Radical Scepticism, How-Possible Questions and Modest Transcendental Arguments

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Radical Scepticism, How-Possible Questions and Modest Transcendental Arguments International Journal of Philosophical Studies ISSN: 0967-2559 (Print) 1466-4542 (Online) Journal homepage: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/riph20 Radical Scepticism, How-Possible Questions and Modest Transcendental Arguments Ju Wang To cite this article: Ju Wang (2017) Radical Scepticism, How-Possible Questions and Modest Transcendental Arguments, International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 25:2, 210-226, DOI: 10.1080/09672559.2017.1296881 To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09672559.2017.1296881 Published online: 08 Mar 2017. Submit your article to this journal Article views: 40 View related articles View Crossmark data Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=riph20 Download by: [Fudan University] Date: 12 April 2017, At: 01:43 INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES, 2017 VOL. 25, NO. 2, 210–226 http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09672559.2017.1296881 Radical Scepticism, How-Possible Questions and Modest Transcendental Arguments Ju Wang School of Philosophy, Fudan University, Shanghai, China ABSTRACT According to radical scepticism, knowledge of the external world is impossible. Transcendental arguments are supposed to be anti-sceptical, but can they provide a satisfying response to radical scepticism? Especially, when radical scepticism is cast as posing a how-possible question, there is a concern that transcendental arguments are neither sufficient nor necessary for answering such question. In light of this worry, I argue that we can take a modest transcendental argument as a stepping stone for a diagnostic anti-sceptical proposal, and I use a Wittgensteinian modest transcendental argument to illustrate my point. KEYWORDS Sceptical paradox; Wittgenstein; hinge commitments; how-possible questions; diagnosis 1. Introduction Transcendental arguments are supposed to be anti-sceptical, but can transcendental arguments provide a satisfying response to radical scepticism? In what follows, I take radical scepticism to amount to the thesis that our knowledge of the external world is impossible. Following Pritchard (2015, 15), I present the sceptical paradox as follows1: The Sceptical Paradox (1) One cannot know that one is not a brain in a vat (BIV). (2) If one knows that one is reading a book, then one is in a position to know that one is not a BIV. (3) One knows that one is reading a book. Each claim in the paradox looks prima facie plausible, but they are jointly incompatible. For (1), if one were a BIV, then one would have subjectively indistinguishable experience from one’s ordinary experience, therefore one cannot discriminate the two scenarios. The second claim is licenced by the clo- sure principle, which says that one’s knowledge can be extended via competent CONTACT Ju Wang [email protected] © 2017 Informa UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis Group INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES 211 deduction.2 The third claim is an example of everyday knowledge we think we have. Formulated this way, the sceptical paradox doesn’t involve any suspicious claim, at least at first sight; rather it hinges on nothing more than platitudes that we find intuitive. That is to say, by our own epistemic standards,3 we have no reason to reject any claim, but holding them together will land us in a predicament. Therefore, in order to get rid of this paradox, at least one claim in this paradox needs to be rejected. However, there are two approaches to solving this paradox.4 We can provide an obstacle-overriding response. To be specific, we can admit that the difficulty involved in this paradox is genuine and we must revise our intuition such that we can find a way out of the pre- dicament. Alternatively, we can provide an obstacle-dissolving response. This strategy takes the difficulty involved in the paradox to be spurious. That is to say, there are some problematic assumptions disguising as pre-theoretic intuitions. Therefore, it is unnecessary to revise our intuition in order to deal with the sceptical challenge. Instead, we only need to reveal the problematic assumptions behind the paradox and thereby scepticism will disappear. Crucially, an obsta- cle-dissolving response involves a diagnosis as to why we are lead into such a predicament. With such a diagnosis in play, we get intellectual relief. For, we can be shown that what cause the predicament are some faulty theories rather than our innocent epistemic platitudes. And if our default epistemic status is innocent, any theoretical revision is therefore unnecessary. With this strategical concern in mind, a diagnostic obstacle-dissolving approach to resolving radical scepticism, so long as it is viable, would be preferable. Transcendental arguments, as presented by Stern (1999, 2–4), have the fol- lowing features: A: That one thing X is a necessary condition for the possibility of something else Y, so that the latter cannot obtain without the former. B: The nature of the subject matter Y is to be experience, language, belief and intentionality. C: X is to have some anti-sceptical effect. With these three features in mind, we can roughly sketch how transcendental arguments work. A transcendental argument starts from a premise Y which the sceptic will accept, and then via a priori reasoning we arrive at a conclusion about some necessary conditions for (the possibility of) Y, namely X. That is to say, Y cannot obtain unless X is satisfied. Therefore, if we grant the existence of Y in the first place, we must be rationally committed to the existence of X. Note that the anti-sceptical effect of X is special, for the sceptic has no plausible way to reject it. On the one hand, she is committed to the premise Y, so she cannot challenge the premise in the first place; on the other hand, if she were to follow the argument, she would be rationally committed to the conclusion, because Y is impossible unless X obtains. Suppose the sceptic denies the conclusion, she will be accused of not the falsity of her claim, but rather the inconsistency J. WANG 212 of her position and the unintelligibility of her claim. In this sense, scepticism is labelled as self-defeating and therefore simply cannot get off the ground.5 With transcendental arguments so presented, it seems that they can play a significant role in arguing against radical scepticism. However, this is a demand- ing task, for we have witnessed various objections to transcendental arguments. In particular, Stroud (1968) famously argues against ambitious transcendental arguments.6 Ambitious transcendental arguments are arguments that aim to establish a non-psychological fact from an undisputed psychological fact via a claim of the form ‘X is a necessary condition for (the possibility of) Y’. In light of his objection, some transcendentalists tend to advance transcendental arguments modestly.7 Modest transcendental arguments are arguments that involve a necessity claim between only psychological facts. That is, instead of arguing that X is a necessary condition for (the possibility of) Y, modest transcendentalists merely argue that our commitment to X is a necessary condition for (the possibility of) Y. Hence, whether X is true is not what modest transcendentalists should bother about. However, even the modest variant faces objections to the extent that we are left wondering what the epistemological significance of adopting modest transcendental arguments is and whether modest transcendental arguments can contribute to one’s anti-sceptical proposal.8 In this paper, I will consider Cassam’s objection. To anticipate, I will argue that modest transcendental argu- ments are stepping stones for diagnostic anti-sceptical proposals. Here is my plan: in section 2, I discuss Cassam’s objection to the idea that transcendental arguments can answer how-possible questions; in section 3, I propose an alternative understanding of the role of (modest) transcendental arguments in anti-scepticism; after that I provide an example to illustrate my proposal in section 4; I have some concluding remarks in section 5. 2. Cassam’s objection Cassam (2007) develops a Multi-Level Response (hereafter MLR for short) to answer how-possible questions, and he argues that transcendental arguments are not suitable for answering how-possible questions.9 In this part, I will exam- ine his argument against transcendental arguments. What are how-possible questions? How-possible questions are usually put this way: ‘how is X possible?’ However, even though there is a similar form in posing how-possible questions, I think there are different types of how-possible questions. Imagine in a snooker match, John Higgins lost to a player who plays snooker for the first time. A snooker fan Ross would ask ‘how is that possible?’ This situation seems impossible because John Higgins is a top snooker player, and how could he lose his match against someone who is totally new to the sport? What is impossible in this situation is not the result, for it has been the case; rather it is that a satisfying explanation of this result seems impossible. INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES 213 After all, there are obstacles that a potential explanation needs to counter. For instance, how can a top player in snooker play so badly that he loses to a novice? Therefore, a response to this snooker how-possible question needs to solve this obstacle. In contrast, there is a different kind of how-possible question. Imagine some- one says that the best runner can finish a 100m sprint in less than 9 seconds. Given that current world record is 9.58 seconds and that a slight improvement in 100m sprint (0.1s) is very difficult, we would ask how it is possible. In this case, we also find obstacles: a big gap between our current world record and the target, and the difficulty in running much faster than our current highest running speed.
Recommended publications
  • Skepticism and Pluralism Ways of Living a Life Of
    SKEPTICISM AND PLURALISM WAYS OF LIVING A LIFE OF AWARENESS AS RECOMMENDED BY THE ZHUANGZI #±r A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE DIVISION OF THE UNIVERSITY OF HAWAI'I IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN PHILOSOPHY AUGUST 2004 By John Trowbridge Dissertation Committee: Roger T. Ames, Chairperson Tamara Albertini Chung-ying Cheng James E. Tiles David R. McCraw © Copyright 2004 by John Trowbridge iii Dedicated to my wife, Jill iv ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS In completing this research, I would like to express my appreciation first and foremost to my wife, Jill, and our three children, James, Holly, and Henry for their support during this process. I would also like to express my gratitude to my entire dissertation committee for their insight and understanding ofthe topics at hand. Studying under Roger Ames has been a transformative experience. In particular, his commitment to taking the Chinese tradition on its own terms and avoiding the tendency among Western interpreters to overwrite traditional Chinese thought with the preoccupations ofWestern philosophy has enabled me to broaden my conception ofphilosophy itself. Roger's seminars on Confucianism and Daoism, and especially a seminar on writing a philosophical translation ofthe Zhongyong r:pJm (Achieving Equilibrium in the Everyday), have greatly influenced my own initial attempts to translate and interpret the seminal philosophical texts ofancient China. Tamara Albertini's expertise in ancient Greek philosophy was indispensable to this project, and a seminar I audited with her, comparing early Greek and ancient Chinese philosophy, was part ofthe inspiration for my choice ofresearch topic. I particularly valued the opportunity to study Daoism and the Yijing ~*~ with Chung-ying Cheng g\Gr:p~ and benefited greatly from his theory ofonto-cosmology as a means of understanding classical Chinese philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Beyond Skepticism Foundationalism and the New Fuzziness: the Role of Wide Reflective Equilibrium in Legal Theory Robert Justin Lipkin
    Cornell Law Review Volume 75 Article 2 Issue 4 May 1990 Beyond Skepticism Foundationalism and the New Fuzziness: The Role of Wide Reflective Equilibrium in Legal Theory Robert Justin Lipkin Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/clr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Robert Justin Lipkin, Beyond Skepticism Foundationalism and the New Fuzziness: The Role of Wide Reflective Equilibrium in Legal Theory , 75 Cornell L. Rev. 810 (1990) Available at: http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/clr/vol75/iss4/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Cornell Law Review by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. BEYOND SKEPTICISM, FOUNDATIONALISM AND THE NEW FUZZINESS: THE ROLE OF WIDE REFLECTIVE EQUILIBRIUM IN LEGAL THEORY Robert Justin Liphint TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION .............................................. 812 I. FOUNDATIONALISM AND SKEPTICISM ..................... 816 A. The Problem of Skepticism ........................ 816 B. Skepticism and Nihilism ........................... 819 1. Theoretical and PracticalSkepticism ................ 820 2. Subjectivism and Relativism ....................... 821 3. Epistemic and Conceptual Skepticism ................ 821 4. Radical Skepticism ............................... 822 C. Modified Skepticism ............................... 824 II. NEW FOUNDATIONALISM
    [Show full text]
  • Analytic Transcendental Arguments
    Analytic Transcendental Arguments Jonathan Bennett From: P. Bieri et al. (eds), Transcendental Arguments and Science (Reidel: Dordrecht, 1979), pp. 45–64. 1. Locke on the objective world nothing could follow about what exists other than myself. Can we strengthen the conclusion by strengthening the Someone who thinks that his own inner states are the basis premises? Could a more contentful belief about an outer for all his other knowledge and beliefs may wonder how world be defended as explaining certain further facts about anything can be securely built on this foundation. He need my inner states, e.g. about the order or regularity which not actually doubt that his own edifice is securely founded, they exhibit? Locke does argue like that, but unfortunately though he may pretend to have doubts about this in order he pollutes all his premises—which should be purely about to consider how they could be resolved if they did occur. inner states—with an admixture of statements about the This person is a ‘Cartesian sceptic’. which implies that he outer world; for instance, he uses the premise that men is not sceptical at all. He is untouched by such crude English with no eyes have no visual states. But that seems to be moves as Locke’s protest that ‘nobody can in earnest be so an accidental defect in Locke’s treatment. He could have sceptical’, or Moore’s holding up his hand as proof that there cleansed his premises, as Hume nearly did, so that they is a physical object. Such intellectual bullying is irrelevant spoke only of the order, coherence etc.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 the Disjunctive Conception of Experience As Material for A
    The disjunctive conception of experience as material for a transcendental argument John McDowell University of Pittsburgh 1. In Individuals1 and The Bounds of Sense,2 P. F. Strawson envisaged transcendental arguments as responses to certain sorts of scepticism. An argument of the sort Strawson proposed was to establish a general claim about the world, a claim supposedly brought into doubt by sceptical reflections. Such an argument was to work by showing that unless things were as they were said to be in the claim that the argument purported to establish, it would not be possible for our thought or experience to have certain characteristics, not regarded as questionable even by someone who urges sceptical doubts. So the argument’s conclusion was to be displayed as the answer to a “How possible?” question. That has a Kantian ring, and the feature of such arguments that the formulation fits is the warrant for calling them “transcendental”. Barry Stroud responded to Strawson on the following lines.3 Perhaps we can see our way to supposing that if our thought or experience is to have certain characteristics it does have (for instance that experience purports to be of a world of objects independent of us), we must conceive the world in certain ways (for instance as containing objects that continue to exist even while we are not perceiving them). But it is quite another matter to suggest that by reflecting about how it is possible that our thought and experience are as they are, we could establish conclusions not just about how we must conceive the world but about how the world must be.
    [Show full text]
  • A Defense of Moderate Invariantism
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Philosophy Dissertations, Theses, & Student Research Philosophy, Department of July 2008 A DEFENSE OF MODERATE INVARIANTISM Leo W. Iacono University of Nebraska at Lincoln, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/philosophydiss Part of the Philosophy Commons Iacono, Leo W., "A DEFENSE OF MODERATE INVARIANTISM" (2008). Philosophy Dissertations, Theses, & Student Research. 1. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/philosophydiss/1 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy, Department of at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Dissertations, Theses, & Student Research by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. A DEFENSE OF MODERATE INVARIANTISM by Leo Iacono A DISSERTATION Presented to the Faculty of The Graduate College at the University of Nebraska In Partial Fulfillment of Requirements For the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Major: Philosophy Under the Supervision of Professor Albert Casullo Lincoln, Nebraska August, 2008 A DEFENSE OF MODERATE INVARIANTISM Leo Iacono, Ph.D. University of Nebraska, 2008 Adviser: Albert Casullo This dissertation is a defense of moderate invariantism, the traditional epistemological position combining the following three theses: invariantism, according to which the word ‘know’ expresses the same content in every context of use; intellectualism, according to which whether one knows a certain proposition does not depend on one’s practical interests; and anti- skepticism, according to which we really do know much of what we ordinarily take ourselves to know. Moderate invariantism needs defending because of seemingly powerful arguments for contextualism, the view that, like ‘I’ and ‘now’, ‘know’ expresses different contents in different contexts.
    [Show full text]
  • Moonshadows: Conventional Truth in Buddhist Philosophy
    Moonshadows This page intentionally left blank Moonshadows Conventional Truth in Buddhist Philosophy T HE C OWHERDS 2011 Oxford University Press, Inc., publishes works that further Oxford University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education. Oxford New York Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi New Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto With offi ces in Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam Copyright © 2011 by Oxford University Press, Inc. Published by Oxford University Press, Inc. 198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016 www.oup.com Oxford is a registered trademark of Oxford University Press All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior permission of Oxford University Press. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Cowherds (Authors) Moonshadows : conventional truth in Buddhist philosophy / the Cowherds. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-0-19-975142-6; ISBN 978-0-19-975143-3 (pbk.) 1. Truth—Religious aspects—Buddhism. 2. Buddhist philosophy. I. Title. BQ4255.C69 2011 121.088′2943—dc22 2009050158 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper Preface This is an unusual volume. It is neither an anthology nor a monograph. We prefer to think of it as a polygraph— a collectively written volume refl ecting the varying views of a large collection of authors.
    [Show full text]
  • Contextualist Responses to Skepticism
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy 6-27-2007 Contextualist Responses to Skepticism Luanne Gutherie Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Gutherie, Luanne, "Contextualist Responses to Skepticism." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2007. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/22 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. CONTEXTUALIST RESPONSES TO SKEPTICISM by LUANNE GUTHERIE Under the Direction of Stephen Jacobson ABSTRACT External world skeptics argue that we have no knowledge of the external world. Contextualist theories of knowledge attempt to address the skeptical problem by maintaining that arguments for skepticism are effective only in certain contexts in which the standards for knowledge are so high that we cannot reach them. In ordinary contexts, however, the standards for knowledge fall back down to reachable levels and we again are able to have knowledge of the external world. In order to address the objection that contextualists confuse the standards for knowledge with the standards for warranted assertion, Keith DeRose appeals to the knowledge account of warranted assertion to argue that if one is warranted in asserting p, one also knows p. A skeptic, however, can maintain a context-invariant view of the knowledge account of assertion, in which case such an account would not provide my help to contextualism.
    [Show full text]
  • New Directions for Transcendental Claims. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 93 (2)
    Giladi, Paul (2016) New Directions for Transcendental Claims. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 93 (2). pp. 212-231. ISSN 0165-9227 Downloaded from: https://e-space.mmu.ac.uk/621126/ Version: Accepted Version Publisher: Brill DOI: https://doi.org/10.1163/18756735-09302006 Please cite the published version https://e-space.mmu.ac.uk 1 New Directions for Transcendental Claims Keywords: transcendental claims; transcendental arguments; epistemology; post-Kantian philosophy This paper aims to provide an account of the relationship between transcendental claims and the project of using transcendental argumentation that differs from the mainstream literature.1 By a ‘transcendental claim’, I mean a proposition which states that y is a necessary condition for the possibility of x.2 In much of the literature, such claims are said to have as their primary value the overcoming of various sceptical positions. I argue that whilst transcendental arguments may be narrowly characterised as anti-sceptical, transcendental claims do not have to be used in only this way, and in fact can be useful in several areas of philosophy outside the issue of scepticism, and so can be used by transcendental arguments more broadly conceived. I offer four examples of transcendental claims that are not used in narrow, anti-sceptical transcendental arguments. I argue that these broader arguments use transcendental claims but not in an anti-sceptical way. From this, I conclude that one can separate the project of making transcendental claims and the project of using transcendental arguments to defeat scepticism. Given the well-known difficulties transcendental arguments in this narrow sense seem to have had in defeating scepticism,3 distinguishing narrow transcendental arguments clearly from transcendental claims as such in this manner can provide a way for the latter to still serve an important role in philosophy, by showing how such claims can be used more broadly, regardless of any doubts one may have about the anti- sceptical value of such claims.
    [Show full text]
  • A Weakly Pragmatic Defense of Authoritatively Normative Reasons
    NIHILISM AND ARGUMENTATION: A WEAKLY PRAGMATIC DEFENSE OF AUTHORITATIVELY NORMATIVE REASONS Scott Simmons A Dissertation Submitted to the Graduate College of Bowling Green State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY August 2020 Committee: Michael Weber, Advisor Verner Bingman Graduate Faculty Representative Christian Coons Molly Gardner Sara Worley ii ABSTRACT Michael Weber, Advisor Global normative error theorists argue that there are no authoritative normative reasons of any kind. Thus, according to the error theory, the normative demands of law, prudence, morality, etc. are of no greater normative significance than the most absurd standards we can conceive of. Because the error theory is a radically revisionary view, theorists who accept it only do so because they maintain the view is supported by the best available arguments. In this dissertation, I argue that error theory entails that it is impossible that there are successful arguments for anything, thus defenses of error theory are in tension with the view, itself. My argument begins with the observation that it is natural to think a successful argument is one that gives us an authoritative normative reason to believe its conclusion. Error theory entails that there are no authoritative reasons to believe anything. What are arguments for error theory even supposed to accomplish? Error theorists may respond that their arguments are solely intended to get at the truth. I argue that this reply fails. One problem is that it cannot make sense of why in practice even error theorists still want evidence for the premises of sound arguments. Error theorists may try to capture the importance of evidence by appeal to our social norms or goals.
    [Show full text]
  • Redalyc.DESCARTES's MODAL RELIABILISM
    Praxis Filosófica ISSN: 0120-4688 [email protected] Universidad del Valle Colombia Gómez Alonso, Modesto M. DESCARTES'S MODAL RELIABILISM Praxis Filosófica, núm. 32, enero-junio, 2011, pp. 11-26 Universidad del Valle Cali, Colombia Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=209022654001 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America, the Caribbean, Spain and Portugal Journal's homepage in redalyc.org Non-profit academic project, developed under the open access initiative DESCARTES’S MODAL RELIABILISM* El confiabilismo modal de Descartes Modesto M. Gómez Alonso Universidad Pontificia de Salamanca ABSTRACT This paper’s objective is to undermine the standard reading on Descartes’s Meditations, a reading which, abstracting from the skeptical challenge of a reduction of reason to absurdity which Descartes is responding to, overstresses the epistemological priority of the Cogito argument, and which, ignoring the anti-skeptical strategy deployed by Descartes, is blind to the fact that, instead of trying to garner better support for nuclear propositions, he attempts to subtract grounds for doubt, working himself into an enlightened position from which those radical scenarios no longer make sense. Descartes’s proposal is a modal or metaphysical version of reliabilism analogous to the contemporary one defended by Ernest Sosa, a position capable of overcoming skepticism without a vicious circle and which demonstrates that a correct use of reason yields a theory on how things are in the world which precludes the unreliability of our cognitive faculties. Key Words: Descartes, Ernest Sosa, Global Scenarios, Reliabilism, Skepticism.
    [Show full text]
  • Knowledge and Skepticism
    PHL 110 6. Knowledge and Skepticism What do I know? Knowledge and Skepticism Whatt ccan wee rreealllly know? Knowledge is justied, true, belief. George Matthews, Pennsylvania College of Technology 2020 1 / 26 2 / 26 What do I know? What do I know? Knowledge is Knowledge is justied, justied, true, true, belief. belief. How can we know anything at all? This ancient philosophical To count as knowledge our beliefs also have to be true. question has troubled many people. While it may be hard to figure out just what the facts are, First, note that knowledge is a state of mind, a type of belief. simply believing something strongly is not enough to make it But there's more to knowledge than just belief. true or make it count as knowledge. 3 / 26 4 / 26 What do I know? Epistemological questions In spite of how obvious it may be that we know many things, below the surface lurk some difficult questions. Knowledge is justied, What is the source of genuine knowledge of reality? true, belief. Can we attain knowledge from our built-in ability to reason like the rationalists claim we can? Finally we need justification for anything to really count as knowledge since knowledge is more than just lucky guessing. Or is all knowledge derived from sense experience like the empiricists claim? How we can justify our claims is one of the major concerns of epistemology or the philosophical theory of knowledge. Or is knowledge a result of interactions between our ability to reason and what we get from experience as constructivists claim? 5 / 26 6 / 26 1 CC George Matthews, 2020 PHL 110 6.
    [Show full text]
  • Perception and Reflection
    PERCEPTION AND REFLECTION Anil Gomes Trinity College, University of Oxford Forthcoming, Philosophical Perspectives [accepted 2017] What method should we use to determine the nature of perceptual experience? My focus here is the Kantian thought that transcendental arguments can be used to determine the nature of perceptual experience. I set out a dilemma for the use of transcendental arguments in the philosophy of perception, one which turns on a comparison of the transcendental method with the first-personal method of early analytic philosophy, and with the empirical methods of much contemporary philosophy of mind. The transcendental method can avoid this dilemma only if it commits to our possessing a capacity for imaginative reflection, one which is capable of identifying certain formal properties of experience. This result indicates some of the commitments which must be made if transcendental arguments are to be used in the philosophy of perception, and it has implications for those views that take the philosophy of perception to be autonomous of the empirical science of perception. 1. Introduction Questions about perception arise across the academy: philosophers, psychologists, neuroscientists, and others are interested in the nature of perceptual experience and its role in our cognitive life. And it is a salient fact to anyone who is interested in these questions that there is disagreement both across and within these disciplines as to the nature of perceptual experience. In some cases, this is the kind of disagreement which one would expect in any healthy body of research. But in some cases it seems to betray a deeper disagreement about the methods appropriate for studying the nature of perceptual experience.
    [Show full text]