Linnebo-Philosophy of Mathematics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Linnebo-Philosophy of Mathematics Philosophy of Mathematics Copyright c 2017 by Princeton University Press Published by Princeton University Press, 41 William Street, Princeton, New Jersey 08540 In the United Kingdom: Princeton University Press, 6 Oxford Street, Woodstock, Oxfordshire OX20 1TR press.princeton.edu All Rights Reserved ISBN 978-0-691-16140-2 British Library Cataloging-in-Publication Data is available This book has been composed in Minion Pro and Archer Printed on acid-free paper. ∞ Typeset by Nova Techset Pvt Ltd, Bangalore, India Printed in the United States of America 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Contents Acknowledgments vii Introduction 1 CHAPTER ONE Mathematics as a Philosophical Challenge 4 CHAPTER TWO Frege’s Logicism 21 CHAPTER THREE Formalism and Deductivism 38 CHAPTER FOUR Hilbert’s Program 56 CHAPTER FIVE Intuitionism 73 CHAPTER SIX Empiricism about Mathematics 88 CHAPTER SEVEN Nominalism 101 CHAPTER EIGHT Mathematical Intuition 116 CHAPTER NINE Abstraction Reconsidered 126 CHAPTER TEN The Iterative Conception of Sets 139 CHAPTER ELEVEN Structuralism 154 CHAPTER TWELVE The Quest for New Axioms 170 Contents Concluding Remarks 183 Bibliography 189 Index 199 vi Acknowledgments I am grateful to many people for discussion of material covered in this book or comments on earlier drafts, in particular Solveig Aasen, Jens Erik Fenstad, Dagfinn Føllesdal, Peter Fritz, Leila Haaparanta, Bob Hale, Mirja Hartimo, Richard Heck, Leon Horsten, Toni Kannisto, Frode Kjosavik, Charles Parsons, Agustín Rayo, Stewart Shapiro, Wilfried Sieg, Hans Robin Solberg, James Studd, Mark van Atten, Crispin Wright, and two anonymous referees. The book has been shaped by courses on the philosophy of mathematics that I taught at the universities of Bristol, London, and Oslo. Thanks to all of my students for their reactions and feedback, which were of great help when designing and eventually writing the book. Most of the writing took place during a period of research leave at the Center for Advanced Study, Oslo, whose support I gratefully acknowledge. Philosophy of Mathematics Introduction MATHEMATICS RAISES A WEALTH of philosophical questions, which have occupied some of the greatest thinkers in his- tory. So when writing this book, some hard choices had to be made. Let me begin with the aim of the book. Its target audience are advanced undergraduates and graduate students in philosophy, but also mathematicians and others interested in the foundations of one of the most successful, but also most puzzling, human endeavors. For the most part, the book does not presuppose much mathematics. Knowledge of elementary logic, the number systems from the natural numbers up through the reals, and some basic ideas from the calculus will be plenty for all except two late chapters devoted to set theory. While some familiarity with the philosophical mode of thinking will be a clear ad- vantage, I have attempted to explain all relevant philosophical concepts. I make no attempt to hide my own views concerning what is important and what works. Accordingly, my discussion has some general themes that serve to distinguish it from other introductions to the subject. First, Frege figures prominently in the book, both through his own views and his criticism of other thinkers. While my views often differ from Frege’s, I share his fundamental conviction that mathematics is an autonomous science. Like other sciences, mathematics uses a meaningful lan- guage to express truths, ever more of which are discovered. Yet mathematics differs profoundly from the paradigmatic empirical sciences concerning the nature of its subject matter and the methods it employs. Following Frege, I am critical of any kind of formalism or fictionalism that deprives mathematics of its status as a body of truths, and of any attempt to assimilate mathematics to the empirical sciences. Frege famously defended the objectivity of mathematics. Just as geographers discover continents and oceans, so mathematicians explore numbers and sets. The two Introduction kinds of object are equally “real” and are described by equally objective truths. A second theme of the book is how to understand the objects (such as numbers and sets) that mathematics explores. I pay more attention than is customary to the question of whether mathematical objects can be accepted without fully embracing a so-called platonistic conception of them. So I discuss some less demanding conceptions of mathematical objects. Might these objects be explicable in terms of a network of objective mathe- matical truths? Or might they be constructed by us? Or might they exist only potentially, not actually? A final theme concerns mathematical knowledge. This knowl- edge must be explained in a way that links up with the subject matter of mathematics. It is not just an accident that our math- ematical beliefs tend to be true. We would like to know why. What is it about our ways of forming mathematical beliefs which ensures that most of the beliefs correctly represent their subject matter? The answer must draw on an account of mathematical evidence. So what evidence do we have for our mathematical beliefs? A variety of answers have been proposed. Perhaps the evidence is logical or conceptual, or broadly perceptual in character, or of some indirect form that flows from mathematical principles’ ability to explain and systematize knowledge already established. My approach to the question of mathematical ev- idence will be pluralist and gradualist. That is, one form of evidence need not exclude another. And evidence may come in degrees, such that the elementary parts of mathematics enjoy a higher degree of evidence than the more advanced parts, especially those of a highly set-theoretic character. Space considerations have forced me to downplay some issues to make room for a proper discussion of the themes just described. There is no systematic discussion of the philosophy of mathematics before Frege’s pioneering works of the 1880s and 1890s. I give only the briefest of introductions to Plato’s and Kant’s views on the subject. Traditional geometry receives little attention. Other important topics receive none. Examples in- clude Wittgenstein on mathematics, explanation in mathematics, 2 the philosophy of mathematical practice, the use of experimental Introduction and other nontraditional methods in mathematics, and new developments such as homotopy type theory.1 The first seven chapters cover topics that tend to be included in any good course in the philosophy of mathematics. The last five chapters discuss more recent developments. These chapters are more specialized and somewhat more demanding, both mathematically and philosophically, but are largely independent of one another (except for Chapter 12, which depends on Chapter 10). 1 Useful introductions to these topics can be found in Rodych (2011), Mancosu (2015, 2008), Baker (2015), and Awodey (2014), respectively. 3 CHAPTER ONE Mathematics as a Philosophical Challenge 1.1 PROBLEMATIC PLATONISM Mathematics poses a daunting philosophical challenge, which has been with us ever since the beginning of Western philosophy. To see why, imagine a community that claims to possess a wonderful kind of knowledge resulting from some discipline practiced there. Community members claim that this knowledge has three distinctive characteristics. First, it is apriori,inthe sense that it doesn’t rely on sense experience or on experimen- tation. Truths are arrived at by reflection alone, without any sensory observation. Second, the knowledge is concerned with truths that are necessary, in the sense that things could not have been otherwise. It is therefore safe to appeal to these truths when reasoning not only about how the world actually is but also when reasoning about how it would have been had things been otherwise. Third, the knowledge is concerned with objects that are not located in space or time, and that don’t participate in causal relationships. Such objects are said to be abstract. In fact, the knowledge that our imagined community claims to posses is rather like the knowledge promised by rational metaphysics, which for centuries professed to deliver insights into the ultimate nature of reality and ourselves, based solely on reason and without any reliance on sense experience. Many people today would dismiss such knowledge claims as incredible. And in fact, science and philosophy have developed in ways that now allow this dismissal to proceed fairly smoothly. The philosophical challenge posed by mathematics is this. Mathematics seems to deliver knowledge with the three distinctive characteristics that are claimed by our imagined community. “The queen of the sciences”—as Gauss famously called mathematics, usurping a title previously reserved for Mathematics as a Philosophical Challenge rational metaphysics—seems to be practiced by means of reflec- tion and proof alone, without any reliance on sense experience or experimentation; and it seems to deliver knowledge of necessary truths that are concerned with abstract things such as numbers, sets, and functions. But in stark contrast to rational metaphysics, mathematics is a paradigm of a solid and successful science. In short, by being so different from the ordinary empirical sciences, mathematics is philosophically puzzling; but simultaneously, it is rock solid. This challenge obviously requires closer examination. Let us begin with mathematics’ strong credentials, before we return, in the sections that follow, to its three apparent characteris- tics. Mathematics is an extremely successful science, both in its own right and as a tool for the empirical sciences. There is (at least today) widespread agreement among mathematicians about the guiding problems of their field and about the kinds of methods that are permissible when attempting to solve these problems. By using these methods, mathematicians have made, and continue to make, great progress toward solving these guid- ing problems. Moreover, mathematics plays a pivotal role in many of the empirical sciences. The clearest example is physics, which would be unimaginable without the conceptual resources offered by modern mathematics; but other sciences too, such as biology and economics, are becoming increasingly dependent on mathematics.
Recommended publications
  • On Mathematical Problem Posing*
    On Mathematical Problem Posing* EDWARD A. SILVER In mathematics classes at all levels of schooling in all itself an exercise in exploring, conjecturing, examining, and countries of the world, students can be observed solving testing-all aspects of problem solving .. 1 asks should be problems .. The quality and authenticity of these mathemat­ created and presented that are accessible to students and ics problems has been the subject of many discussions and ~xtend their knowledge of mathematics and problem solv­ debates in recent years. Much of this attention has resulted ing. Students should be given opportunities to formulate in a rich, more diverse collection of problems being incor­ problems from given situations and create new problems by porated into school mathematics curricula. Although the modifying the conditions of a given problem [NCIM, problems themselves have received much scrutiny, less 1991, p. 95] attention has been paid to diversifying the sources for the Despite this interest, however, there is no coherent, com­ problems that students are asked to consider in school Stu­ prehensive account of problem posing as a prut of mathe­ dents are almost always asked to solve only the problems matics curriculum and instruction nor has there been sys­ that have been presented by a teacher or a textbook Stu­ tematic research on mathematical problem posing [Kil­ dents are rarely, if ever, given opportunities to pose in patrick, 1987] For the past several years, I have been some public way their own mathematics problems. Tradi­ working with colleagues and students on a number of tional transmission/reception models of mathematics investigations into various aspects of problem posing .
    [Show full text]
  • Ludwig.Wittgenstein.-.Philosophical.Investigations.Pdf
    PHILOSOPHICAL INVESTIGATIONS By LUDWIG WITTGENSTEIN Translated by G. E. M. ANSCOMBE BASIL BLACKWELL TRANSLATOR'S NOTE Copyright © Basil Blackwell Ltd 1958 MY acknowledgments are due to the following, who either checked First published 1953 Second edition 1958 the translation or allowed me to consult them about German and Reprint of English text alone 1963 Austrian usage or read the translation through and helped me to Third edition of English and German text with index 1967 improve the English: Mr. R. Rhees, Professor G. H. von Wright, Reprint of English text with index 1968, 1972, 1974, 1976, 1978, Mr. P. Geach, Mr. G. Kreisel, Miss L. Labowsky, Mr. D. Paul, Miss I. 1981, 1986 Murdoch. Basil Blackwell Ltd 108 Cowley Road, Oxford, OX4 1JF, UK All rights reserved. Except for the quotation of short passages for the purposes of criticism and review, no part of this publication may be NOTE TO SECOND EDITION reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or THE text has been revised for the new edition. A large number of otherwise, without the prior permission of the publisher. small changes have been made in the English text. The following passages have been significantly altered: Except in the United States of America, this book is sold to the In Part I: §§ 108, 109, 116, 189, 193, 251, 284, 352, 360, 393,418, condition that it shall not, by way of trade or otherwise, be lent, re- 426, 442, 456, 493, 520, 556, 582, 591, 644, 690, 692.
    [Show full text]
  • Download Article (PDF)
    Advances in Social Science, Education and Humanities Research, volume 104 2nd Annual International Seminar on Transformative Education and Educational Leadership (AISTEEL 2017) Development of Learning Devices Oriented Problem Based Learning to Increase Student’s Combinatorial Thinking in Mathematical Problem Solving Ability Ammamiarihta Department of Mathematics Education Universitas Negeri Medan Medan, Indonesia Corresponding Email: [email protected] Edi Syahputra Department of Mathematics Education Universitas Negeri Medan Medan, Indonesia Edy Surya Department of Mathematics Education Universitas Negeri Medan Medan, Indonesia Abstract–This research study is research and students, and learn the initial knowledge of students, all this development learning devices. This study aimed to describe will unravel its implementation in the learning device[1]. how the validity, practically, and effectiveness of learning Learning devices should not only provide materials devices oriented of problem based learning which is developed instantly, but be able to lead students to the ability to and knowing about increase students’ combinatorial thinking understand learned concepts. It aims to determine the extent in mathematical problem solving ability after using learning to which learning devices have been presented, what devices which is developed. The product that produce in this indicators to be achieved, to how the follow-up will be done study is lesson plan, handbook’s teacher, student’s book, and by the teacher. worksheet. Learning devices development using 4D model which developed by Thiagarajan, Semmel and Semmel with In the development of quality learning devices need four step, that is define, design, develop and disseminate. This an assessment of products developed. In order to make the study was conducted in two trials in two different class .
    [Show full text]
  • The Development of Mathematical Logic from Russell to Tarski: 1900–1935
    The Development of Mathematical Logic from Russell to Tarski: 1900–1935 Paolo Mancosu Richard Zach Calixto Badesa The Development of Mathematical Logic from Russell to Tarski: 1900–1935 Paolo Mancosu (University of California, Berkeley) Richard Zach (University of Calgary) Calixto Badesa (Universitat de Barcelona) Final Draft—May 2004 To appear in: Leila Haaparanta, ed., The Development of Modern Logic. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004 Contents Contents i Introduction 1 1 Itinerary I: Metatheoretical Properties of Axiomatic Systems 3 1.1 Introduction . 3 1.2 Peano’s school on the logical structure of theories . 4 1.3 Hilbert on axiomatization . 8 1.4 Completeness and categoricity in the work of Veblen and Huntington . 10 1.5 Truth in a structure . 12 2 Itinerary II: Bertrand Russell’s Mathematical Logic 15 2.1 From the Paris congress to the Principles of Mathematics 1900–1903 . 15 2.2 Russell and Poincar´e on predicativity . 19 2.3 On Denoting . 21 2.4 Russell’s ramified type theory . 22 2.5 The logic of Principia ......................... 25 2.6 Further developments . 26 3 Itinerary III: Zermelo’s Axiomatization of Set Theory and Re- lated Foundational Issues 29 3.1 The debate on the axiom of choice . 29 3.2 Zermelo’s axiomatization of set theory . 32 3.3 The discussion on the notion of “definit” . 35 3.4 Metatheoretical studies of Zermelo’s axiomatization . 38 4 Itinerary IV: The Theory of Relatives and Lowenheim’s¨ Theorem 41 4.1 Theory of relatives and model theory . 41 4.2 The logic of relatives .
    [Show full text]
  • An Unexplored Aspect of Following a Rule by Rachael Elizabeth Driver
    An Unexplored Aspect of Following a Rule by Rachael Elizabeth Driver Bachelor of Science, University of New South Wales, 2001 Bachelor of Liberal Studies (Honours), University of Sydney, 2006 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Dietrich School of Arts and Sciences in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2020 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH DIETRICH SCHOOL OF ARTS AND SCIENCES This dissertation was presented by Rachael Elizabeth Driver It was defended on July 27, 2020 and approved by Robert Batterman, Distinguished Professor of Philosophy Warren Goldfarb, Walter Beverly Pearson Professor of Modern Mathematics and Mathematical Logic, Harvard University Erica Shumener, Assistant Professor of Philosophy Dissertation Co-Directors: Thomas Ricketts, Professor of Philosophy Mark Wilson, Distinguished Professor of Philosophy ii Copyright © by Rachael Elizabeth Driver 2020 iii An Unexplored Aspect of Following a Rule Rachael Elizabeth Driver, PhD University of Pittsburgh, 2020 Though Wittgenstein has been most often identified as opposing Platonism in his writings about mathematics, I argue that Wittgenstein’s radical contextualism about mathematics finds its most natural opponent not in Platonism, but in a variety of formalism. One of Wittgenstein’s obvious formalist targets is his colleague the mathematician G. H. Hardy. If we discard this—still influential—picture of mathematics and replace it with a more nuanced account of mathematical activity as exemplified in the metamathematical thinking of the nineteenth century mathematician Augustus De Morgan, the example of the wayward pupil takes on a different significance. Against a more complex background, the wayward pupil can be reinterpreted as representing an exemplar of mathematical discovery.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language
    SAUL A. KRIPKE Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language An Elementary Exposition Harvard University Press Cambridge, Massachusetts Contents Copyright © 1982 by Saul A. Kripke All rights reserved Preface Vll EIGHTH PRINTING, 1995 1 Introductory 1 Printed in the United States of America 2 The Wittgensteinian Paradox 7 3 The Solution and the 'Private Language' Argument 55 Postscript Wittgenstein and Other Minds Library ofCongress Cataloging in Publication Data 114 Index Kripke, Saul A., 1940- 147 Wittgenstein on rules and private language. Includes bibliographical references and index. Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 1889-1951. I. Title B3376.W564K74 192 81-20070 AACR2 ISBN 0-674-95401-7 (paper) - To my parents Preface The main part ofthis work has been delivered at various places as lectures, series oflectures, or seminars. It constitutes, as I say, 'an elementary exposition' ofwhat I take to be the central thread of Wittgenstein's later work on the philosophy of language and the philosophy of mathematics, including my interpretation of the 'private language argument', which on my view is principally to be explicated in terms ofthe problem of 'following a rule'. A postscript presents another problem Wittgenstein saw in the conception ofprivate language, which leads to a discussion of some aspects of his views on the problem ofother minds. Since I stress the strong connection in Wittgenstein's later philosophy between the philosophy of psychology and the philosophy of mathematics, I had hoped to add a second postscript on the philosophy ofmathematics. Time has not permitted this, so for the moment the basic remarks on philosophy ofmathematics in the main text must suffice.
    [Show full text]
  • Problem Posing As a Means for Developing Mathematical
    PROBLEM POSING AS A MEANS FOR DEVELOPING MATHEMATICAL KNOWLEDGE OF PROSPECTIVE TEACHERS Ilana Lavy and Atara Shriki Emek Yezreel Academic College / Oranim Academic College of Education Abstract In the present study we aim at exploring the development of mathematical knowledge and problem solving skills of prospective teachers as result of their engagement in problem posing activity. Data was collected through the prospective teachers’ reflective portfolios and weekly class discussions. Analysis of the data shows that the prospective teachers developed their ability to examine definition and attributes of mathematical objects, connections among mathematical objects, and validity of an argument. However, they tend to focus on common posed problems, being afraid of their inability to prove their findings. This finding suggests that overemphasizing the importance of providing a formal proof prevents the development of inquiry abilities. Introduction Problem posing (PP) is recognized as an important component of mathematics teaching and learning (NCTM, 2000). In order that teachers will gain the knowledge and the required confidence for incorporating PP activities in their classes, they have to experience it first. While experiencing PP they will acknowledge its various benefits. Hence such an experience should start by the time these teachers are being qualified towards their profession. Therefore, while working with prospective teachers (PT) we integrate activities of PP into their method courses. In addition, accompanying the process with reflective writing might make the PT be more aware to the processes they are going through (Campbell et al, 1997), and as a result increase the plausibility that the PT will internalize the effect of the processes that are involved in PP activities.
    [Show full text]
  • Problem Solving Strategies Students Use When Solving
    PROBLEM SOLVING STRATEGIES STUDENTS USE WHEN SOLVING COMBINATORIAL PROBLEMS by GARY YUEN A THESIS SUBMITTED iN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS in THE FACULTY OF GRADUATE STUDIES (Mathematics Education) THE UNIVERSITY OF BRITISH COLUMBIA (Vancouver) August 2008 © Gary Yuen, 2008 ABSTRACT This research is a case study that examines the strategies that three grade 11 students use to manoeuvre through a series of three combinatorial problems. Grade 11 students were chosen as participants because they have had no formal training in solving this class of math problems. Data includes video recordings of each participant’s problem solving sessions along with each participant’s written work. Through analysis of this data, several themes related to problem solving strategies were identified. First, students tend to rely on algebraic representation and methods as they approach a problem. Second, students use the term “guess and check” to describe any strategy where the steps to a solution are not clearly defined. Thirdly, as students negotiate problems, they tend to search for patterns that will streamline their methods. Fourthly, students approach complicated problems by breaking up the problem into smaller parts. Finally, students who verify their work throughout the problems solving process tend to experience more success than those who do not. From these findings, I suggest that mathematics teachers need to ensure that they are not over-emphasizing algebraic strategies in the classroom. In addition, students need to be given the opportunity to explore various solution strategies to a given problem. Finally, students should be taught how to verify their work, and be encouraged to perform this step throughout the problem solving process.
    [Show full text]
  • Karl Popper and the Philosophy of Mathematics Proceedings of the Conference Held in Klagenfurt, 5 – 7 April, 2018
    Symposium Karl Popper and the Philosophy of Mathematics Proceedings of the Conference held in Klagenfurt, 5 – 7 April, 2018 Edited by Reinhard Neck Alpen-Adria-Universität Klagenfurt 2018 Contents Preface ................................................................................................................ v Programme ...................................................................................................... vii Abstracts and Preliminary Papers .................................................................. 1 Schroeder-Heister, Peter Popper on deductive logic and logical education ...................................................... 2 Binder, David A Critical Edition of Popper's Work on Logic .......................................................... 3 Brîncuş, Constantin and Toader, Iulian Non-normal Interpretations of Positive Logic .......................................................... 8 Pimbé, Daniel Popper and “absolute proofs” ................................................................................. 12 Albert, Max Critical Rationalism and Decision Theory .............................................................. 25 Del Santo, Flavio The physical motivations for a propensity interpretation of probability ................. 26 Afisi, Oseni Taiwo Prospensity Probability and Its Applications of Knowledge in Ifa ......................... 32 Miller, David Independence (Probabilistic) and Independence (Logical) ..................................... 36 Burgoyne, Bernard From cosmic paths to psychic
    [Show full text]
  • The Influence of Teaching Mathematical Problem Solving Strategies on Students’ Attitudes in Middle School
    University of Central Florida STARS Electronic Theses and Dissertations, 2004-2019 2012 Mathematic Strategies For Teaching Problem Solving: The Influence Of eachingT Mathematical Problem Solving Strategies On Students' Attitudes In Middle School Kelly Lynn Klingler University of Central Florida Part of the Science and Mathematics Education Commons Find similar works at: https://stars.library.ucf.edu/etd University of Central Florida Libraries http://library.ucf.edu This Masters Thesis (Open Access) is brought to you for free and open access by STARS. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations, 2004-2019 by an authorized administrator of STARS. For more information, please contact [email protected]. STARS Citation Klingler, Kelly Lynn, "Mathematic Strategies For Teaching Problem Solving: The Influence Of eachingT Mathematical Problem Solving Strategies On Students' Attitudes In Middle School" (2012). Electronic Theses and Dissertations, 2004-2019. 2316. https://stars.library.ucf.edu/etd/2316 MATHEMATIC STRATEGIES FOR TEACHING PROBLEM SOLVING: THE INFLUENCE OF TEACHING MATHEMATICAL PROBLEM SOLVING STRATEGIES ON STUDENTS’ ATTITUDES IN MIDDLE SCHOOL by KELLY LYNN KLINGLER B.A. Mount Vernon Nazarene University, 2006 A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Education in the School of Teaching, Learning and Leadership in the College of Education at the University of Central Florida Orlando, Florida Spring Term 2012 © 2012 Kelly L. Klingler ii ABSTRACT The purpose of this action research study was to observe the influence of teaching mathematical problem solving strategies on students’ attitudes in middle school. The goal was to teach five problem solving strategies: Drawing Pictures, Making a Chart or Table, Looking for a Pattern, Working Backwards, and Guess and Check, and have students reflect upon the process.
    [Show full text]
  • HISTORY-BASED PROBLEMS in the TEACHING of SENIOR HIGH SCHOOL Mathematics in Mainland China Xiaoqin Wang
    HISTORY-BASED PROBLEMS IN THE TEACHING OF SENIOR HIGH SCHOOL Mathematics in Mainland China Xiaoqin Wang To cite this version: Xiaoqin Wang. HISTORY-BASED PROBLEMS IN THE TEACHING OF SENIOR HIGH SCHOOL Mathematics in Mainland China. History and Pedagogy of Mathematics, Jul 2016, Montpellier, France. hal-01349273 HAL Id: hal-01349273 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01349273 Submitted on 27 Jul 2016 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. HISTORY-BASED PROBLEMS IN THE TEACHING OF SENIOR HIGH SCHOOL Mathematics in Mainland China Xiaoqin Wang Department of Mathematics East China Normal University, Shanghai 200241 汪晓勤 [email protected] ABSTRACT This paper deals with the integration of history in mathematics teaching. Four possible approaches are considered: complementation, replication, accommodation, reconstruction. The main focus is on the relation between. mathematical problems posed on the basis of historical information (history-based problems) and mathematics teaching from the HPM perspective. In this paper 20 HPM lessons are analysed. 1 Introduction Integrating the history of mathematics into mathematics teaching is one of the important research fields in HPM. As shown in table 1, four ways are identified in which historical information is used in classroom teaching in Mainland China.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Mathematics, Mathematics Education, and Philosophy of Mathematics Education Yuxin Zheng Nanjing University
    Humanistic Mathematics Network Journal Issue 9 Article 9 2-1-1994 Philosophy of Mathematics, Mathematics Education, and Philosophy of Mathematics Education Yuxin Zheng Nanjing University Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.claremont.edu/hmnj Part of the Logic and Foundations of Mathematics Commons, Mathematics Commons, Scholarship of Teaching and Learning Commons, and the Science and Mathematics Education Commons Recommended Citation Zheng, Yuxin (1994) "Philosophy of Mathematics, Mathematics Education, and Philosophy of Mathematics Education," Humanistic Mathematics Network Journal: Iss. 9, Article 9. Available at: http://scholarship.claremont.edu/hmnj/vol1/iss9/9 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Claremont at Scholarship @ Claremont. It has been accepted for inclusion in Humanistic Mathematics Network Journal by an authorized administrator of Scholarship @ Claremont. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Philosophy of Mathematics, Mathematics Education and Philosophy of Mathematics Education Zheng Yuxin (Y. Zheng) Department of Philosophy Nanling University. China (P. R. C.) As a philosopher of mathematics. I have been the great infl uence of the philosophy of thinking about, or rather, worried about the mathematics on mathematics education. The third follow ing qu esti on: is there any important section discusses the problem of how to develop rel ation ship between the philosophy of the subject 'philosophy of mathematics education , mathematics and actual mathematical activities which in fact can be regarded as an impetus from (including mathematical research, teaching and mathematics education to the further development learning)? Or, does the philosophy of mathematics of philosophy of mathematics and philosophy in have any important infl uence on act ual general.
    [Show full text]