Evolutionary Psychology and the Brain Bradley Duchaine*, Leda Cosmides† and John Tooby‡

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Evolutionary Psychology and the Brain Bradley Duchaine*, Leda Cosmides† and John Tooby‡ 225 Evolutionary psychology and the brain Bradley Duchaine*, Leda Cosmides† and John Tooby‡ The human brain is a set of computational machines, each of they solve adaptive problems. This requires theories of which was designed by natural selection to solve adaptive adaptive function. These are engineering specifications, problems faced by our hunter–gatherer ancestors. These which provide analyses of what would count as good machines are adaptive specializations: systems equipped with design for a particular problem [1]. In so doing, they also design features that are organized such that they solve an provide the criteria necessary to decide whether a property ancestral problem reliably, economically and efficiently. The of an organism is a design feature, a functionless search for functionally specialized computational adaptations by-product, a kludge in the system, or noise. has now begun in earnest. A host of specialized systems have recently been found, including ones designed for sexual The functional organization of the brain can be illuminated motivation, social inference, judgment under uncertainty and by applying the same biological theories and principles. The conditioning, as well as content-rich systems for visual task of cognitive neuroscience is to reverse-engineer the recognition and knowledge acquisition. brain: to dissect its computational architecture into function- ally isolable information-processing units, and to determine Addresses how these units operate, both computationally and physically. *‡Department of Psychology, University of California, Santa Barbara, A correct dissection is one that illuminates the design of these CA 93106, USA units and explains their presence. The engineering specifica- *e-mail: [email protected] tions that a good theory of adaptive function provides are ‡e-mail: [email protected] †Center for Evolutionary Psychology, University of California, Santa essential to this enterprise. Theories of adaptive function can Barbara, CA 93106, USA tell one several things. First, they can suggest what kind of computational machines to look for (e.g. units designed for Current Opinion in Neurobiology 2001, 11:225–230 tasks such as: choosing a fertile mate; minimizing contagion; 0959-4388/01/$ — see front matter foraging; caring for children; predicting the trajectories of © 2001 Elsevier Science Ltd. All rights reserved. inanimate objects; predicting the behavior of predators, prey, and other members of one’s own species). Second, they can Introduction tell us what would count as a good design for solving each of In this article, we shall review some of the recent evidence for these problems. Third, they can reveal when a unit designed functionally specialized problem-solving machinery in the for solving one task will be unable to solve another. The brain. We shall also discuss how theories of adaptive function latter is important: when the computational requirements of have been used to uncover their presence and design. two tasks differ, one expects selection to have created a different computational system for accomplishing each —that The phenomenon that Darwin was trying to explain is the is, two different functionally specialized adaptations [2,3••]. presence of functional organization in living systems — the kind of organization that one finds in artifacts that were This expectation is at variance with associationist and designed by an intelligent engineer to solve a problem of other unitarian views of the brain, which many cognitive some kind. Darwin showed how the feedback loops of a neuroscientists have inherited from the parent disciplines blind causal process —natural selection —could create of neuroscience and cognitive psychology. As Gallistel structures that looked like they were designed by an intelli- [4••] puts it, gent engineer to solve a problem. His detailed studies of plants and animals revealed complex structures composed “It is odd but true that most past and contemporary of parts that appeared to be organized to overcome repro- theorizing about learning does not assume that ductive obstacles (e.g. the presence of predators) or to take learning mechanisms are adaptively specialized for advantage of reproductive opportunities (e.g. the presence the solution of particular kinds of problems. Most of fertile mates). And this made sense: although selection theorizing assumes that there is a general-purpose can inject problem-solving machines into the architecture learning process in the brain, a process adapted only of a species, the only problems it can design machines for to solving the problem of learning. There is no solving are ones that had an impact on reproductive rates attempt to formalize what the problem of learning is in the environments in which a species evolved. and thereby determine whether it can in fact be conceived as a single or uniform problem. From a Discovering how to dissect the architecture of a species in biological perspective, this assumption is equiva- a way that illuminates its functional organization and lent to assuming that there is a general-purpose explains its presence has been a foundational task for evo- sensory organ, which solves the problem of sensing.” lutionary biology ever since. To arrive at the appropriate construal, one must conceptualize this architecture as com- Gallistel [4••] has analyzed various learning problems solved posed of nonrandom parts that interact in such a way that by desert ants, bees, pigeons, and other animals, showing: 226 Cognitive neuroscience first, that they are incommensurate; second, that each is Note that although these systems can operate on a wide solved by a different computational machine that is special- array of contents, they are designed for solving problems ized for that task; and third, that associative theories of that arise in a particular domain —foraging —and they are learning are incapable of explaining the animal learning data. specialized for solving foraging problems. Other adaptive We will begin with this last result, because associationist problems, such as learned taste aversions and danger avoid- expectations about the brain persist and continue to organize ance, also rely on the computation of temporal research agendas in cognitive neuroscience, despite demon- contingencies and may use some of the same machinery. strations that associationist mechanisms are not capable of Despite some overlap, however, the solution to these prob- explaining many features of human cognition [4••,5••,6,7]. lems requires additional, functionally specialized machinery (with different brain regions implicated) [11,12]. Selection Content-general systems: functional can specialize the performance of a computational machine specialization and adaptive design by giving it what amounts to innate knowledge about a A computational adaptation can be content-general —that domain, and this appears to have happened in many is, it can operate on information drawn from many different domains that come under the heading of ‘conditioning’ domains —yet still be functionally specialized. Classical [13,14]. This would include the existence of domain- and operant conditioning provide a case in point. According specialized unconditioned stimulus–unconditioned to traditional accounts, conditioning is produced by response (US–UR) relationships (e.g. toxins and enzyme associative mechanisms that track spatio-temporal induction [15], snakes and avoidance [16]), as well as contiguity —the paradigmatic general-purpose learning content-specific, privileged hypotheses about conditioned process. In contrast, adaptationist analyses suggest that the stimulus–unconditioned stimulus (CS–US) relationships mechanisms that produce conditioning are functionally (e.g. taste and nausea [13,17]). Accordingly, some forms of specialized for efficient foraging in the wild [5••]. Rates of conditioning enjoin the neostriatum, others the neocortex reward differ at different foraging sites and under different and amygdala, and yet others the cerebellum [11,12]. foraging conditions: a well-designed mechanism should be sensitive to these differences in rates, detect changes in Content-specific systems: functional them, and take into account the statistical uncertainties specialization and adaptive design inherent in a limited number of observations. Foragers need Another way to specialize and thereby improve the perfor- to compute temporal contingencies, not contiguities. Based mance of a computational machine is to restrict its domain on this evolutionary task analysis, Gallistel and Gibbon [5••] of application. A domain-restricted device can be endowed argue that, formally, this problem corresponds to multivari- with content: with assumptions, privileged hypotheses, and ate nonstationary time-series analysis; they demonstrate that inference procedures that are appropriate to a domain, but associative mechanisms are incapable of performing the may be irrelevant or even misleading when applied outside necessary computations, and provide an alternative compu- that domain. Configural information about the human face tational model that is. Their model predicts many known may help infants to recognize their parents, but will be conditioning phenomena that associationist models cannot useless for recognizing plants; assuming that invisible account for, such as the time-scale invariance of condition- mental states (beliefs and desires) exist may help predict ing, the failure of partial reinforcement to influence the the behavior of people
Recommended publications
  • In Defense of Massive Modularity
    3 In Defense of Massive Modularity Dan Sperber In October 1990, a psychologist, Susan Gelman, and three anthropolo- gists whose interest in cognition had been guided and encouraged by Jacques Mehler, Scott Atran, Larry Hirschfeld, and myself, organized a conference on “Cultural Knowledge and Domain Specificity” (see Hirsch- feld and Gelman, 1994). Jacques advised us in the preparation of the conference, and while we failed to convince him to write a paper, he did play a major role in the discussions. A main issue at stake was the degree to which cognitive development, everyday cognition, and cultural knowledge are based on dedicated do- main-specific mechanisms, as opposed to a domain-general intelligence and learning capacity. Thanks in particular to the work of developmental psychologists such as Susan Carey, Rochel Gelman, Susan Gelman, Frank Keil, Alan Leslie, Jacques Mehler, Elizabeth Spelke (who were all there), the issue of domain-specificity—which, of course, Noam Chomsky had been the first to raise—was becoming a central one in cognitive psychol- ogy. Evolutionary psychology, represented at the conference by Leda Cosmides and John Tooby, was putting forward new arguments for seeing human cognition as involving mostly domain- or task-specific evolved adaptations. We were a few anthropologists, far from the main- stream of our discipline, who also saw domain-specific cognitive pro- cesses as both constraining and contributing to cultural development. Taking for granted that domain-specific dispositions are an important feature of human cognition, three questions arise: 1. To what extent are these domain-specific dispositions based on truly autonomous mental mechanisms or “modules,” as opposed to being 48 D.
    [Show full text]
  • Preferences Under Pressure
    Eric Skoog Preferences Under Pressure Conflict, Threat Cues and Willingness to Compromise Dissertation presented at Uppsala University to be publicly examined in Zootissalen, EBC, Villavägen 9, Uppsala, Friday, 13 March 2020 at 10:15 for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. The examination will be conducted in English. Faculty examiner: Associate Professor Thomas Zeitzoff (American University, School of Public Affairs). Abstract Skoog, E. 2020. Preferences Under Pressure. Conflict, Threat Cues and Willingness to Compromise. Report / Department of Peace and Conflict Research 121. 66 pp. Uppsala: Department of Peace and Conflict Research. ISBN 978-91-506-2805-0. Understanding how preferences are formed is a key question in the social sciences. The ability of agents to interact with each other is a prerequisite for well-functioning societies. Nevertheless, the process whereby the preferences of agents in conflict are formed have often been black boxed, and the literature on the effects of armed conflict on individuals reveals a great variation in terms of outcomes. Sometimes, individuals are willing to cooperate and interact even with former enemies, while sometimes, we see outright refusal to cooperate or interact at all. In this dissertation, I look at the role of threat in driving some of these divergent results. Armed conflict is rife with physical threats to life, limb and property, and there has been much research pointing to the impact of threat on preferences, attitudes and behavior. Research in the field of evolutionary psychology has revealed that threat is not a singular category, but a nuanced phenomenon, where different types of threat may lead to different responses.
    [Show full text]
  • States in Mind Anthony C. Lopez, Rose Mcdermott, and Michael
    States in Mind States in Mind Anthony C. Lopez, Rose McDermott, and Evolution, Coalitional Psychology, and Michael Bang International Politics Petersen One of the most com- monly studied puzzles in international politics is the recurrence of coalitional competition and aggression between political groups such as states. Indeed, this pattern constitutes an enduring and central feature of all politics. Yet de- spite the tragic endurance of this leitmotif throughout history, its manifestation varies through time and space. Some wars are fought for honor or revenge, whereas others are ignited for mere opportunism or as a consequence of vari- ous misperceptions, whatever their source. We argue that evolutionary theory provides a theoretical framework that can explain both the stubborn endur- ance and dynamic diversity of coalitional behavior. Debate on the relevance of “human nature” and biological factors for explaining political behavior is not new.1 Yet the comprehensive value of evo- lutionary theory for explaining important aspects of international politics has not been adequately explicated. As we discuss below, this has in part been a consequence of general skepticism about the validity and scope of evolution- ary theory for explaining political behavior. We argue, however, that evolu- tionary psychology can generate falsiªable ex ante predictions that are of central interest to the study of international politics, and we offer several hy- potheses derived from this model to illustrate the depth of this approach. Evo- lutionary psychologists have already generated a large body of work that suggests that the human brain contains webs of psychological mechanisms, or adaptations, each designed to operate in domains relevant to modern politics, and which emerged as a product of natural selection.
    [Show full text]
  • The Descent of Edward Wilson
    prospectmagazine.co.uk http://www.prospectmagazine.co.uk/magazine/edward-wilson-social-conquest- earth-evolutionary-errors-origin-species/ The descent of Edward Wilson A new book on evolution by a great biologist makes a slew of mistakes The Social Conquest of Earth By Edward O Wilson (WW Norton, £18.99, May) When he received the manuscript of The Origin of Species, John Murray, the publisher, sent it to a referee who suggested that Darwin should jettison all that evolution stuff and concentrate on pigeons. It’s funny in the same way as the spoof review of Lady Chatterley’s Lover, which praised its interesting “passages on pheasant raising, the apprehending of poachers, ways of controlling vermin, and other chores and duties of the professional gamekeeper” but added: “Unfortunately one is obliged to wade through many pages of extraneous material in order to discover and savour these sidelights on the management of a Midland shooting estate, and in this reviewer’s opinion this book can not take the place of JR Miller’s Practical Gamekeeping.” I am not being funny when I say of Edward Wilson’s latest book that there are interesting and informative chapters on human evolution, and on the ways of social insects (which he knows better than any man alive), and it was a good idea to write a book comparing these two pinnacles of social evolution, but unfortunately one is obliged to wade through many pages of erroneous and downright perverse misunderstandings of evolutionary theory. In particular, Wilson now rejects “kin selection” (I shall explain this below) and replaces it with a revival of “group selection”—the poorly defined and incoherent view that evolution is driven by the differential survival of whole groups of organisms.
    [Show full text]
  • A Lego Model of the Modularity of the Mind Steven J
    Eastern Illinois University The Keep Faculty Research and Creative Activity Psychology January 2004 A Lego Model of the Modularity of the Mind Steven J. Scher Eastern Illinois University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://thekeep.eiu.edu/psych_fac Part of the Psychology Commons Recommended Citation Scher, Steven J., "A Lego Model of the Modularity of the Mind" (2004). Faculty Research and Creative Activity. 32. http://thekeep.eiu.edu/psych_fac/32 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Psychology at The Keep. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Research and Creative Activity by an authorized administrator of The Keep. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A LEGO MODEL OF THE MODULARITY OF THE MIND STEVEN J. SCHER Eastern Illinois University Abstract. In this paper I propose that the dominant form of evolutionary psychology (which I term “cognitive adaptationism”) can be improved by adopting an alternative version of the concept of mental modularity. I suggest a metaphor of mental modules as Lego blocks. The Lego blocks represent a relatively small set of elementary operations that the mind/brain can carry out. These Lego blocks are repeatedly assembled in different ways to execute a wide variety of different functions. These repeated assemblies correspond more closely to the things that cognitive adaptationists have asserted are modules. Arguments in favor of the Lego model include the fact that the localized neural systems identified in the brain appear to carry out elementary operations, rather than higher-level functions, and the fact that evolution by natural selection occurs by the gradual modification of small-level features.
    [Show full text]
  • Steven Pinker Why Nature & Nurture Won't Go Away
    Steven Pinker Why nature & nurture won’t go away When Richard Mulcaster referred in that debates over nature and nurture 1581 to “that treasure . bestowed on evoke more rancor than just about any them by nature, to be bettered in them issue in the world of ideas. by nurture,” he gave the world a eupho- During much of the twentieth century, nious name for an opposition that has a common position in this debate was to been debated ever since. People’s beliefs deny that human nature existed at all– about the relative importance of heredi- to aver, with José Ortega y Gasset, that ty and environment affect their opinions “Man has no nature; what he has is his- on an astonishing range of topics. Do tory.” The doctrine that the mind is a adolescents engage in violence because blank slate was not only a cornerstone of the way their parents treated them of behaviorism in psychology and social early in life? Are people inherently ag- constructionism in the social sciences, gressive and sel½sh, calling for a market but also extended widely into main- economy and a strong police, or could stream intellectual life.1 they become peaceable and cooperative, Part of the blank slate’s appeal came allowing the state to wither and a spon- from the realization that many differ- taneous socialism to blossom? Is there a ences among people in different classes universal aesthetic that allows great art and ethnic groups that formerly were to transcend time and place, or are peo- 1 Carl N. Degler, In Search of Human Nature: ple’s tastes determined by their era and The Decline and Revival of Darwinism in American culture? With so much seemingly at Social Thought (New York: Oxford University stake in so many ½elds, it is no surprise Press, 1991); Steven Pinker, The Blank Slate: The Modern Denial of Human Nature (New York: Viking, 2002); Robin Fox, The Search for Soci- ety: Quest for a Biosocial Science and Morality Steven Pinker, Johnstone Family Professor in the (New Brunswick, N.J.: Rutgers University department of psychology at Harvard University, Press, 1989); Eric M.
    [Show full text]
  • Face-Specific Impairment in Holistic Perception Following Focal Lesion of the Right Anterior Temporal Lobe
    Neuropsychologia 56 (2014) 312–333 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Neuropsychologia journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/neuropsychologia Face-specific impairment in holistic perception following focal lesion of the right anterior temporal lobe Thomas Busigny a,d,n, Goedele Van Belle a, Boutheina Jemel b, Anthony Hosein b, Sven Joubert c, Bruno Rossion a a Institute of Research in Psychology and Institute of Neuroscience, Université Catholique de Louvain, Louvain-la-Neuve, Belgium b Neuroscience and Cognitive Electrophysiology Research Lab, Hôpital Rivière-des-Prairies, Montréal, Canada c Département de Psychologie, Université de Montreal & Centre de Recherche Institut Universitaire de Gériatrie de Montréal, Canada d Université de Toulouse, UPS, Centre de Recherche Cerveau et Cognition (CNRS, Cerco), Toulouse, France article info abstract Article history: Recent studies have provided solid evidence for pure cases of prosopagnosia following brain damage. Received 29 May 2013 The patients reported so far have posterior lesions encompassing either or both the right inferior occipital Received in revised form cortex and fusiform gyrus, and exhibit a critical impairment in generating a sufficiently detailed holistic 21 January 2014 percept to individualize faces. Here, we extended these observations to include the prosopagnosic patient LR Accepted 24 January 2014 (Bukach, Bub, Gauthier, & Tarr, 2006), whose damage is restricted to the anterior region of the right Available online 4 February 2014 temporal lobe. First, we report that LR is able to discriminate parametrically defined individual exemplars of Keywords: nonface object categories as accurately and quickly as typical observers, which suggests that the visual Acquired prosopagnosia similarity account of prosopagnosia does not explain his impairments.
    [Show full text]
  • The Natures of Universal Moralities, 75 Brook
    Brooklyn Law Review Volume 75 Issue 2 SYMPOSIUM: Article 4 Is Morality Universal, and Should the Law Care? 2009 The aN tures of Universal Moralities Bailey Kuklin Follow this and additional works at: https://brooklynworks.brooklaw.edu/blr Recommended Citation Bailey Kuklin, The Natures of Universal Moralities, 75 Brook. L. Rev. (2009). Available at: https://brooklynworks.brooklaw.edu/blr/vol75/iss2/4 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Journals at BrooklynWorks. It has been accepted for inclusion in Brooklyn Law Review by an authorized editor of BrooklynWorks. The Natures of Universal Moralities Bailey Kuklin† One of the abiding lessons from postmodernism is that reason does not go all the way down.1 In the context of this symposium, one cannot deductively derive a universal morality from incontestible moral primitives,2 or practical reason alone.3 Instead, even reasoned moral systems must ultimately be grounded on intuition,4 a sense of justice. The question then † Professor of Law, Brooklyn Law School. I wish to thank the presenters and participants of the Brooklyn Law School Symposium entitled “Is Morality Universal, and Should the Law Care?” and those at the Tenth SEAL Scholarship Conference. Further thanks go to Brooklyn Law School for supporting this project with a summer research stipend. 1 “Simplifying to the extreme, I define postmodern as incredulity toward metanarratives.” JEAN-FRANCOIS LYOTARD, THE POSTMODERN CONDITION: A REPORT ON KNOWLEDGE xxiv (Geoff Bennington & Brian Massumi trans., 1984). “If modernity is viewed with Weberian optimism as the project of rationalisation of the life-world, an era of material progress, social emancipation and scientific innovation, the postmodern is derided as chaotic, catastrophic, nihilistic, the end of good order.” COSTAS DOUZINAS ET AL., POSTMODERN JURISPRUDENCE 16 (1991).
    [Show full text]
  • Fusiform Gyrus Face Selectivity Relates to Individual Differences in Facial Recognition Ability
    Fusiform Gyrus Face Selectivity Relates to Individual Differences in Facial Recognition Ability Nicholas Furl, Lúcia Garrido, Raymond J. Dolan, Jon Driver, and Bradley Duchaine Abstract ■ Regions of the occipital and temporal lobes, including a re- robust relationships between face selectivity and face identifi- gion in the fusiform gyrus (FG), have been proposed to con- cation ability in FG across our sample for several convergent stitute a “core” visual representation system for faces, in part measures, including voxel-wise statistical parametric mapping, because they show face selectivity and face repetition suppres- peak face selectivity in individually defined “fusiform face areas” sion. But recent fMRI studies of developmental prosopagnosics (FFAs), and anatomical extents (cluster sizes) of those FFAs. (DPs) raise questions about whether these measures relate to None of these measures showed associations with behavioral face processing skills. Although DPs manifest deficient face expression or object recognition ability. As a group, DPs had processing, most studies to date have not shown unequivocal reduced face-selective responses in bilateral FFA when com- reductions of functional responses in the proposed core re- pared with non-DPs. Individual DPs were also more likely than gions. We scanned 15 DPs and 15 non-DP control participants non-DPs to lack expected face-selective activity in core regions. with fMRI while employing factor analysis to derive behavioral These findings associate individual differences in face process- components related to face identification or other processes. ing ability with selectivity in core face processing regions. Repetition suppression specific to facial identities in FG or to This confirms that face selectivity can provide a valid marker expression in FG and STS did not show compelling relation- for neural mechanisms that contribute to face identification ships with face identification ability.
    [Show full text]
  • Evolutionary Psychology: a Primer
    Evolutionary Psychology: A Primer Leda Cosmides & John Tooby Center for Evolutionary Psychology UC Santa Barbara http://www.psych.ucsb.edu/research/cep/ Introduction The goal of research in evolutionary psychology is to discover and understand the design of the human mind. Evolutionary psychology is an approach to psychology, in which knowledge and principles from evolutionary biology are put to use in research on the structure of the human mind. It is not an area of study, like vision, reasoning, or social behavior. It is a way of thinking about psychology that can be applied to any topic within it. In this view, the mind is a set of information-processing machines that were designed by natural selection to solve adaptive problems faced by our hunter-gatherer ancestors. This way of thinking about the brain, mind, and behavior is changing how scientists approach old topics, and opening up new ones. This chapter is a primer on the concepts and arguments that animate it. Debauching the mind: Evolutionary psychology's past and present In the final pages of the Origin of Species, after he had presented the theory of evolution by natural selection, Darwin made a bold prediction: "In the distant future I see open fields for far more important researches. Psychology will be based on a new foundation, that of the necessary acquirement of each mental power and capacity by gradation." Thirty years later, William James tried to do just that in his seminal book, Principles of Psychology, one of the founding works of experimental psychology (James, 1890). In Principles, James talked a lot of "instincts".
    [Show full text]
  • Evolutionary Psychology – 2007
    Evolutionary Psychology www.epjournal.net – 2007. 5(4): 683-695 ¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯ Original Article What’s in a Name: Is “Evolutionary Psychology” Eclipsing “Sociobiology” in the Scientific Literature? Gregory D. Webster, Department of Psychology, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign, Champaign, IL 61820, USA. Email: [email protected] (Corresponding author) Abstract: Is the term “evolutionary psychology” supplanting “sociobiology” in the scientific literature? How influential was E. O. Wilson’s (1975) book, Sociobiology, in establishing the discipline of the same name? Similarly, how influential were the two Tooby-Cosmides chapters appearing in The Adapted Mind (Cosmides and Tooby, 1992; Tooby and Cosmides, 1992) in establishing evolutionary psychology as a viable outgrowth of sociobiology? The purpose of the present research was to answer these questions using quantitative analyses of publication trends. The Internet search engine Google Scholar was used to count the number of hits (i.e., the number of scholarly works, citations, etc.) for “sociobiology” and “evolutionary psychology” separately per year from 1960 to 2003. Interrupted time-series analyses revealed significant increases (intercept shifts) for sociobiology hits between 1974 and 1975, and for evolutionary psychology hits between 1991 and 1992. Evolutionary psychology hits also experienced a significant increase in change-over-time (a slope shift) between 1991 and 1992. Growth curve analyses revealed that the rate of growth for evolutionary psychology, which
    [Show full text]
  • How Human Evolutionary Psychology Can Inform Adaptive Behavior Research Geoff
    A bottom-up approach with a clear view of the top: How human evolutionary psychology can inform adaptive behavior research Geoffrey F. Miller School of Cognitive and Computing Sciences University of Sussex Falmer, Brighton BN1 9QH, England (Now at Department of Psychology, University of Nottingham; [email protected]) Peter M. Todd Department of Psychology University of Denver 2155 S. Race Street Denver, CO 80208 USA [email protected] The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture. Edited by Jerome H. Barkow, Leda Cosmides, and John Tooby. New York: Oxford University Press (1992). ISBN 0-19- 506023-7, xii + 666 pp., $55 hardback. Introduction Psychologists have long paid lip service to Darwin, conceding that the human brain did arise through the course of evolution (for whatever, often unspecified, reason). But the full power of Darwinian theory is almost never used in day-to-day psychology research. This is peculiar, given the successful, integrated nature of evolutionary biology, and the typically fragmented and incomplete visage of modern psychology: one would think that a theory that explains the origin and maintenance of complex behavioral adaptations across all species (evolution) could inform and unify the study of human behavior (psychology) just as productively as it does the study of animal behavior (ethology and comparative cognition). But the emergence of a genuinely evolutionary psychology of humans (HEP) has been a slow, painful, and quite recent occurrence, marked at last by the publication of a flagship volume, The Adapted Mind. This work is of great importance not only for researchers in all branches of human psychology, but also for those in the field of adaptive behavior as well, because it demonstrates that the operation of even the most sophisticated and seemingly general behavioral system we know of -- the human brain -- can only be understood as the conglomeration of a great variety of specific mental mechanisms, each finely tuned to a particular adaptive problem.
    [Show full text]