Countable Sets, Unions and Prodcuts

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Countable Sets, Unions and Prodcuts These are theorems that I proved in class that, I think, cover the material in Section 5.3 much more efficiently. These theorems immediately imply Theorem 5.17-5.29 in the textbook. Theorem 1 If EßE¶Þ is an infinite subset of then Proof Since EÁgßand E© ßthe Well-Ordering Principle says there is a smallest member +−E" . Since Eis not finite ß E Ö+"# × Á gÞ Let +be the smallest member of E Ö+ " × Since E is not finite, we can always continue this process another step. We inductively define +8" to be the smallest member of EÖ+ " ß ÞÞÞß + 8 ×. The sequence +"# ß + ß ÞÞÞß + 8 ß ÞÞÞcontains every member of E (why? ), and the mapping 0 À E Ä defined by 0Ð+8 Ñ œ 8 is one-to-one and onto . Therefore E ¶ Þ ñ Corollary 2 A set E0ÀEÄ is countable iff there exists a one-to-one function (not necessarily onto!) Proof If such a function exists, then E¶range Ð0Ñ© . Therefore Eis finite or, by Theorem 1, E¶. Therefore E is countable. If EE is countable, then is either finite or denumerable so either there is a one-to-one function 0ÀEÄ5 © or there is a bijection 0ÀEÄ Þ Either way, we have a one-to-one function from EE to so is countable. ñ Corollary 3 A subset of a countable set is countable. Proof Suppose F©E where E is countable. By Corollary 2, there is a one-to-one function 0ÀEÄ Þ Then 1œ0lF is a one-to-one function from Finto so F is countable. Theorem 4 If EF and are countable, then E‚F is countable. Proof By assumption, there exist one-to-one functions 0ÀEÄ and 1ÀFÄ . For each ordered pair Ð+ß ,Ñ − E ‚ F, define 2Ð+ß ,Ñ œ #0Ð+Ñ $ 1Ð,Ñ − Þ Then 2 À E ‚ F Ä Þ (Example: if, say, 0Ð+Ñ œ #( and 1Ð,Ñ œ ""$ , then 2ÐÐ+ß ,ÑÑ œ ##( $ ""$ ÞÑ We claim that 2 is one-to-one: Suppose Ð+ß,ÑÁÐ-ß.Ñ−E‚F. Then either +Á- or ,Á.Þ If +Á-, then 0Ð+ÑÁ0Ð-Ñ since 0 is one-to-one. So #0Ð+Ñ $ 1Ð,Ñ Á# 0Ð-Ñ $ 1Ð.Ñ by the Fundamental Theorem of Arithmetic. If ,Á., then 1Ð,ÑÁ1Ð.Ñ since 1 is one-to-one. So #0Ð+Ñ $ 1Ð,Ñ Á# 0Ð-Ñ $ 1Ð.Ñ Either way, 2Ð+ß ,Ñ Á 2Ð-ß .Ñ, so 2 is one-to-one. Therefore, by Corollary 2, E‚F is countable. ñ Note: If EFG, , are countable then E‚F is countable so, by Theorem 4, ÐE‚FÑ‚G is also countable. But ÐE‚FÑ‚G ¶E‚F‚G, so E‚F‚G is countable. Continuing in this way, we can prove by induction that a product of finitely many countable sets is countable.) Theorem 5 Suppose, for each , that is countable. Then _ is countable. 8− E88-8œ" E (The union of a countable collection ÖE"8 ß ÞÞÞß E ß ÞÞÞ× of countable sets is countable.) Proof To show _ is countable, it is sufficient, by to produce a one-to-one map -8œ"E8 : _ (by Corollary 2). 0EÄ-8œ" 8 1) We begin by showing that we can find pairwise disjoint countable sets F8 such that __ (Then we will just need to show that _ is countable.) --8œ"Fœ88 8œ" EÞ - 8œ" F 8 Define FœE"" FœEE##" FœEÐEEÑ$$ "# ã F88 œ E ÐE " ÞÞÞ E 8" Ñ ã To see that the F8's are pairwise disjoint: Consider FF78 and where, say, 78Þ=−F If 7 œ E7" ÐE ÞÞÞ E 7" Ñ, then B − E 7. But that implies B  F88 œ E ÐE " ÞÞÞ E 7 ÞÞÞ E 8"78 ÑÞ So F F œ gÞ To see that __ : --8œ"Fœ88 8œ" E Since , certainly we have __. F©E88--8œ" F© 8 8œ" E 8 Conversely, if _ , then is in at least one of the 's. Pick B−-8œ" E88 B E the smallest 8B−EB−FB!8Þ8 such that !! Then because is not in E"8" ÞÞÞ E! , the set “discarded” in the definition of F 8! . Therefore ___, so . B−---8œ" F888 8œ" F œ 8œ" E 2) Since each FE88 is a subset of a countable set , Corollary 3 tells us that each F 8 is countable. We want to show that _ is countable. -8œ"F8 There is a one-to-one function 0ÀFÄ88, for each 8 (since F 8is countable). List the prime numbers as :"#$ œ #ß : œ $ß : œ &ß ÞÞÞß : 8 ß ÞÞÞÞ Define _ as follows:if , then 08ÐBÑ 0À-8œ" F88 Ä B−F 0ÐBÑœ:8 − For example, if B−F$$$, then 0 ÀF Ä and 0ÐBÑ $ is some natural 0ÐBÑ$ numberÞ Suppose, to illustrate, that 0$ ÐBÑ œ '%ÞThen 0ÐBÑ œ :$ '% '% œ:$ œ& . Notice that for each _ , there is exactly one for which B−-8œ"F8 8 B−F88 because the F 's are pairwise disjoint. This means there's no ambiguity in how 0 is being defined. We claim that is one-to-one. Suppose _ and 0BßC−FBÁCÞ-8œ" 8 i) if B−F87 and C−F, where 7Á8, then 0ÐBÑ87 0 ÐCÑ 0ÐBÑœ:87 Á: œ0ÐCÑ because :87 Á: 0ÐBÑ8 Fundamental Theorem of Arithmetic: :8 can't be factored as a product of :7's. ii) if BC and are both in the same F88, then 0ÐBÑÁ0ÐCÑ 8 because the function 0ÀFÄ88 is one-to-one. Therefore 0ÐBÑ88 0ÐCÑ 0ÐBÑœ:88 Á: œ0ÐCÑ 0ÐBÑ88 0ÐCÑ Fundamental Theorem of Arithmetic again: ::88 and have different numbers of :8's in their prime factorizations, so they can't be equal. Therefore 2 is one-to-one. Therefore _ is countable. -8œ"Fñ8 Corollary 6 A union of a finite number of countable sets is countable. (In particular, the union of two countable sets is countable.) (This corollary is just a minor “fussy” step from Theorem 5. The way Theorem 5 is stated, it applies to an infinite collection of countable sets E"8 ß ÞÞÞß E ß ÞÞÞ If we have only finitely many, we artificially create the others using g. ) Proof Suppose E"# ß E ß ÞÞÞß E 5 are countable sets. In order to apply Theorem 5, we define EœEœEÞÞÞœgÞ5" 5# 5$ Then _ , which is countable. E"5"5 ÞÞÞE œE ÞÞÞE ggÞÞÞœ-8œ" E 8 ñ Examples i) We proved earlier that the set of positive rationals is countable. The set of negative rationals is countable since ¶ Ðusing, for example, the function 0ÐBÑ œ BÑÞ The finite set Ö!× is countable. Therefore œ Ö!× is countable, by Corollary 6. ii) If F©E, and F is uncountable, then Emust be uncountable. ÐIf E were countable, then Corollary 3 would say that FÑmust be countable. For example, ‘‘ is uncountable because Ð!ß "Ñ © (in fact, we already knew ‘ is uncountable we proved ‘ ¶ Ð!ß "ÑÞ ‘‘‚ Ö!× ‚ Ö!× is uncountable (it's clearly equivalent to ‘ ), and ‚ Ö!× ‚ Ö!× © ‘‘$$. Therefore is uncountable. A similar argument shows that ‘8 is uncountable for any integer 8"Þ iii) Let ‘ be the set of irrational numbers. If were countable, then œ would be countable (by Corollary 6). Therefore is uncountable so there are “more” irrational numbers than there are rational numbers !! iv) A harder example: suppose E œ Ö+"# ß + ß ÞÞÞ , + 8 ß ÞÞÞ × © ‘% and let be an arbitrary % positive number. Let M+88 denote the open interval centered at with length #8" , that is M œ Ð+ %% ß + Ñ . Then E ©_ M (because each + is in the corresponding M Ñà 88##8# 8 8# -8œ" 8 8 8 but the total length of all the intervals M is _ % %. 8 !8œ" #8" This says, informally, that any countable subset of ‘ can be “covered” by a countable collection of open intervals whose total length is %%, where the positive number can be chosen as small as you like. So for a dramatic and counterintuitive example you can cover the set of all rational numbers with a countable collection of open intervals whose total length is "!"! xx.
Recommended publications
  • Axiomatic Set Teory P.D.Welch
    Axiomatic Set Teory P.D.Welch. August 16, 2020 Contents Page 1 Axioms and Formal Systems 1 1.1 Introduction 1 1.2 Preliminaries: axioms and formal systems. 3 1.2.1 The formal language of ZF set theory; terms 4 1.2.2 The Zermelo-Fraenkel Axioms 7 1.3 Transfinite Recursion 9 1.4 Relativisation of terms and formulae 11 2 Initial segments of the Universe 17 2.1 Singular ordinals: cofinality 17 2.1.1 Cofinality 17 2.1.2 Normal Functions and closed and unbounded classes 19 2.1.3 Stationary Sets 22 2.2 Some further cardinal arithmetic 24 2.3 Transitive Models 25 2.4 The H sets 27 2.4.1 H - the hereditarily finite sets 28 2.4.2 H - the hereditarily countable sets 29 2.5 The Montague-Levy Reflection theorem 30 2.5.1 Absoluteness 30 2.5.2 Reflection Theorems 32 2.6 Inaccessible Cardinals 34 2.6.1 Inaccessible cardinals 35 2.6.2 A menagerie of other large cardinals 36 3 Formalising semantics within ZF 39 3.1 Definite terms and formulae 39 3.1.1 The non-finite axiomatisability of ZF 44 3.2 Formalising syntax 45 3.3 Formalising the satisfaction relation 46 3.4 Formalising definability: the function Def. 47 3.5 More on correctness and consistency 48 ii iii 3.5.1 Incompleteness and Consistency Arguments 50 4 The Constructible Hierarchy 53 4.1 The L -hierarchy 53 4.2 The Axiom of Choice in L 56 4.3 The Axiom of Constructibility 57 4.4 The Generalised Continuum Hypothesis in L.
    [Show full text]
  • 17 Axiom of Choice
    Math 361 Axiom of Choice 17 Axiom of Choice De¯nition 17.1. Let be a nonempty set of nonempty sets. Then a choice function for is a function f sucFh that f(S) S for all S . F 2 2 F Example 17.2. Let = (N)r . Then we can de¯ne a choice function f by F P f;g f(S) = the least element of S: Example 17.3. Let = (Z)r . Then we can de¯ne a choice function f by F P f;g f(S) = ²n where n = min z z S and, if n = 0, ² = min z= z z = n; z S . fj j j 2 g 6 f j j j j j 2 g Example 17.4. Let = (Q)r . Then we can de¯ne a choice function f as follows. F P f;g Let g : Q N be an injection. Then ! f(S) = q where g(q) = min g(r) r S . f j 2 g Example 17.5. Let = (R)r . Then it is impossible to explicitly de¯ne a choice function for . F P f;g F Axiom 17.6 (Axiom of Choice (AC)). For every set of nonempty sets, there exists a function f such that f(S) S for all S . F 2 2 F We say that f is a choice function for . F Theorem 17.7 (AC). If A; B are non-empty sets, then the following are equivalent: (a) A B ¹ (b) There exists a surjection g : B A. ! Proof. (a) (b) Suppose that A B.
    [Show full text]
  • Worksheet: Cardinality, Countable and Uncountable Sets
    Math 347 Worksheet: Cardinality A.J. Hildebrand Worksheet: Cardinality, Countable and Uncountable Sets • Key Tool: Bijections. • Definition: Let A and B be sets. A bijection from A to B is a function f : A ! B that is both injective and surjective. • Properties of bijections: ∗ Compositions: The composition of bijections is a bijection. ∗ Inverse functions: The inverse function of a bijection is a bijection. ∗ Symmetry: The \bijection" relation is symmetric: If there is a bijection f from A to B, then there is also a bijection g from B to A, given by the inverse of f. • Key Definitions. • Cardinality: Two sets A and B are said to have the same cardinality if there exists a bijection from A to B. • Finite sets: A set is called finite if it is empty or has the same cardinality as the set f1; 2; : : : ; ng for some n 2 N; it is called infinite otherwise. • Countable sets: A set A is called countable (or countably infinite) if it has the same cardinality as N, i.e., if there exists a bijection between A and N. Equivalently, a set A is countable if it can be enumerated in a sequence, i.e., if all of its elements can be listed as an infinite sequence a1; a2;::: . NOTE: The above definition of \countable" is the one given in the text, and it is reserved for infinite sets. Thus finite sets are not countable according to this definition. • Uncountable sets: A set is called uncountable if it is infinite and not countable. • Two famous results with memorable proofs.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Necessary Use of Abstract Set Theory
    ADVANCES IN MATHEMATICS 41, 209-280 (1981) On the Necessary Use of Abstract Set Theory HARVEY FRIEDMAN* Department of Mathematics, Ohio State University, Columbus, Ohio 43210 In this paper we present some independence results from the Zermelo-Frankel axioms of set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC) which differ from earlier such independence results in three major respects. Firstly, these new propositions that are shown to be independent of ZFC (i.e., neither provable nor refutable from ZFC) form mathematically natural assertions about Bore1 functions of several variables from the Hilbert cube I” into the unit interval, or back into the Hilbert cube. As such, they are of a level of abstraction significantly below that of the earlier independence results. Secondly, these propositions are not only independent of ZFC, but also of ZFC together with the axiom of constructibility (V = L). The only earlier examples of intelligible statements independent of ZFC + V= L either express properties of formal systems such as ZFC (e.g., the consistency of ZFC), or assert the existence of very large cardinalities (e.g., inaccessible cardinals). The great bulk of independence results from ZFCLthe ones that involve standard mathematical concepts and constructions-are about sets of limited cardinality (most commonly, that of at most the continuum), and are obtained using the forcing method introduced by Paul J. Cohen (see [2]). It is now known in virtually every such case, that these independence results are eliminated if V= L is added to ZFC. Finally, some of our propositions can be proved in the theory of classes, as formalized by the Morse-Kelley class theory with the axiom of choice for sets (MKC), but not in ZFC.
    [Show full text]
  • SET THEORY Andrea K. Dieterly a Thesis Submitted to the Graduate
    SET THEORY Andrea K. Dieterly A Thesis Submitted to the Graduate College of Bowling Green State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS August 2011 Committee: Warren Wm. McGovern, Advisor Juan Bes Rieuwert Blok i Abstract Warren Wm. McGovern, Advisor This manuscript was to show the equivalency of the Axiom of Choice, Zorn's Lemma and Zermelo's Well-Ordering Principle. Starting with a brief history of the development of set history, this work introduced the Axioms of Zermelo-Fraenkel, common applications of the axioms, and set theoretic descriptions of sets of numbers. The book, Introduction to Set Theory, by Karel Hrbacek and Thomas Jech was the primary resource with other sources providing additional background information. ii Acknowledgements I would like to thank Warren Wm. McGovern for his assistance and guidance while working and writing this thesis. I also want to thank Reiuwert Blok and Juan Bes for being on my committee. Thank you to Dan Shifflet and Nate Iverson for help with the typesetting program LATEX. A personal thank you to my husband, Don, for his love and support. iii Contents Contents . iii 1 Introduction 1 1.1 Naive Set Theory . 2 1.2 The Axiom of Choice . 4 1.3 Russell's Paradox . 5 2 Axioms of Zermelo-Fraenkel 7 2.1 First Order Logic . 7 2.2 The Axioms of Zermelo-Fraenkel . 8 2.3 The Recursive Theorem . 13 3 Development of Numbers 16 3.1 Natural Numbers and Integers . 16 3.2 Rational Numbers . 20 3.3 Real Numbers .
    [Show full text]
  • CSE541 CARDINALITIES of SETS BASIC DEFINITIONS and FACTS Cardinality Definition Sets a and B Have the Same Cardinality Iff ∃F
    CSE541 CARDINALITIES OF SETS BASIC DEFINITIONS AND FACTS 1¡1;onto Cardinality de¯nition Sets A and B have the same cardinality i® 9f( f : A ¡! B): Cardinality notations If sets A and B have the same cardinality we denote it as: jAj = jBj or cardA = cardB, or A » B. We aslo say that A and B are equipotent. Cardinality We put the above notations together in one de¯nition: 1¡1;onto jAj = jBj or cardA = cardB, or A » B i® 9f( f : A ¡! B): 1¡1;onto Finite A set A is ¯nite i® 9n 2 N 9f (f : f0; 1; 2; :::; n ¡ 1g ¡! A), i.e. we say: a set A is ¯nite i® 9n 2 N(jAj = n). In¯nite A set A is in¯nite i® A is NOT ¯nite. Cardinality Aleph zero @0 (Aleph zero) is a cardinality of N (Natural numbers). A set A has a cardinality @0 (jAj = @0) i® A » N, (or jAj = jNj, or cardA = cardN). Countable A set A is countable i® A is ¯nite or jAj = @0. In¯nitely countable A set A is in¯nitely countable i® jAj = @0. Uncountable A set A is uncountable i® A is NOT countable, Fact A set A is uncountable i® A is in¯nite and jAj 6= @0. Cardinality Continuum C (Continuum ) is a cardinality of Real Numbers, i.e. C = jRj. Sets of cardinality continuum. A set A has a cardinality C, jAj = C i® jAj = jRj, or cardA = cardR). Cardinality A · Cardinality B jAj · jBj i® A » C and C ⊆ B.
    [Show full text]
  • The Axiom of Determinacy
    Virginia Commonwealth University VCU Scholars Compass Theses and Dissertations Graduate School 2010 The Axiom of Determinacy Samantha Stanton Virginia Commonwealth University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarscompass.vcu.edu/etd Part of the Physical Sciences and Mathematics Commons © The Author Downloaded from https://scholarscompass.vcu.edu/etd/2189 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at VCU Scholars Compass. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of VCU Scholars Compass. For more information, please contact [email protected]. College of Humanities and Sciences Virginia Commonwealth University This is to certify that the thesis prepared by Samantha Stanton titled “The Axiom of Determinacy” has been approved by his or her committee as satisfactory completion of the thesis requirement for the degree of Master of Science. Dr. Andrew Lewis, College of Humanities and Sciences Dr. Lon Mitchell, College of Humanities and Sciences Dr. Robert Gowdy, College of Humanities and Sciences Dr. John Berglund, Graduate Chair, Mathematics and Applied Mathematics Dr. Robert Holsworth, Dean, College of Humanities and Sciences Dr. F. Douglas Boudinot, Graduate Dean Date © Samantha Stanton 2010 All Rights Reserved The Axiom of Determinacy A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Science at Virginia Commonwealth University. by Samantha Stanton Master of Science Director: Dr. Andrew Lewis, Associate Professor, Department Chair Department of Mathematics and Applied Mathematics Virginia Commonwealth University Richmond, Virginia May 2010 ii Acknowledgment I am most appreciative of Dr. Andrew Lewis. I would like to thank him for his support, patience, and understanding through this entire process.
    [Show full text]
  • Countable by Enumeration Real Numbers.. the Reals
    Today. Countable. Examples Countably infinite (same cardinality as naturals) I Z + - positive integers Definition: S is countable if there is a bijection between S and some Where’s 0? subset of N. Bijection: f (z) = z 1. − I Finish Countability. If the subset of N is finite, S has finite cardinality. (Where’s 0? 1 Where’s 1? 2 ...) If the subset of N is infinite, S is countably infinite. I ..or uncountaility. I E even numbers. Bijection to or from natural numbers implies countably infinite. Where are the odds? Half as big? I Undecidability. Bijection: f (e) = e/2. Enumerable means countable. I Z- all integers. Subset of countable set is countable. Twice as big? All countably infinite sets are the same cardinality as each other. Bijection: f (z) = 2 z sign(z). | | − Enumerate: 0, 1,1, 2,2... − − Where sign(z) = 1 if z > 0 and sign(z) = 0 otherwise. Examples: Countable by enumeration Real numbers.. The reals. I N N - Pairs of integers. × Square of countably infinite? Enumerate: (0,0),(0,1),(0,2),... ??? Are the set of reals countable? ( , ) Never get to 1 1 ! Lets consider the reals [0,1]. Enumerate: (0,0),(1,0),(0,1),(2,0),(1,1),(0,2)... (a,b) at position (a + b + 1)(a + b)/2 + b in this order. Real numbers are same size as integers? Each real has a decimal representation. .500000000... (1/2) I Positive Rational numbers. .785398162... π/4 Infinite Subset of pairs of natural numbers. .367879441... 1/e Countably infinite. .632120558... 1 1/e − I All rational numbers.
    [Show full text]
  • 2.3 Infinite Sets and Cardinality
    2.3 Infinite sets and cardinality Recall from the last section that The cardinality of afinite set is defined as the number of elements in it. • Two setsA andB have the same cardinality if (and only if) it is possible to match each ele- • ment ofA to an element ofB in such a way that every element of each set has exactly one “partner” in the other set. Such a matching is called a bijective correpondence or one-to-one correspondence. A bijective correspondence betweenA andB may be expressed as a function fromA toB that assigns different elements ofB to all the elements ofA and “uses” all the elements ofB. A function that has these properties is called a bijection. In the case offinite sets, the second point above might seem to be overcomplicating the issue, since we can tell if twofinite sets have the same cardinality by just counting their elements and noting that they have the same number. The notion of bijective correspondence is emphasized for two reasons. First, as we saw in Example 2.2.9, it is occasionally possible to establish that twofinite sets are in bijective correspondence without knowing the cardinality of either of them. More importantly, we would like to develop some notion of cardinality for infinite sets aswell. We can’t count the number of elements in an infinite set. However, for a given pair of infinite sets, we could possibly show that it is or isn’t possible to construct a bijective correspondence between them. Definition 2.3.1. Suppose thatA andB are sets (finite or infinite).
    [Show full text]
  • Unions and the Axiom of Choice
    Unions and the Axiom of Choice Omar De la Cruz Eric J. Hall Paul Howard Kyriakos Keremedis Jean E. Rubin September 9, 2007 Abstract We study statements about countable and well ordered unions and how they are related to each other and to countable and well ordered forms of the axiom of choice. 1 Introduction and Definitions In this paper we study the relationships between statements about countable and well ordered unions and the axiom of choice for families of countable and well ordered sets. All proofs, unless otherwise stated, are in ZF, Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory without AC (the axiom of choice). In [14, p 158 ff], several theorems about unions are given which are equivalent to AC. S S AC1 :(∀x)[ x ≺ n∈ω An → (∃m ∈ ω)(x n≤m An)] [ Y AC2 : For any index set J,(∀j ∈ J, Aj ≺ Bj) → Aj ≺ Bj. j∈J j∈J [ Y AC3 : For any index set J,(∀j ∈ J, 2 Aj) → Aj Aj. j∈J j∈J The union theorems in this paper are weaker than AC. Some abbreviations will be used repeatedly for statements which are consequences of AC, as illustrated by the following examples. UT is a union theorem, PUT is a partial union theorem, C is a statement asserting the existence of choice functions, and PC is a partial choice theorem: • UT(ℵ0, < ℵ0, WO): The union of a countable number of finite sets can be well ordered. • UT(ℵ0, ℵ0, cuf): Every countable union of countable sets is cuf —that is, a countable union of finite sets.
    [Show full text]
  • Countable and Uncountable Sets
    Sets Alvin Lin Discrete Math for Computing: January 2017 - May 2017 Countable and Uncountable Sets Recall for a set S, jSj is the cardinality of S, If S has a finite number of objects, then jSj 2 N. Consider the following six sets: • E is the set of positive even numbers less than or equal to 100. • Z is the set of all integers. • U is the set of all real numbers between 0 and 1. • P is the set of all prime numbers less than or equal to 50. • Q is the set of all rational numbers. • R is the set of all real numbers. Both E and P are finite sets with jEj = 50 and jP j = 15. The remaining four sets are all infinite. If f : A ! B is 1-1, then jAj ≤ jBj. Recall from functions that f is 1-1 if every output is uniquely associated to 1 input. Also, for real-valued functions, f is 1-1 if it passed the horizontal line test. If A ⊆ B, then jAj ≤ jBj by using f(x) = x where f : A ! B. Schr¨oder-BernsteinTheorem If f : A ! B is 1-1 and g : B ! A is 1-1, then jAj = jBj. Using the above example, −1 π tan (x)+ 2 jUj = jRj since f(x) = π where f : R ! U is 1-1 and g(x) = x where g : U ! R is 1-1. 1 Countably Infinite Sets Set A is countably infinite if jAj = jZ+j. Equivalently, there are 1-1 functions f; g such that f : A ! Z+ and g : Z+ ! A.
    [Show full text]
  • Countable and Uncountable Sets
    Section 2.5 Cardinality (another) Definition: The cardinality of a set A is equal to the cardinality of a set B, denoted |A| = |B|, if and only if there is a bijection from A to B. If there is an injection from A to B, the cardinality of A is less than or the same as the cardinality of B and we write |A| ≤ |B|. Cardinality Definition: A set that is either finite or has the same cardinality as the set of positive integers (Z+) is called countable. A set that is not countable is uncountable. The set of all finite strings over the alphabet of lowercase letters is countable. The set of real numbers R is an uncountable set. Showing that a Set is Countable An infinite set is countable if and only if it is possible to list the elements of the set in a sequence (indexed by the positive integers). The reason for this is that a bijection f from the set of positive integers to a set S can be expressed in terms of a sequence a1,a2,…, an ,… where a1 = f(1), a2 = f(2),…, an = f(n),… Showing that a Set is Countable Example 1: Show that the set of positive even integers is countable set. Proof: Let E be the set of even integers and f(x) = 2x be a function from N to E. 1 2 3 4 5 6 ….. 2 4 6 8 10 12 …… Then f is a bijection from N to E since f is both one‐to‐one and onto.
    [Show full text]