see for example, Giddens, 1998). Indeed, Maurice Glasman (1996: 54- 53 54 1 55 I researched the Ordoliberal tradition with the support of an ESRC grant entitled ‘Ordoliberalism and the Crisis 56 of Neoliberal Political Economy’, RES-000-22-4006. The support of the ESRC is gratefully acknowledged. Earlier 57 versions were presented to the staff/student research seminar at Ruskin College, Oxford (March 2011), BISA at 58 Manchester (April 2011), and a workshop on State Power, New School, New York (May 2011). I want to thank 59 Neal Lawson who was most generous with his time, allowing me to verbalise my account about the ordoliberals, 60 which proved most helpful. Peter Burnham, Paul Langley, John Roberts, Rudi Schmitt, Eric Sheppard, Tim Stanton and Hugo Radice provided generous advice, helpful comments, and encouragement, for which I am most grateful. I wish to express my thanks to the three anonymous referees whose comments helped to sharpen the argument. Finally, I thank Colin Hay for his careful handling of the editorial process. 1 URL: http:/mc.manuscriptcentral.com/cnpe New Political Economy Page 2 of 22 1 2 3 56) conceives of it as a socially responsible political economy that in contrast to neoliberal 4 5 ideas of free markets, is not a market economy at all. In his view, it amounts to a socially 6 responsible form of government that protects individuals from the sort of homogenisation and 7 strife that markets bring about. However, closer inspection reveals ‘a rather different 8 orientation from that usually attributed to the term’ social market economy (Tribe 1995: 205). 9 In the British context, Thomas Balogh (1950) who was a Keynesian economist and advisor to 10 the Labour Party, rejected the idea of the social market economy as an attempt at planning by 11 the free price mechanism. For the political right, this was precisely what made it so 12 interesting. Terence Hutchinson (1981) agreed with the ordoliberal critique of laissez faire 13 liberalism, saying that it concedes too much power to economic agents, whose greed, though 14 required to oil the wheels of competition, is all consuming to the extent that it destroys its 15 own foundation, the prevention of which he says, is a political task. As Director of the Centre 16 For Peer Review Only 17 for Policy Studies, Sir Keith Joseph had shown lively interest in German ordo-liberalism. It 18 provided, he said (1975: 3) for ’responsible policies, which work with and through the market 19 to achieve [the] wider social aims’ of an integrated society. Andrew Gamble (1979) focused 20 the ‘revival’ of neoliberalism in the 1970s as a political practice of ‘free economy and strong 21 state’. With this conception Gamble traced the political stance of the incoming Thatcher 22 government back to this defining ordoliberal idea. At the same time, Foucault’s (2008) 23 lectures at the College de France, 1978-1979, argued that the neo-liberalism usually 24 associated with the free market deregulation of the Chicago school derives from the German 25 ordoliberal tradition, and he discussed the ordoliberal stance as an original contribution to the 26 bio-political practices of liberal governance.2 In the language of the ordoliberals, bio-politics 27 is called Vitalpolitik – a politics of life. They conceive of social market economy as a project 28 of Vitalpolitik – which they describe as a social policy that undercuts demands for collective 29 30 forms of welfare provision in favour of a human economy of self-responsible social 31 enterprise. The designated purpose of ordoliberal social policy is to ingrain entrepreneurship, 32 private property and the free price mechanism into the fabric of society to prevent the 33 proletarianisation of social structures. 34 35 For the ordoliberals, the experience of capitalist crisis of the late 1920s was proof that the 36 economic cannot be left to organise itself. They accepted that capitalism had brought about 37 miserable social conditions, which they conceived of as proletarianisation. They recognised 38 collectivist responses to capitalism as understandable reactions to this misery but argued that 39 they reinforce that same misery. They thus saw their neo-liberalism as a third way in 40 distinction to laissez faire liberalism and collective forms of political economy, the latter 41 ranging from Bismarckian paternalism to social-democratic ideas of social justice, 42 3 43 Keynesianism and Bolshevism. Against laissez faire liberalism, they argued that it is blind to 44 the social consequences of capitalism, which, they argued, liberals need to address to sustain 45 market freedom. Against collectivist forms of political economy they argued that they 46 compounded that same proletarian condition which they ostensibly sought to overcome, and 4 47 that their attempts at organising the economy will eventually lead to tyranny. 48 49 The fundamental question at the heart of ordoliberal thought is how to sustain market-liberal 50 governance in the face of mass-democratic challenges, class conflicts, and political strife: 51 how, in other words, to promote enterprise and secure the role of the entrepreneur in the face 52 53 54 2 Peck (2010) doubts Foucault’s claim that Chicago neo-liberalism derives from German ordoliberalism. In his 55 defence, Foucault did not argue that Chicago neo-liberalism is a German derivative, but that it developed core 56 ordoliberal ideas in its own distinctive deregulatory manner. Friedman’s support of, and indeed advisory role in, 57 the Pinochet dictatorship is well known, and does not contradict his market-liberal stance.
Recommended publications
  • Competition in a Social Market Economy
    Competition in a Social Market economy Speech by Commissioner Monti at the Conference of the European Parliament and the European Commission on ‘Reform of European Competition law’ in Freiburg on 9/10 November 2000 Ladies and Gentlemen, Let me take my turn to welcome you to this conference that has been jointly organised by the European Parliament and the European Commission to discuss the Reform of EC competition policy. The Commission has launched a reform that aims at overhauling the whole of the competition law framework in order to ensure more efficient enforcement of the European competition rules and thereby reinforce their effect. A reform of this scope is an excellent opportunity to re-visit and to re-examine what is basic to our understanding. The venue here at Freiburg of course reminds us of the Freiburg School. The Freiburg School has made a major contribution to shaping the post-war economy as one of the sources of the concept of Soziale Marktwirtschaft – Social market economy. When we take a close look at what ‘Social Market Economy’ stands for, we find that we are in the presence of one of those basic concepts to which many policy choices can be traced back. We also realise that we are in the presence of strikingly modern ideas. Having said this, it is not my intention to discuss here the issue whether ‘Social Market economy’ is a model for Europe1 or whether the concept of Social Market Economy and the historic experience it encompasses is a major building block of what we sometimes call the ‘European Model’.
    [Show full text]
  • German Political and Economic Ideology in the Twentieth Century
    EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF CULTURAL AND POLITICAL SOCIOLOGY https://doi.org/10.1080/23254823.2018.1559745 German political and economic ideology in the twentieth century and its theological problems: The Lutheran genealogy of ordoliberalism Troels Krarup Department of Sociology, Copenhagen University, Copenhagen, Denmark ABSTRACT Ordoliberalism is widely considered to be the dominant ideology of the German political elite today and consequently responsible at least in part for its hard ‘austerity’ line during the recent Eurozone crisis. This article presents a genealogy of the main concerns, concepts and problems around which early German ordoliberalism was formed and structured as a political and economic ideology. Early ordoliberalism is shown to be rooted in an interwar Germanophone Lutheran Evangelical tradition of anti-humanist ‘political ethics’. Its specific conceptions of the market, the state, the individual, freedom and duty were developed on a Lutheran Evangelical basis. Analytically, the article considers ideological influences of theology on political and economic theory not so much in terms of consensus and ideational overlap, but rather in terms of shared concerns, concepts and problems across different positions. ARTICLE HISTORY Received 18 March 2018; Accepted 10 December 2018 KEYWORDS Ordoliberalism; ideology; Europe; economic thought; religion; genealogy JEL Classification A12 relation of economics to other disciplines; A13 relation of economics to social values; B29 history of economic thought since 1925: other 1. Introduction: unity and variety in neoliberalism In Colombel’s(1994, p. 128) accurate rephrasing of Foucault’s(1993, p. 35) ‘history of the present’, genealogy is ‘the history of a problem of which the present relevance must be assessed’. One such problem, one that is of major political, cultural and sociological interest in Europe today, relates to the particular German tradition of economic and political thinking termed ordoliberalism.
    [Show full text]
  • The „Consumer Choice“ Paradigm in German Ordoliberalism and Its Impact Upon EU Competition Law
    Discussion Paper No 1/14 The „Consumer Choice“ Paradigm in German Ordoliberalism and its Impact upon EU Competition Law Peter Behrens March 2014 Discussion Paper No 1/14 Europa-Kolleg Hamburg Institute for European Integration The Europa-Kolleg Hamburg is a private law foundation. The foundation has the objective of furthering research and academic teachings in the area of European integration and inter- national cooperation. The Institute for European Integration, an academic institution at the University of Hamburg, constitutes the organisational framework for the academic activities of the Europa-Kolleg. The Discussion Papers are designed to make results of research activities pursued at the Institute for European Integration accessible for the public. The views expressed in these papers are those of the authors only and do not necessarily reflect positions shared by the Institute for European Integration. Please address any comments that you may want to make directly to the author. Editor: Europa-Kolleg Hamburg Institute for European Integration Prof. Dr. Markus Kotzur, LL.M. (Duke) (managing director), Dr. Konrad Lammers (research director) Windmühlenweg 27 22607 Hamburg, Germany http://www.europa-kolleg-hamburg.de Please quote as follows: Europa-Kolleg Hamburg, Institute for European Integration, Discussion Paper No 1/14, http://www.europa-kolleg-hamburg.de 2 Discussion Paper No 1/14 The „Consumer Choice“ Paradigm in German Ordoliberalism and its Impact upon EU Competition Law Peter Behrens* Abstract This paper explores the origin and development of the "consumer choice" paradigm as the core concept of German ordoliberal thought which has had a strong impact on EU competition policy and law.
    [Show full text]
  • Markets Not Capitalism Explores the Gap Between Radically Freed Markets and the Capitalist-Controlled Markets That Prevail Today
    individualist anarchism against bosses, inequality, corporate power, and structural poverty Edited by Gary Chartier & Charles W. Johnson Individualist anarchists believe in mutual exchange, not economic privilege. They believe in freed markets, not capitalism. They defend a distinctive response to the challenges of ending global capitalism and achieving social justice: eliminate the political privileges that prop up capitalists. Massive concentrations of wealth, rigid economic hierarchies, and unsustainable modes of production are not the results of the market form, but of markets deformed and rigged by a network of state-secured controls and privileges to the business class. Markets Not Capitalism explores the gap between radically freed markets and the capitalist-controlled markets that prevail today. It explains how liberating market exchange from state capitalist privilege can abolish structural poverty, help working people take control over the conditions of their labor, and redistribute wealth and social power. Featuring discussions of socialism, capitalism, markets, ownership, labor struggle, grassroots privatization, intellectual property, health care, racism, sexism, and environmental issues, this unique collection brings together classic essays by Cleyre, and such contemporary innovators as Kevin Carson and Roderick Long. It introduces an eye-opening approach to radical social thought, rooted equally in libertarian socialism and market anarchism. “We on the left need a good shake to get us thinking, and these arguments for market anarchism do the job in lively and thoughtful fashion.” – Alexander Cockburn, editor and publisher, Counterpunch “Anarchy is not chaos; nor is it violence. This rich and provocative gathering of essays by anarchists past and present imagines society unburdened by state, markets un-warped by capitalism.
    [Show full text]
  • Public Choice, Constitutional Political Economy and Law and Economics
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Research Papers in Economics 0610 PUBLIC CHOICE, CONSTITUTIONAL POLITICAL ECONOMY AND LAW AND ECONOMICS Ludwig Van den Hauwe Brussels, Belgium © Copyright 1999 Ludwig Van den Hauwe Abstract The various subdisciplines within the emerging ‘new institutionalism’ in economics all draw special attention to the legal-political constraints within which economic and political agents choose and therefore represent a return of economics to its appropriate legal foundations. By changing the name of his research programme to constitutional political economy Buchanan distanced himself from those parts of the public choice literature that remained too close to the traditional welfare economics approach. This chapter draws lessons for law and economics from recent developments in the re-emerging field of constitutional political economy. CPE compares alternative sets of institutional arrangements, in markets and the polity, and their outcomes, using ‘democratic consent’ as an internal standard of comparison. The chapter discusses the methodological foundation of the CPE approach, presents Buchanan’s reconstruction of the Coase theorem along subjectivist-contractarian lines and gives an overview of recent contributions to the literature. JEL classification: B41, D70, H10 Keywords: Constitutional Economics, Constitutional Political Economy, Public Choice, James M. Buchanan, Methodological Foundation A. The Manifold Legacy of Adam Smith 1. Introduction As the title of this chapter suggests, the new law and economics movement on the one hand and the now rapidly emerging field of constitutional political economy - as well as the somewhat older public choice branch of economics from which it emerged - on the other hand, are research traditi- ons that are in some respects genuinely related.
    [Show full text]
  • Libertarianism Karl Widerquist, Georgetown University-Qatar
    Georgetown University From the SelectedWorks of Karl Widerquist 2008 Libertarianism Karl Widerquist, Georgetown University-Qatar Available at: https://works.bepress.com/widerquist/8/ Libertarianism distinct ideologies using the same label. Yet, they have a few commonalities. [233] [V1b-Edit] [Karl Widerquist] [] [w6728] Libertarian socialism: Libertarian socialists The word “libertarian” in the sense of the believe that all authority (government or combination of the word “liberty” and the private, dictatorial or democratic) is suffix “-ian” literally means “of or about inherently dangerous and possibly tyrannical. freedom.” It is an antonym of “authoritarian,” Some endorse the motto: where there is and the simplest dictionary definition is one authority, there is no freedom. who advocates liberty (Simpson and Weiner Libertarian socialism is also known as 1989). But the name “libertarianism” has “anarchism,” “libertarian communism,” and been adopted by several very different “anarchist communism,” It has a variety of political movements. Property rights offshoots including “anarcho-syndicalism,” advocates have popularized the association of which stresses worker control of enterprises the term with their ideology in the United and was very influential in Latin American States and to a lesser extent in other English- and in Spain in the 1930s (Rocker 1989 speaking countries. But they only began [1938]; Woodcock 1962); “feminist using the term in 1955 (Russell 1955). Before anarchism,” which stresses person freedoms that, and in most of the rest of the world (Brown 1993); and “eco-anarchism” today, the term has been associated almost (Bookchin 1997), which stresses community exclusively with leftists groups advocating control of the local economy and gives egalitarian property rights or even the libertarian socialism connection with Green abolition of private property, such as and environmental movements.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Characteristics of the Free Market in a Cooperative Society
    ON THE CHARACTERISTICS OF THE FREE MARKET IN A COOPERATIVE SOCIETY Norbert N. Agbeko Email: [email protected] ABSTRACT The key characteristic of a true free market economy is that exchanges are entirely voluntary. When there is a monopoly in the creation of currency as we have in today’s markets, you no longer have a true free market. Features of the current economic system such as central banking and taxation would be nonexistent in a free market. This paper examines how currency monopoly leads to the instabilities and imbalances that we see in today’s economy. It also proposes that currencies should emerge from the voluntary exchange of goods and services, and studies economic interaction across all scales, by considering economic action in cases where the self-interests of individuals are coincident. By examining the voluntary exchange of goods and services at the scale of an entire society, it is shown that a new currency system, which resolves a lot of the problems caused by the current fiat currency system, emerges naturally from the free market. The new currency system is robust and efficient, and provides a way for public goods and services to be provided, and its providers compensated, without the need for direct taxation. JEL Codes: E14, E42. I. INTRODUCTION In our world today, currency arises from banking. Currency is initially created by a central bank and then expanded by banks through fractional reserve banking. The question of what the best way is for currency to be created is an open one. Our currency is generated from banking because of the way it evolved.
    [Show full text]
  • Neoliberal Reason and Its Forms: Depoliticization Through Economization∗
    Neoliberal reason and its forms: Depoliticization through economization∗ Yahya M. Madra Department of Economics Boğaziçi University Bebek, 34342, Istanbul, Turkey [email protected] Yahya M. Madra studied economics in Istanbul and Amherst, Massachusetts. He has taught at the universities of Massachusetts and Boğaziçi, and at Skidmore and Gettysburg Colleges. He currently conducts research in history of modern economics at Boğaziçi University with the support of TÜBITAK-BIDEB Scholarship. His work appeared in Journal of Economic Issues, Rethinking Marxism, The European Journal of History of Economic Thought, Psychoanalysis, Society, Culture and Subjectivity as well as edited volumes. His current research is on the role of subjectivity in political economy of capitalism and post-capitalism. and Fikret Adaman Department of Economics, Boğaziçi University Bebek, 34342, Istanbul, Turkey [email protected] Fikret Adaman studied economics in Istanbul and Manchester. He has been lecturing at Boğaziçi University on political economy, ecological economics and history of economics. His work appeared in Journal of Economic Issues, New Left Review, Cambridge Journal of Economics, Economy and Society, Ecological Economics, The European Journal of History of Economic Thought, Energy Policy and Review of Political Economy as well as edited volumes. His current research is on the political ecology of Turkey. DRAFT: Istanbul, October 3, 2012 ∗ Earlier versions of this paper have been presented in departmental and faculty seminars at Gettysburg College, Uludağ University, Boğaziçi University, İstanbul University, University of Athens, and New School University. The authors would like to thank the participants of those seminars as well as to Jack Amariglio, Michel Callon, Pat Devine, Harald Hagemann, Stavros Ioannides, Ayşe Mumcu, Ceren Özselçuk, Maliha Safri, Euclid Tsakalatos, Yannis Varoufakis, Charles Weise, and Ünal Zenginobuz for their thoughtful comments and suggestions on the various versions of this paper.
    [Show full text]
  • The Need of State? American Anarcho-Capitalism
    Ad Americam Journal of American Studies Vol. 10, 2009 ISSN 1896-9461 ISBN 978-83-233-2905-3 Magdalena Modrzejewska THE NEED OF STATE? AMERICAN ANARCHO-CAPITALISM The paper examines the theory of anarcho-capitalists philosophers David Friedman and Murray Rothbard. Both philosophers argue for a society based in voluntary trade of private property (including money, consumer goods, land, and capital goods) and services (includ- ing protection services) in order to maximize individual liberty and prosperity. Moreover, they maintain that order exists in the pre-state situation, and any form of compulsion from the government/state violates that natural order. The paper examines how society can func- tion in such an anarchic, non-state situation (especially how the law and legal system can arise and exist without a state/government). Libertarians created a vision of an individual as a rational being, with a broad range of rights bestowed upon him/her, free from any form of external coercion. Therefore, they postulated that all relations between individuals should be established on volun- tary ground. Consequently, they faced the vital question of whether the existence of a state is required at all, and if so – how we could justify the rise of a state without the violation of the individual rights. In their reflection about the shape of the state, libertarians use methodological an- archism.1 “In political philosophy this method means that, as a starting point for their research, they use the state of nature as described by Locke or Hobbes, associated with anarchy, and then they show the possibility of overcoming such an anarchy and reaching in a rational manner the just social state” (Miklaszewska 1994: 21).
    [Show full text]
  • Constitutional Economics
    Prof. Dr. Bernhard Neumärker Summer Term 2013 University of Freiburg Constitutional Economics I Introduction II The constitutional perspective in economics 1 Constitutional and orthodox view of economics [3,4,6] 2 The methodological hard core of constitutional analysis [4,5] 3 Constitutional economics as a part of modern political economy [11,24] 4 The logic of constitutional constraints [3,5] 5 Constitutional design and constitutional reform [2,4,12,15,19,22] 6 Constitutions as social contracts 6.1 Explicit and implicit contracts [17,19] 6.2 Complete and incomplete contracts [11,15,19,23] 7 Normative and positive constitutional economics 7.1 Emergence and stability of constitutions [1,14,17,18,20, 25] 7.2 Economic effects of constitutional rules [21,24] 7.3 'Optimal' constitutions [12,17,19] III Applications 1 Constitutional design of democratic institutions [1,8,12,17,25] 2 Fiscal constitutions [3,16,19, 26] 3 Constitutional rules for market regulation [6,15] 4 Constitutional change and rent-seeking [10,17] 5 Economic policy consequences of constitutional arrangements [6,10,21] 2 References [1] Acemoglu, D., Robinson, J.A.: Economic Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy, Cambridge 2006. [2] Bailey, M.J.: Constitution for a Future Country, Basingstoke et al. 2001. [3] Brennan, G., Buchanan, J. M.: The Power to Tax, Cambridge et al. 1980. [4] Brennan, G., Buchanan, J. M.: The Reason of Rules, Cambridge et al. 1985. [5] Buchanan, J. M.: The Domain of Constitutional Economics, in: Constitutional Political Economy, vol. 1, no. 1 (1990), 1-18. [6] Buchanan, J. M.: The Constitution of Economic Policy, in: American Economic Review 77 (1987), 243-250.
    [Show full text]
  • Breaking the Mould: an Institutionalist Political Economy Alternative to the Neoliberal Theory of the Market and the State Ha-Joon Chang, May 2001
    Breaking the Mould An Institutionalist Political Economy Alternative to the Neoliberal Theory of the Market and the State Ha-Joon Chang Social Policy and Development United Nations Programme Paper Number 6 Research Institute May 2001 for Social Development The United Nations Research Institute for Social Development (UNRISD) thanks the governments of Denmark, Finland, Mexico, the Netherlands, Norway, Sweden, Switzerland and the United Kingdom for their core funding. Copyright © UNRISD. Short extracts from this publication may be reproduced unaltered without authorization on condition that the source is indicated. For rights of reproduction or translation, application should be made to UNRISD, Palais des Nations, 1211 Geneva 10, Switzerland. UNRISD welcomes such applications. The designations employed in UNRISD publications, which are in conformity with United Nations practice, and the presentation of material therein do not imply the expression of any opinion whatsoever on the part of UNRISD con- cerning the legal status of any country, territory, city or area or of its authorities, or concerning the delimitation of its frontiers or boundaries. The responsibility for opinions expressed rests solely with the author(s), and publication does not constitute endorse- ment by UNRISD. ISSN 1020-8208 Contents Acronyms ii Acknowledgements ii Summary/Résumé/Resumen iii Summary iii Résumé iv Resumen v 1. Introduction 1 2. The Evolution of the Debate: From “Golden Age Economics” to Neoliberalism 1 3. The Limits of Neoliberal Analysis of the Role of the State 3 3.1 Defining the free market (and state intervention) 4 3.2 Defining market failure 6 3.3 The market primacy assumption 8 3.4 Market, state and politics 11 4.
    [Show full text]
  • The Role of Private Property Rights and Ethics in the Market Economy
    UNLV Retrospective Theses & Dissertations 1-1-1994 In defense of private property: The role of private property rights and ethics in the market economy Iftikhar Ahmed University of Nevada, Las Vegas Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalscholarship.unlv.edu/rtds Repository Citation Ahmed, Iftikhar, "In defense of private property: The role of private property rights and ethics in the market economy" (1994). UNLV Retrospective Theses & Dissertations. 371. http://dx.doi.org/10.25669/cpxp-v4in This Thesis is protected by copyright and/or related rights. It has been brought to you by Digital Scholarship@UNLV with permission from the rights-holder(s). You are free to use this Thesis in any way that is permitted by the copyright and related rights legislation that applies to your use. For other uses you need to obtain permission from the rights-holder(s) directly, unless additional rights are indicated by a Creative Commons license in the record and/ or on the work itself. This Thesis has been accepted for inclusion in UNLV Retrospective Theses & Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Digital Scholarship@UNLV. For more information, please contact [email protected]. INFORMATION TO USERS This manuscript has been reproduced from the microfilm master. UMI films the text directly from the original or copy submitted. Thus, some thesis and dissertation copies are in typewriter face, while others may be from any type of computer printer. The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. Broken or indistinct print, colored or poor quality illustrations and photographs, print bleedthrough, substandard margins, and improper alignment can adversely afreet reproduction.
    [Show full text]