<<

arXiv:1905.09860v1 [gr-qc] 23 May 2019 beto oteeitneo ieoeao nQatmMechanics Quantum in operator by Theory a supported of Quantum furthermore existence of is the “time” view to This the objection and [1]. pa GR notions” greater incompatible of “The th tually “time” and is [4]; the time” theory because of fundamental concept occurs more coherent a A gain spac to dynamical. needed the is of equations part t as Einstein’s Schr¨odinger of time e in ing mechanics), problem parameter Newtonian the (the from faces absolute inherited one been is prese hand, theory quantum the other in reflects the time that “On dynamic that: of a t stated curvature acquires thus in the time time tim to (GR) that absolute due Relativity considering and acter General space from in absolute part whereas the in as Newton), arises reference eleme of 10] (an frame parameter 9, ternal a 8, is 7, Relativity (TDSE) Schr¨odinger 6, General Equation Dependent of 5, quantization 4, the 3, in 2, (PoT) time” of “problem The Introduction 1 ieetprpcieo h rbe ftm in time of problem the on perspective different A nvria ainlAtooad ´xc,CM,MEXICO M´exico, CDMX, Aut´onoma de Nacional Universidad sn noptblt,a eeal sue nteextensiv the Gravity. Quantum in in assumed time” generally of reference as ”problem Newtonian incompatibility, external no an is to spaceti curved than fla dynamical rather Minkowski actual Relativity, a the in to coordinate approximation time local the to corresponds chanics .Isiuod ´sc;2 nttt eCeca Nucleares Ciencias de Instituto F´ısica; 2. de Instituto 1. h esetv savne httetm aaee nquant in parameter time the that advanced is perspective The .Bauer M. unu gravity quantum *bauer@fisica.unam.mx 1 ∗ ..Aguill´on C.A. , a 7 2019 27, May Abstract 1 2 n .Garc´ıa G. and eo General of me rm.There frame. l discussed ely c fms.I is It mass. of nce spacetime t nrdcdby introduced e 2 m.Whereas ime. to h PoT the of rt mme- um -ieobey- e-time uto has quation ex- an of nt Q)[11]. (QM) eTime he r mu- are (GR)[1, lchar- al Pauli’s erefore 2 A different perspective

Based on recent theoretical and experimental developments, this outlook of the problem of time is modified if one takes into account the following: a) The relativistic quantum equation as formulated by Dirac satisfies Lorentz invariance. This is achieved by integrating the time parameter of the time depen- dent Schr¨odinger equation (TDSE) with the three space coordinates into a four dimensional spacetime Minkowski frame of reference[12, 13]. As such, neither the time nor the space coordinates are represented by operators, as postulated in (QM) to be associated to the properties of the system under study; nor time can be considered to be canonically conjugate to the Hamiltonian [14]. b) Closed systems (foremost the Universe, although finite macroscopic and atomic systems have been so considered for all practical purposes in the for- mulations (non relativistic first and then relativistic) of classical and quantum mechanics. Being closed, they are static, i.e., they do not evolve. Therefor in QM the basic equation is the time independent Schr¨odinger equation (TISE). c) Time in the TDSE is the laboratory time transferred by the entangle- ment of the microscopic system with its macroscopic environment where clocks are found; thus the TDSE is a classical quantum equation where t is part of a dynamical reference frame in the curved spacetime [15, 16, 17]. A similar situ- ation is expected to follow in the case of the time independent Wheeler-deWitt equation (WdW) in the canonical quantization of GR [15]. d) QM and GR are at present assumed to be universally valid in the cos- mological development of the Universe, from the Big Bang to the progressive expansion and cooling, the appearence of fundamental particles, the aggregation into atoms and, as a consequence of decoherence, into the massive components of the present world and the remnant cosmic background radiation (CMBR), and possibly also dark matter and dark energy, all inmersed in a GR curved spacetime [8]. Although this is still an open problem, “Local agreement with SR () is also required. A natural hypothesis here is Einstein’s that SR inertial frames are global idealizations of GR’s local inertial frames that are attached to freely falling particles. Furthemore, in parallel with the developmeent of SR, Einstein retained a notion of metric gµν on spacetime to account for observers in spacetime having the ability to measure lengths and if equipped with standard rods and clocks, encode the distinction between time and space, as gµν reduces locally to GR’s ηµν everywhere the other laws of Physics take their SR form”[1]. And also: “Any acceptable theory must allow us to recover the classical spacetime in the appropiate limit. Moreover, the spacetime geometrical notions should be intrisically tied to the behavior of matter that probes them” [18]. e) A composite closed system ( micoscopic system plus macroscopic environ- ment -the laboratory-) is found in a curved spacetime representing the pervasive gravitational interaction. However, the minimal (less than 0.02%) correction to the hydrogen spectrum that arises from a extended to curved spacetime suggests that the laboratory is subject to a very weak curvature [19],

2 so the Minkowski flat spacetime of SR is a good local approximation to the GR curved spacetime. Furthermore, Dirac’s formulation of Relativistic Quantum Mechanics (RQM) allows the introduction of a self-adjoint ”time” operator for the microscopic sys- 2 tem T = α.r/c + βτ 0, in analogy to the Hamiltonian H = cα.p + βm0c , where α = (αx, αy,αz) and β are the Dirac matrices. It represents in principle an addi- tional observable. This operator generates a unitary transformation that shifts momentum - whose spectrum is continuous and unbounded -, and ensuingly the energy in both positive and negative energy branches, thus circumventing Pauli’s objection. It also provides a time energy uncertainty relation directly related to the space momentum uncertainty, as envisionned originally by Bohr in the uncertainty of the time of passage of a wave packet at a certain point; and a formal basis for de Broglie’s daring assumption of associating a wave of frequency υ = mc2/h to a particle of mass m [20, 21, 22, 23].

3 Conclusion

In view of the above one can conclude that in relativistic classical and quantum mechanics, time is part of a Minkowski reference frame that locally approxi- mates well the actual GR dynamic curved spacetime where the laboratory is locates. It is not Newtonian. Its origin is dynamical1. There is therefore no in- compatibility. To quote Einstein: “Newton, forgive me; you found the only way which, in your age, was just about possible for a man of highest thought and cre- ative power. The concepts, which you created, are even today still guiding our thinking in physics, although we now know that they will have to be replaced by others farther removed from the sphere of immediate experience, if we aim at a profounder understanding of relationships” [24]. This apology and recogni- tion should be extended to the creators of the Hamilton Jacobi formulation of and to the creators of quantum mechanics. To be pointed out is that not every link of the present perspective has been fully developed at present. The quantization of GR is still an open question in many aspects [1, 18, 25]. However, this point of view removes the question of whether time is to be identified before or after quantization, in favour of a timeless interpretation of quantum gravity [10], where time would emerge as the observable that conditions all the others, as proposed by Page and Wootters [26]. The proposed self-adjoint time operator that complements the Dirac formulation of RQM may play the role of that observable [27], in response to the objection of Unruh and Wald [28]. And perhaps it may also help in removing the ambiguity with respect to time in the foliation of spacetime in the canonical approach to Quantum Gravity. . 1Another source of confusion arises because “dynamical” is attached to two different as- pects. One is the variation associated with the impact of matter on the spacetime reference frame. The other is the dependence on the parameter t of the of the system, that in QM is made explicit in the .

3 References

[1] E. Anderson, “Problem of Time and Background Independence”, arXiv:1409.4117v1 (2014) and references therein. [2] E. Anderson, “The problem of time in quantum gravity”, arXiv:1009.2157v3; Ann.Phys. (Berlin) 524, 757-786 (2012) [3] K,V, Kushar, “Time and interpretations of quantum gravity”, Int.J.Mod.Phys. D 20 (2011) [4] C. Kiefer, “Concept of Time in Canonical Quantum Theory and String Theory”, J.Phys. Confererence Series 174, 012021 (2009) [5] A. Ashtekar, “Gravity and the quantum”, New J.Phys. 7, 198 (2005); “The winding road to quantum gravity”, Curr.Sci. 89, No.12 (2005) [6] J. Butterfield and C.J. Isham, “On the Emergence of Time in Quantum Gravity”, in The Arguments of Time, ed. J. Butterfield, Oxfourd University Press (1999) [7] C. Kiefer, “Does Time Exists at the Most Fundamental Level?”, in Time, Temporality, Now, eds.H. Atmanspacher et al., Springer-Verlag Berlin Hei- delberg (1997) [8] C. Kiefer, “Emergence of a classical Universe from quantum gravity and cosmology”, Phil.Trans.R.Soc. 370, 4566-4575 (2012) [9] C.J. Isham, “Prima Facie Questions in Quantum Gravity”, arXiv:9310031v1 (1993) [10] C.J. Isham, “Canonical Quantum Gravity and the Problem of Time”, arXiv:gr-qc/9210011v1 (1992) [11] W. Pauli, “General Principles of Quantum Mechanics”, Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg New York, p.41 (1980) [12] B. Thaller, “The Dirac Equation”, Springer-Velag, Berlin Heidelberg New York (1992) [13] W. Greiner, “ Relativistic Quantum Mechanics - Wave equations”, (3d ed.) Springer, Berlin Heidelberg New York (2000) [14] J. Hilgevoord, “Time in quantum mechanics: a story of confusion”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 36, 29-60 (2005) [15] J.S. Briggs and J.M. Rost, “Time dependence in quantum mechanics”, Eur.Phys.J. 10, 311 (2000); ”On the Derivation of the Time-dependent Schr¨odinger Equation”, Found.Phys. 31, 694 (2001) [16] J.S. Briggs, “Equivalent emergence of time dependence in classical and quantum mechanics”, Phys.Rev. A 052119 (2015)

4 [17] E. Moreva et al., “Time from ”, Phys.Rev. A 89, 052122 (2014); “The time as an emergent property of quantum mechanics, a synthetic description of a first experimental approach”, J.Phys.: Conference Series 626, 012019 (2015) [18] Y. Bonder, C. Chryssomalakos and D. Sudarsky, “Extracting Geome- try from Quantum Spacetime: Obstacles Down the Road”, Found.Phys. 48:1038–1060 (2018) [19] C.C. Barros Jr., “Quantum mechanics in curved space-time”, Eur.Phys.J. C 42, 119–126 (2005) [20] M. Bauer, “A dynamical time operator in Dirac’s relativistic quantum me- chanics”, Int.J.Mod.Phys. 29, 14500365 (2014) [21] M. Bauer, “On the problem of time in quantum mechanics”, Eur.J.Phys. 38, 035402 (2017) [22] M. Bauer, “de Broglie Clock, Electron Channeling and Time in Quantum Mechanics”, Can.J.Phys. 97, 37-41 (2018) [23] S.Y. Lan et al., “A clock directly linking time to a particle mass”, Science 339 554–7 (2013) [24] A. Einstein, “ Autobiographical notes”, p.31, in Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist, Ed. Paul Arthur Schilpp, Cambridge University Press (1949) [25] Smolin, L., “How far are we from the quantum theory of relativity”, arXiv:0303185v2 (2003) [26] D.N. Page and W.K. Wootters, “Evolution without evolution: Dynamics described by stationary observables”, Phys Rev D 27 ,2885-2892 (1983) [27] M. Bauer, “Quantum gravity and a time operator in relativistic quantum mechanics”, arXiv:1605.01659 (2016) [28] W.G. Unruh and R.M. Wald, “Time and the interpretation of canonical quantum gravity”, Phys.Rev. D 40, 2598 (1989)

5