The Obstinate Real: Barad, Escobar, and Object-Oriented Ontology

The Obstinate Real: Barad, Escobar, and Object-Oriented Ontology

Open Philosophy 2019; 2: 86–97 Object-Oriented Ontology and Its Critics Michael Feichtinger* The Obstinate Real: Barad, Escobar, and Object-Oriented Ontology https://doi.org/10.1515/opphil-2019-0009 Received January 28, 2019; accepted April 18, 2019 Abstract: Relational ontologies that postulate the primacy of relations over their relata may seem like a contrary and incompatible approach to object-oriented ontology (OOO). Therefore, this paper aims to clarify the relationship between Barad’s and Escobar’s relational ontologies and Harman’s OOO by comparing and contrasting the relative coherences between them. After outlining the central assumptions of the different accounts, I discuss the problems of relational ontologies with regard to several ethical, political, and posthumanist issues. I argue that OOO is able to avoid their pitfalls without rejecting the major benefits of relational ontologies. After a critique of the pluralization of worlds within relational ontologies, I argue for the rejection of the concept of world(s) in favor of understanding space and time as emerging from polar tensions within the quadruple objects. Consequently, this highlights the potential of OOO to encounter the Anthropocene beyond scientific realism and to account for the plurality of reality without granting any hegemonic access to it. This paper, therefore, argues for a conceptualization of ontological difference without one or many worlds. Keywords: speculative realism; new materialism; Barad; One-World World; Harman; Escobar; critical posthumanism; Meillassoux; postcolonial studies; Anthropocene 1 Reconsidering ontology In the last few years, there has been an increasing tendency within the humanities and cultural sciences to proceed beyond thinking and shed light onto the realm of being, which was dark and beyond our grasp since Kant. The ontological turn in the field of social and cultural anthropology, for example, aims to overcome a dualistic representationalism and logocentrism.1 This ontological turn includes “the attention to a host of factors that deeply shape what we come to know as reality but that social theory has rarely tackled— factors like objects and things, non-humans, matter and materiality […], emotions, spirituality, feelings, and so forth.”2 In particular, relational ontologies have been preferred for conceptualizing the plurality of the world without postmodern constructivism through epistemic systems, and for conceptualizing reality without the hegemonic demand of scientific realism. In this respect, one can describe the theoretical developments of Karen Barad’s and Arturo Escobar’s relational ontologies as departing from the critique of epistemology and, instead, starting with the critique and overcoming of a specific sort of non-relational ontology. A radical implication of these relational ontologies consists in the multiplication of worlds,3 thereby suspending a classical global perspective. 1 Cf. Hollbrand et al., The Ontological Turn, 284. 2 Escobar, Designs for the Pluriverse, 63. 3 Cf. Escobar, “Thinking-feeling with the Earth,” 15. *Corresponding author: Michael Feichtinger, University of Vienna, Vienna, Austria; E-mail: [email protected] Open Access. © 2019 Michael Feichtinger, published by De Gruyter. This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Public License. The Obstinate Real: Barad, Escobar, and Object-Oriented Ontology 87 At the same time as the ontological turn within social and cultural anthropology, there is another realist movement happening within continental philosophy. The founding of heterogeneous positions that might be subsumed under the label of “speculative realism” dates back to 2007. Graham Harman’s object-oriented ontology (OOO), with its new conceptualization of objects, is still the most discussed strand of speculative realism. Despite many differences, there is one common feature in all these philosophies: namely, the encounter with correlationism. This is a term coined by Quentin Meillassoux that describes the basic assumption of post-Kantian continental philosophy “according to which we only ever have access to the correlation between thinking and being.”4 The consequences of correlationism are that thinking and being cannot be considered independent or identical. Furthermore, it is impossible to overcome an anthropocentric perspective within the correlationist framework. As I will show, the relational ontologies of Barad and Escobar aim, at least implicitly, also to break with correlationism. The prevailing narrative in the Anthropocene discourse is still one that Christophe Bonneuil called the “naturalist narrative,”5 which is strongly connected with the idea that “humanity” will fix the world with scientific progress. Within Bonneuil’s classification, relational ontologies and OOO can be described as being part of the “post-nature grand narrative”6 that “proclaims the inescapable immersion of human destiny in the great natural cycles of the Earth.”7 Nevertheless, relational ontologies are much more dominant within this narrative. By contrast, I will argue for the benefits of an OOO in the encounters of the Anthropocene. After outlining the central assumptions of Escobar and Barad’s relational ontologies and Harman’s OOO, I will discuss the problems of relational ontologies with regard to several ethical, political, and posthumanist issues that are entangled with these problems. The importance of discussing these relational ontologies within such a framework becomes clear if one acknowledges the emphasis of Barad and Escobar on the inseparability of thinking, acting, and being. Barad, therefore, uses the concept of “ethico-onto- epistem-ology”8 to stress that these fields of study cannot be separated. Yet I will argue that OOO is able to avoid the pitfalls of relational ontologies without rejecting their major benefits. A critique of the world or pluriverse within relational ontologies will show that this concept forecloses a perspective that is necessary to encounter the upcoming challenges of the Anthropocene. Therefore, I will further discuss Harman’s notions of space and time as emergent properties of objects that allow us to discuss problems classically denoted as “global.” with global warming being an obvious example, without reintroducing a “One-World World.”9 In summary, this paper compares and contrasts the relative coherences of Escobar, Barad, and OOO, and highlights the potential of a OOO account to encounter the Anthropocene beyond scientific realism or scientism, and argues for a conceptualization of ontological difference with neither one nor many worlds. 2 The real in Barad, Escobar, and Harman The concept of the real or realism is frequently neglected due to its connotation with hegemonic claims. This may result from the common association of realism with scientific realism or scientism. Hilary Putnam’s infamous characterization of such realism consists of three basic claims: 1. The world consists of a fixed totality of mind-independent objects. 2. There is exactly one true and complete description of how the world looks. 3. Truth means the corresponding relation between words or thought-signs and external things.10 4 Meillassoux, After Finitude, 5. 5 Bonneuil, “The geological turn,” 18. 6 Ibid., 23. 7 Ibid., 24. 8 Barad, Meeting the Universe Halfway, 90. 9 Law, “What’s Wrong with a One-World World,” 2. 10 Cf. Putnam, Reason, Truth and History, 49. 88 M. Feichtinger Furthermore, the resulting problem consists of the assumption of scientific realism or scientism that only empirical sciences yield true and complete descriptions of the world. The set of real entities is thereby tremendously reduced to a small number of entities that are not directly relevant to our daily practice. Also, the only legitimate knowing subject is considered to be the one embedded in Western scientific practice. In addition, this definition of realism is deeply embedded in a post-Kantian framework that stresses an implicit distinction between noumena and phenomena. Therefore, a realist account in the vein of a process that Enrique Dussel calls “philosophical decolonization”11 demands a counter-hegemonic concept of the real that on the one hand conceptualizes the real in a way that allows no exclusive hegemonic access, and on the other is able to explain the plurality of the real. Relational ontologies and OOO choose two divergent post-Kantian solutions to attain such a real. In line with the tradition of the usual anti-realist solutions, Escobar and Barad reject the noumena behind the phenomena. As compared to accounts that refute realism with this claim, Barad and Escobar posit the phenomena as the real. Both thinkers argue for a similar account in different ways, which I will outline in the following paragraphs. Barad’s agential realism, as proposed in Meeting the Universe Halfway, is a “move toward performative alternatives to representationalism [that] shifts the focus from questions of correspondence between descriptions and reality […] to matters of practice, doings, and actions.”12 Therefore, Barad acknowledges the material-discursive practices that are enacted at the heart of Western epistemology: namely, scientific research. According to her agential realism, “knowing, thinking, measuring, theorizing, and observing are material practices of intra-acting within and as part of the world.”13 Intra-action has to be clearly distinguished from interaction, as the latter always presupposes relata that interact. Intra-action, in comparison, presupposes

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    12 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us